Virtue Ethics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Virtue Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Sessions 19 & 20 April 20th & 22nd, 2020 Normative Ethics: Virtue Ethics Today we start investigating normative ethics, which involves Ø formulating practical rules/principles for how we should behave in order to be a good person. – (normative = concerning how things ideally should/ought to be, in contrast with descriptive = concerning how things actually are) » We have already come across some theories in class that present views about how we should behave: • contractarianism: doing the right thing means fulfilling your obligations to other people by keeping the promises/agreements you’ve made with them, • including obeying the laws in your community • care ethics: doing the right thing generally results from viewing others as deserving of care & concern Ø In this unit we’ll focus on three additional leading theories about how we ought to behave: virtue ethics, consequentialism (esp. utilitarianism), & deontology. 2 What do we mean by a “good person”? Ø A normative ethical theory is about what we should do / being a “good person” in the sense of doing the right thing for others to affect their lives in a positive way, and making the world a better place for everyone to live in. – In contrast, a normative prudential theory describes what we should do / being a “good person” in the sense of doing what it takes to satisfy one’s desires & achieve personal goals. Sometimes being a good person ethically aligns with or contributes to being a good person prudentially: – i.e., doing something to help other people could also make you happier, or help you work towards one of your goals. …but other times, being a good person ethically can be in tension/conflict with what seems to be prudent for you (beneficial for achieving your personal goals). – Doing the right thing might be inconvenient or unpleasant sometimes, » or it might require you to give up some things you’d like to do or to have. 3 One of the major debates in normative ethics is generalism vs. particularism: Ø Generalist normative ethical theories propose that there are general rules, principles, or formulas that define what it means to be an ethically good person / do the right thing. That is, in all situations, one can do the right thing by acting in accordance with a moral rule, principle, or formula. » Utilitarianism & deontology are each generalist theories. Ø Particularist normative ethical theories contend that being a good person / doing the right thing can’t be boiled down to rules, principles, or formulas. Particularists typically argue that doing the right thing is about using one’s own judgment to determine the right action for each specific situation. » Virtue ethics, the topic of this week’s sessions, is a particularist theory. 4 The first normative ethical theory we will consider: Ø virtue ethics = doing the right thing results from developing good moral character, which involves cultivating moral virtues Aristotle (384-322 BCE), a particularist, believed that being a good person is much more complicated than just following rules: » it’s a matter of developing skills which enable us to make the right choice for each situation we confront, • since “the right thing to do” depends upon the situation. » He suggests that the best way to become a good person, we should follow the example set by moral exemplars – people who do the right thing & can serve as role models. He characterizes moral exemplars as people who have cultivated Ø virtues = states of excellence in one’s character, developed through repeated practice, which allow a person to make good choices & do the right thing at the right time – So, we call his theory “virtue ethics” to highlight its emphasis on developing good character & becoming a virtuous person, which will in turn lead to good behavior. 5 The Good Place, Season 1 Episode 3 6 Aristotle indicates right off the bat that he holds a particularist view of normative ethics: • He states that we should only expect to be able to develop rough guidelines – not rigid laws – about how we ought to behave. “…noble & just [i.e., right] actions . exhibit much variety & fluctuation…" – The right thing to do in situation A might be completely different from the right thing to do in situation B, • and that makes it hard to pin down anything all these right actions have in common that makes them "right”. – So, “doing the right thing” could not be expressed in terms of strict rules that apply in all situations. » We must be content, then, in speaking of [ethics] . to indicate the truth roughly & in outline, . speaking about things which are only for the most part true . it is the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits.” (Nicomachean Ethics I.3) 7 Think about a person who you look up to, who always seems to know how to do the right thing in every situation. • According to Aristotle, this person you’re thinking about – someone you regard as a moral exemplar – is likely someone you would define as having good character. – He believes that “good character” is synonymous with being virtuous or having virtues: virtues = states of excellence in one’s character, developed through repeated practice, which allow a person to make good choices & do the right thing at the right time He suggests that you can think of each virtue as a type of learned skill: an ability you gain that allows you to do well when put to the test, – like being a good team player when you have to work with others – or having good time management when you’re on a deadline. » moral virtues: character traits that lead us to do the right thing ethically; skills that lead to good ethical choices (e.g., being fair, considerate, generous, etc.) 8 – According to Aristotle, “good character” is synonymous with being virtuous or having virtues: virtues = states of excellence in one’s character, developed through repeated practice, which allow a person to make good choices & do the right thing at the right time » moral virtues: character traits that lead us to do the right thing ethically; skills that lead to good ethical choices (e.g., being fair, considerate, generous, etc.) Aristotle asserts that nobody is born morally virtuous: Ø instead, we become morally virtuous through our actions. As with any other skill, practice makes perfect: • you have to do the right thing over & over until it becomes “second nature”. So, just as “men become builders by building & lyre-players by playing the lyre; • so too we become just by doing just acts, temperate by doing temperate acts, brave by doing brave acts.” (NE II.1) 9 Aristotle suggests that every interaction with other people is a chance to develop our virtue, and Ø the choices we make determine our character: – “…by doing the acts that we do in our transactions with other [humans] we become just or unjust, – and by doing the acts that we do in the presence of danger, and by being habituated to feel fear or confidence, we become brave or cowardly. – The same is true of appetites and feelings of anger; • some men become temperate & good-tempered, others self-indulgent & irascible, by behaving in one way or the other in the appropriate circumstances.” (II.1) Having good intentions is important, – but Aristotle believes that actions, (rather than your intentions) are the true mark of your character. 10 » moral virtues: character traits that lead us to do the right thing ethically; skills that lead to good ethical choices (e.g., being fair, considerate, generous, etc.) ØEach moral virtue represents the midpoint (“golden mean”) between two extremes: an excess (too much) & a deficiency (too little). He draws this conclusion by noting that most things that are good for us are best in moderation: • E.g., “drink or food which is above or below a certain amount destroys the health, while that which is proportionate [to our needs] produces & increases & preserves it.” • Too much or too little food/drink/sleep/studying/partying is bad: but an intermediate amount is good for you. Aristotle reasons: “So too is it, then, in the case of temperance & courage & the other virtues… • temperance & courage, then, are destroyed by excess and [deficiency], and preserved by the mean [i.e., moderation].” 11 Each moral virtue represents the midpoint (“golden mean”) between two extremes: an excess (too much) & a deficiency (too little). Ø E.g., courage is the midpoint between fearing everything & fearing nothing: – “…the man who flies from and fears everything & does not stand his ground against anything becomes a coward, – & the man who fears nothing at all but goes to meet every danger becomes rash, » …[but] by being habituated to despise things that are fearful & to stand our ground against them we become brave” Ø Temperance is the midpoint between enjoying too much pleasure & not enjoying enough pleasure. – “…the man who indulges in every pleasure & abstains from none becomes self-indulgent, – while the man who shuns every pleasure…becomes in a way insensible [unable to enjoy anything]... » …[but] by abstaining from [most, but not all] pleasures we become temperate” (NE II.2) 12 Each moral virtue represents the midpoint (“golden mean”) between two extremes: an excess (too much) & a deficiency (too little). • Everything in the middle column (”BALANCE”) is a moral virtue (a good character trait, generally resulting in right actions), • …while the Excesses & Deficiencies (side columns) are the corresponding vices (bad character traits, generally resulting in wrong actions). ØDo you agree with this list? 13 However, Aristotle adds that to be truly virtuous, it isn’t quite enough to behave in accordance with each virtue: Ø you also have to enjoy it (& not enjoy doing wrong).
Recommended publications
  • Psychology and the Aims of Normative Ethics”
    Regina A. Rini (forthcoming). “Psychology and the Aims of Normative Ethics”. To appear in Springer Handbook of Neuroethics (ed. J. Clausen and N. Levy). Psychology and the Aims of Normative Ethics Regina A. Rini University of Oxford [email protected] Abstract: This chapter discusses the philosophical relevance of empirical research on moral cognition. It distinguishes three central aims of normative ethical theory: understanding the nature of moral agency, identifying morally right actions, and determining the justification of moral beliefs. For each of these aims, the chapter considers and rejects arguments against employing cognitive scientific research in normative inquiry. It concludes by suggesting that, whichever of the central aims one begins from, normative ethics is improved by engaging with the science of moral cognition. Key words: is/ought gap, moral agency, moral intuition, moral philosophy, ought-implies- can I. Three Central Questions of Normative Ethics It is undeniable that the field of empirical moral psychology has grown dramatically in the last decade, with new experimental techniques allowing us unprecedented understanding of the causal and computational structures of the human moral faculty. Or, at least, it is undeniable that this research contributes to a descriptive project, one of better understanding the facts about who we are and how we think.1 But what might be denied is that these investigations have much to offer to normative ethics, a distinctively prescriptive sort of inquiry.2 The purpose of this chapter is to show why normative ethics - the study of 1 Although this chapter discusses quite a range of psychological findings, it is not intended to be a comprehensive overview of the empirical literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Draft of September 2015 Elinor Mason For Christian Seidel (ed.) Consequentialism: new directions, new problems? OUP, forthcoming. There are two different ways of thinking about the relationship between consequentialism and moral responsibility. First, we might think that consequentialism can give us an account of responsibility. I discuss this possibility briefly, and then set it aside. The other way of thinking about the relationship is the focus of this paper. The question that concerns me, is, to what extent is a normative theory, consequentialism in particular, constrained by requirements that stem from concerns about responsibility? 1. Consequentialist Accounts of Moral Responsibility J.J.C. Smart suggests that we can extend consequentialist reasoning about morality to reasoning about responsibility. One of the attractions of consequentialism is that it provides such a straightforward and attractive account of justification for our moral practices. Why do we pay our taxes, treat each other with respect, look after each other and so on? Because doing so has good consequences. However, this sort of justification, though very appealing when considering moral practice, becomes extremely counterintuitive in other sorts of case. For example, it seems obvious that justification for beliefs cannot be consequentialist. Beliefs must be justified in some way that relates to their truth, though of course there is disagreement about exactly what makes a belief justified. Similarly, so a familiar line of thought goes, whether or not someone is responsible for an act, or for anything else, cannot be determined by looking at the consequences of holding them responsible. The claim that 1 responsibility can be understood in a consequentialist way seems like a category mistake.1 Smart’s view might be correct that, insofar as praising and blaming are actions, consequentialists should take the value of the consequences of performing those acts as the relevant factor in deciding whether or not to perform them.
    [Show full text]
  • SOCRATES in the CLASSROOM Rationales and Effects of Philosophizing with Children Ann S
    SOCRATES IN THE CLASSROOM Rationales and Effects of Philosophizing with Children Ann S. Pihlgren Socrates in the Classroom Rationales and Effects of Philosophizing with Children Ann S. Pihlgren Stockholm University ©Ann S. Pihlgren, Stockholm 2008 Cover: Björn S. Eriksson ISSN 1104-1625-146 ISBN (978-91-7155-598-4) Printed in Sweden by Elanders Sverige AB Distributor: Stockholm University, Department of Education To Kjell with love and gratitude. Contents Contents ........................................................................................................ vii Preface ............................................................................................................ 1 1 Introduction ............................................................................................ 3 1.1 Philosophizing and teaching ethics ..................................................................... 4 1.2 Some guidance for the reader ............................................................................ 5 1.3 Considerations ................................................................................................... 8 2 Research Goals and Design .................................................................. 9 2.1 Classroom interaction ......................................................................................... 9 2.2 Studying Socratic interaction ............................................................................ 10 2.3 Research questions .........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Kenneth Hamilton
    Kenneth Hamilton THE FALSE GLITTER OF THE GOLDEN MEAN A cYNICAL OPINION holds that the great thinkers of the past had but one thing in common-their thoughts were wrong. It may be more nearly true to say that all great thinkers tend to encourage wrong thinking in us. For we are inclined to take over the phrases they have made famous, imagining that we have been given magic formulae to solve our problems without having to do any thinking ourselves. A case in point is Aristotle's doctrine of the Mean. This doctrine has a certain cogency in the context of classical ethics: that, and no more than that. Yet today it is often lifted out of its context and put forward as a general principle both simple and authoritative. The Good (it is urged) stands in a middle place; and therefore any~ thing which can be shown to occupy a middle place must be a Good Thing. Obviously, Aristotle cannot be blamed for later distortions of his doctrine. And the doctrine of the Mean was not entirely his invention. Tracing virtue to a "middle way" between extremes was almost a habit of the Greeks, as we learn from Plato, who tells us of the inscription "Nothing in excess" in the temple at Delphi. Nevertheless, Aristotle's account of the Mean in the Nichomachean Ethics is de­ cisive in the history of this particular tradition. The person who "loves well the Golden Mean" (the phrase is from Horace) may not have the Ethics directly in mind, but the argument of that treatise will lie at the back of what he believes.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Ethics
    Normative ethics From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Normative ethics is the new "it" branch of philosophical ethics concerned with Ethics classifying actions as right and wrong. Theoretical Normative ethics attempts to develop a set of rules governing human conduct, Meta-ethics or a set of norms for action. It deals with what people should believe to be right Normative · Descriptive Consequentialism and wrong, as distinct from descriptive ethics, which deals with what people do Deontology believe to be right and wrong. Hence, normative ethics is sometimes said to be Virtue ethics prescriptive, rather than descriptive. Ethics of care Good and evil · Morality Moreover, because it examines standards for the rightness and wrongness of actions, normative ethics is distinct from meta-ethics, which studies the nature Applied of moral statements, and from applied ethics, which places normative rules in practical contexts. Bioethics · Medical Engineering · Environmental Human rights · Animal rights Normative ethical theories Legal · Media Business · Marketing Consequentialism (Teleology) argues that the morality of an action is Religion · War contingent on the action's outcome or result. Some consequentialist theories include: Core issues Utilitarianism, which holds that an action is right if it leads to the most value for the greatest number of people (Maximizes value for Justice · Value all people). Right · Duty · Virtue Egoism, the belief that the moral person is the self-interested Equality · Freedom · Trust person, holds that an action is right if it maximizes good for the Free will · Consent self. Moral responsibility Deontology argues that decisions should be made considering the factors Key thinkers of one's duties and other's rights.
    [Show full text]
  • CHV 319: Normative Ethics Fall Semester 2014/15
    PHI 319/ CHV 319: Normative Ethics Fall semester 2014/15 Instructor: Johann Frick Office: 203 Marx Hall Office Hours: Wednesdays 10am-noon. Phone: 8-9494 Email: [email protected] Course Description Normative ethics is the systematic study of what is morally right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust, and why. In Part 1 of this course, we will closely examine a number of rival moral theories that provide answers to these questions. We will contrast utilitarian or, more broadly, consequentialist moral theories with various non-consequentialist alternatives, such as contractualism and Kantian ethics, and investigate their respective strengths and weaknesses. Amongst the issues we will discuss are: • Obligations to the distant needy and the demandingness of consequentialism • Ideal vs non-ideal moral theories • Theories of wellbeing • Moral aggregation and the ‘Numbers Problem’ • Intentions and permissibility and the ‘Doctrine of Double Effect’ • Killing vs letting die and the ‘Trolley Problem’ • Negative responsibility, complicity with evil, and the problem of ‘dirty hands’ • Moral maxims and Kant’s Categorical Imperative. In Part 2 of the course, we will look at a number of concrete issues in normative ethics, often connected to the broader theoretical debates examined in Part 1. These will include: • Liberty and paternalism • Moral limits on markets: objections from commodification and exploitation • The value of distributive equality • The ethics of risk imposition • ‘Moral luck’ • Suicide • Abortion • The moral status of future persons and the ‘Non-Identity Problem’. Course Requirements Lectures are Tuesdays and Thursdays, 11:00 to 11:50 am, in McCosh 2. The location and timing of precepts will be determined after the second class.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics for A-Level for AQA Philosophy and OCR Religious Studies
    Ethics for A-Level For AQA Philosophy and OCR Religious Studies MARK DIMMOCK AND ANDREW FISHER To access digital resources including: blog posts videos online appendices and to purchase copies of this book in: hardback paperback ebook editions Go to: https://www.openbookpublishers.com/product/639 Open Book Publishers is a non-profit independent initiative. We rely on sales and donations to continue publishing high-quality academic works. Ethics for A-Level Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher https://www.openbookpublishers.com © 2017 Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license (CC BY 4.0). This license allows you to share, copy, distribute and transmit the work; to adapt the work and to make commercial use of the work providing attribution is made to the authors (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Attribution should include the following information: Mark Dimmock and Andrew Fisher, Ethics for A-Level. Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers, 2017, https:// doi.org/10.11647/OBP.0125 In order to access detailed and updated information on the license, please visit https://www. openbookpublishers.com/product/639#copyright Further details about CC BY licenses are available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ All external links were active at the time of publication unless otherwise stated and have been archived via the Internet Archive Wayback Machine at https://archive.org/web Digital material and resources associated with this volume are available at https://www.openbookpublishers. com/product/639#resources ISBN Paperback: 978-1-78374-388-9 ISBN Hardback: 978-1-78374-389-6 ISBN Digital (PDF): 978-1-78374-390-2 ISBN Digital ebook (epub): 978-1-78374-391-9 ISBN Digital ebook (mobi): 978-1-78374-392-6 DOI: 10.11647/OBP.0125 Cover image: Malaysia from the Sky, photo by Ishan @seefromthesky.
    [Show full text]
  • Acquainting Yourself with Ethics a Tour of the Ethics Hall of Fame
    1 Acquainting Yourself with Ethics A Tour of the Ethics Hall of Fame They honestly consider they are doing the right thing. E.W. Elkington, 1907, on New Guinea Cannibals Or are you a clear thinker examining what is good and useful for society and spending your life in building what is useful and destroying what is harmful? Kahlil Gibran, Mirrors of the Soul Good laws lead to the making of better ones; bad laws bring about worse. As soon as any man says of the affairs of the State, “What does it matter to me?” the State may be given up for lost. Rousseau The present moral crisis is due among other things to the demand for a moral code which is intellectually respectable. R. Niebuhr 1 2ETHICS IN CRIMINAL JUSTICE:IN SEARCH OF THE TRUTH What You Will Learn from This Chapter To understand the foundation of ethics, you should learn the virtue of knowledge and reasoning, the sources of intellect, the nature of truth, the nature of reality, the nature of morality, the nature of goodness, the relationship between actions and consequences, determinism and intentionalism, and the image of the ethical person. You will also learn the reasoning process, Plato’s divided line, the definition of morality and ethics, the grammar of goodness, the principle of summum bonum, and the utilitarianism measure. Key Terms and Definitions Reasoning is a pure method of thinking by which proper conclusions are reached through abstract thought processes. The Divided Line is Plato’s theory of knowledge. It characterizes four levels of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF Lecture 5 a REVOLUTION
    Founders of Western Philosophy: Thales to Hume a 12-lecture course by DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF Edited by LINDA REARDAN, Ph.D. Lecture 5 A REVOLUTION: THE BIRTH OF REASON, PART II A Publication of CONTENTS Preface iv 1. Aristotle’s Teleology 2 2. The Unmoved Mover 8 3. Refutation of Zeno’s Paradoxes 15 4. Aristotle’s Psychology: The Natural Soul 17 5. Psychology Continued: Sense-Perception and Reason 22 6. Prime Matter and the Levels of Reality 29 7. Aristotle’s Ethics: Self-Realization and the Golden Mean 35 8. Political Philosophy 57 9. Conclusion 61 Study Questions 65 iii Lecture 5 A REVOLUTION: THE BIRTH OF REASON, PART II Last week we surveyed Aristotle’s epistemology and some of the essentials of his metaphysics. In regard to metaphysics, we said that reality for Aristotle is this world, the world in which we live, the world of concrete individual things as perceived through man’s senses. We said that for Aristotle each individual object, each primary substance, is comprised of two elements: a univer- salizing element, which constitutes the basis for our putting it into a certain class and ascribing to it a certain nature; and an individuating element, which constitutes the basis of its unique- ness and makes it a this. Aristotle’s technical terms for these two elements, you recall, are “form” and “matter.” Matter is the stuff or material compris- ing a thing; form represents its structure or organization. In these terms, change, we said, is the process of matter taking on new form, so that change in no way involves a contradiction; it is eminently logical, rational, scientifically intelligible.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and Aristotle on the Vocation of the Philosopher
    CHAPTER ONE PLATO AND ARISTOTLE ON THE VOCATION OF THE PHILOSOPHER Lecture I The enterprise called philosophy appears first in the writings of Plato and Aristotle. It is in the Platonic dialogues and in the treatises or lec- tures of Aristotle that Philosophy is for the first time discussed exten- sively, put forth as the highest and most proper or most worthy human endeavor, and defended against its multitudinous adversaries. Certainly there were philosophers before Plato, but their writings were either non-existent, or have survived only in fragmentary fashion. We learn about them for the most part from what we would call today secondary sources. To what extent Plato and Aristotle are reliable in their reports of their predecessors will forever remain a moot question, notwithstanding the voluminous scholarship which attempts to answer just this question. But there is no gainsaying that not only do all major philosophic problems make their appearance in the writings of the two major Greek philosophers, there is hardly a problem which interests them more and which is always present in their minds—sometimes in the back of their minds—than the question of philosophy itself, and of the vocation of the philosopher. My intention is to discuss the two-fold meaning of the term voca- tion: vocation as occupation or activity, and vocation as calling or duty. Or if you will, the philosopher’s duty to himself and the philoso- pher’s duty to others. We all know that philosophy is a problematic term, and we have just been reminded that “vocation” is also an equivocal term.
    [Show full text]
  • A Further Reinterpretation of the Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill
    A FURTHER REINTERPRETATION OF THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN STUART MILL. by Derek Jo Banks M.A.9 University of Glasgow, 1970 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Philosophy 0 DEREK JOHN BANKS 1972 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY January 1972 Name : Derek J. Banks !iiitlc of '.thesis : li ir'urther deinterpretation of the Floral I'hilosophy of John ,Stuart Mill Examining Cornrni-ttee : Chairman: Kay Jennings """ Lionel Kenner Senior Supervisor P "-" Donald G. Brown Lxt ernal Axaminer &of essor of 'hilosophy University of British Columbia I ABSTRACT Those of Mill's critics who focus their attention on Utilitarianism assume that Mill must have held that certain ethical sentences, including one expressing the principle of utility, are properly describable as true. In this thesis I set out to demonstrate the spuriousness of this assumption. I begin by showing that in several important works - works which he thought much more highly of than he did Utilitarianism - Mill denied that the truth (or falsity) of any ethical sentences can ever be established. Next I produce evidence that his reason for this denial lies in his commitment to the view that ethical sentences are really disguised imperative sentences, and hence have no truth-value. Pinally, it is argued that there is nothing in Utilitarianism that is inconsistent with the meta-ethical position which we have found him to adopt in his other works related to ethics. In a short coneluding chapter I devote as much space as I deem permissible in a thesis of this type to show that reinterpretation of Mill's ethical theory on an imperative model renders it more plausible than it is generally taken to be, since all theories which allow truth-values to ethical sentences are open to knock-down objections.
    [Show full text]
  • A. the Three Main Branches of the Philosophical Study of Ethics 1
    A. The Three Main Branches of the Philosophical Study of Ethics 1. Meta-ethics 2. Normative Ethics 3. Applied Ethics 1 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 1. Are ethical statements such as "lying is wrong", or "friendship is good" true or false? a) cognitivism: the view that moral judgments are capable of being true or false b) non-cognitivism: the view that moral judgments are not capable of being true or false (instead they are like commands or interjections) c) debate limited to statements like examples above NOT statements like “Most Catholics oppose abortion” 2 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 2. Assuming there are truths of morality, what sorts of facts make them true? a) subjectivism: the view that moral truths are subjective, i.e., dependent upon the subjective attitudes, values, desires and beliefs of individuals, not on anything external to these things. b) objectivism: the view that moral truths are objective, i.e., based on facts that are independent of the attitudes, values, desires and beliefs of any individual. 3 1 B. Meta-ethics consists in the attempt to answer the fundamental philosophical questions about the nature of ethical theory itself. Examples: 3. What makes ethical discourse meaningful? Is it different from what makes other sorts of discourse meaningful? 4. How do the rules of logic apply to ethical arguments and ethical reasoning? Is it possible to validly infer a moral conclusion based on non-moral premises? 4 B.
    [Show full text]