Dialogue About the Doctrine of Consideration James D

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dialogue About the Doctrine of Consideration James D Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 1 Issue 5 July 1990 Dialogue About the Doctrine of Consideration James D. Gordon III Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation James D. Gordon III, Dialogue About the Doctrine of Consideration , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 986 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss5/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A DIALOGUE ABOUT THE DOCTRINE OF CONSIDERATION James D. Gordon IIt Great scholars' have long contemplated the doctrine of consid- eration in contract law. 2 Come with me, if you will, 3 to a lawyer's office, where a conversation between the lawyer and a client is about to take place. 4 The lawyer is Robert Lichten (L), and the client is t Professor of Law, Brigham Young University Law School. B.A. 1977, Brigham Young University; J.D. 1980, Boalt Hall School of Law, University of California, Berke- ley. I wanted to thank several famous law professors who commented on this article in order to persuade lawreview editors that the article is really good, or in any event that I have several famous law professor friends and am probably pretty famous myself. Un- fortunately, the famous people I contacted told me they were too busy to read the arti- cle, not counting one person who read it and threatened to sue me if I mentioned his name anywhere in the article, or anytime during my entire life, for that matter. But here is the article anyway, with apologies to Pat Bagley, Jae R. Ballif, Dave Barry, George Carlin, Johnny Carson, the Congress of Wonders, Craig Griffin, Brian C. Johnson, Mel Lazarus, Tom Lehrer, Jay Leno, Hans A. Linde, Walter F. Pratt, Jr., Bud Scruggs, Mark Twain, and others. 1 Id. However, it is humbling for me to realize that by the time Stephen Crane was my age, he had been dead for six years. 2 And no wonder. Consideration is to contract law as Elvis is to rock-and-roll: the King. Revisionists, however, have questioned Elvis's greatness. They have wrestled with one disturbing issue: if Elvis is so great, how come he's buried in his own back- yard-like a hamster. They address the question openly, knowing that it is legally im- possible to slander a dead hamster. s Alfred Hitchcock and Rod Serling used this phrase when they were about to in- troduce you to a nightmare. 4 Law review articles in conversational style are in, and I certainly do not want to be left out. The best known is Peter Gabel & Duncan Kennedy, Roll Over Beethoven, 36 STAN. L. Rxv. 1 (1984), an abstruse dialogue about critical legal studies that sounds "like a pair of old acid-heads chewing over a passage in Sartre." David Luban, Legal Modern- ism, 84 MicH. L. REv. 1656, 1671 (1986). Actually, I don't know much about acid-heads. I attended BYU as an undergradu- ate. By the time I arrived at Berkeley in the late 70s, drugs were becoming pass6, mostly because students could see ex-flower children from the 60s still wandering around Berkeley with vacant stares like those people in old pioneer photographs. While a few of my classmates still believed in "Better Living through Chemistry" (and a few had a slight dependency problem involving catnip), most of us were more "into" being laid-back, natural, and holistic, and getting in touch with our feelings. We learned that "the body is an entity." We didn't know what that meant, but it gave us a feeling of wholeness, which was one of the feelings we were busy trying to get in touch with. We ate stone ground bread. The primary advantage of stone ground bread is that it tastes better than oat bran. Of course, dirt tastes better than oat bran, too. But dirt wasn't organic enough. The official student health manual encouraged people not to wear underarm deo- dorant. It said something like, "Put some on. How does your body feel? Does your body like that?" I am not making this up. Consequently, some of our classes were pow- 987 988 CORNELL LAW REVIEW [Vol. 75:987 Carla Marchant (M),5 the president of Slater Valley Coal Company. The camera zooms in, and the volume increases until we can hear what they are saying. 6 L: How can I help you today? M: My company has a contract to sell as much coal to Barton Steel Company 7 as it requires. The market price of coal has risen, so I asked Barton whether it would be willing to increase the con- tract price, and it agreed. I need you to draft the amendment. Here is the original contract. L: (After reading it for a few minutes.)8 This contract is not enforceable. M: What? Why not? L: It provides that Barton can terminate at any time without notice. This is called an unrestricted termination clause, and it means that there is no consideration for your promises in the contract.9 M: What's consideration? L: There are many definitions of consideration, but basically it's a performance or return promise which is bargained for.' 0 There must be consideration for your promises to make them le- gally binding. Although Barton made lots of promises in the con- tract, it can terminate at any time. This is called the "illusory promise" situation." Since Barton's promises are unenforceable, they cannot serve as consideration for your promises. Therefore, you are entitled to walk away from the contract. M: We don't want to walk away from it. We want to modify it, and Barton agreed. erful enough to knock over large rodents at 200 yards. Or at least make their eyes water. Of course, this all changed when interviewing season began. We could figure some things out for ourselves. 5 Notice how the capital letters also stand for lawyer (L), and merchant (M). No- tice also the clever play between "Marchant" and "merchant." Bonus points are awarded for recognizing that "Carla" and "client" both start with "C." This fascinating skill is related to the ability law professors have of writing those absolutely hilarious final exams that just slay students and send them into paroxysms of hysterical laughter. Law professors learn how to write those witty exams at an AALS seminar for new professors, "How to Make Up for Your Humorless Teaching Style on the Final Exam." 6 Thereby setting the billing meter running. Twenty-five hundred billable hours, here I come! 7 I would point out that the seller's name begins with "S" and the buyer's name begins with "B," but you probably saw that already and are sick of my pointing out the incredibly obvious. The merely obvious will do. 8 Moving his lips only slightly. 9 JOHN CALAMARI &JOSEPH PERILLO, THE LAw OF CONTRACTS 229 (3d ed. 1987). 10 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF CONTRACTS § 71(1) (1979). 11 SeeJ. CALAMARI &J. PERILLO, supra note 9, at 228-32. 1990] A DIALOGUE ON CONSIDERATION 989 L: But the contract is unenforceable. Basically, you didn't get anything of value out of the deal. M: Lawyers are so arrogant. 12 Do you think that we spent 3 hours negotiating the deal and thousands of dollars in legal fees' drafting it just for fun? We got precisely what we wanted out of this deal, and the value we received justified our making a commitment to sell coal to Barton. It had commercial utility to us; otherwise we would not have done it. L: What were you bargaining for? M: We were bargaining for a business relationship, 14 the chance to sell coal to Barton. 15 Barton will probably buy an enor- mous amount of coal from us; it will probably not terminate. That's worth a lot-to us, anyway. L: But it's invalid consideration. 16 Barton's promise is illusory. M: You must learn to stop being so condescending. 17 Do you think we're fools? 18 That we can't read?19 We knew that we agreed to a termination clause. We were willing to live with that; we were 20 still willing to commit ourselves to the bargain. L: Not every bargained-for thing counts as consideration. 21 12 However, it is unfair to judge the entire profession by five or six hundred thou- sand bad apples. 13 See supra note 6. 14 Cf. Stewart Macauley, An Empirical View of Contract, 1985 Wis. L. Rv. 465, 468: [Academic contract theories] rest on worlds of discrete transactions where people respond to calculations of short-term advantange. How- ever, people engaged in business often find that they do not need con- tract planning and contract law because of relational sanctions. There are effective private governments and social fields, affected but seldom controlled by the formal legal system. Even discrete transactions take place within a setting of continuing relationships and interdependence. The value of these relationships means that all involved must work to satisfy each other. Potential disputes are suppressed, ignored, or com- promised in the service of keeping the relationship alive. 15 See CHARLES FRIED, CONTRACT AS PROMISE 31 (1981). 16 "Invalid consideration" is an oxymoron, like legal ethics, marital bliss, military intelligence, family vacation, civil war, postal service, scholar athlete, Amtrak schedule, interesting professor, and Justice [insert the name of your least favorite Supreme Court justice here].
Recommended publications
  • Contract Law for Paralegals: Chapter 2 Chapter 2
    Contract Law for Paralegals: Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Tab Text CHAPTER 2 The Offer Phase Chapter 2 is in three parts: (1) the classical offer-the promisor’s promise and consideration for that promise; (2) alternatives to classical consideration so an offer is created; and (3) alternative causes of action (reliance cause of action and restitution cause of action) when no offer is created. Chapter 2 begins with a definition of offer-the promisor’s creation of power in the promisee so the promisee can accept and thereby form a contract. Whether this power is created depends on whether the promisor manifests a willingness to enter into a contract by inviting the promisee to agree to the promisor’s terms. Whether the promisor’s manifestation creates this willingness is evaluated on an objective rather than a subjective basis. Offer vs. No Offer Using a Subjective or an Objective Standard is Exhibit 2-1 (50). The Road Map for the Offer Phase is Exhibit 2-2 (52) and can be downloaded from the Online Companion to this text. The Classical Offer Tab Text THE CLASSICAL OFFER-THE PROMISOR’S PROMISE AND CONSIDERATION FOR THAT PROMISE The two components of the classical offer are the promisor’s promise and the consideration for the promisor’s promise. The text clearly differentiates the promisor’s promise from the consideration for that promise. Without a promisor’s promise there can be no offer. Without consideration for the promisor’s promise there can be no offer. Students are forced to dissect the offer into its components rather than use a macro approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning Law Is
    CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION TO LAW AND LEGAL REASONING LAW IS "MAN MADE" IT CHANGES OVER TIME TO ACCOMMODATE SOCIETY'S NEEDS LAW IS MADE BY LEGISLATURE LAW IS INTERPRETED BY COURTS TO DETERMINE 1)WHETHER IT IS "CONSTITUTIONAL" 2)WHO IS RIGHT OR WRONG THERE IS A PROCESS WHICH MUST BE FOLLOWED (CALLED "PROCEDURAL LAW") I. Thomas Jefferson: "The study of the law qualifies a man to be useful to himself, to his neighbors, and to the public." II. Ask Several Students to give their definition of "Law." A. Even after years and thousands of dollars, "LAW" still is not easy to define B. What does law Consist of ? Law consists of enforceable rule governing relationships among individuals and between individuals and their society. 1. Students Need to Understand. a. The law is a set of general ideas b. When these general ideas are applied, a judge cannot fit a case to suit a rule; he must fit (or find) a rule to suit the unique case at hand. c. The judge must also supply legitimate reasons for his decisions. C. So, How was the Law Created. The law considered in this text are "man made" law. This law can (and will) change over time in response to the changes and needs of society. D. Example. Grandma, who is 87 years old, walks into a pawn shop. She wants to sell her ring that has been in the family for 200 years. Grandma asks the dealer, "how much will you give me for this ring." The dealer, in good faith, tells Grandma he doesn't know what kind of metal is in the ring, but he will give her $150.
    [Show full text]
  • Contracts Outline
    Contracts Outline NYU Fall 2004, Professor Barry Friedman Chapter 1 What Promise Ought We Enforce.............................................................. 8 1. Why we enforce promise......................................................................................... 8 1.1. Moral claim (Foundational) ........................................................................ 8 1.2. Efficiency / Mutual exchange: we can not exchange things simultaneously.............................................................................................. 8 1.3. Reliance: somebody relies on the promise and changes his plan............. 8 1.4. Will theory: somebody makes the promise means he wants the promise to be enforced. .............................................................................................. 8 1.5. Benefits unjustly retained............................................................................ 8 2. Promise with good consideration........................................................................... 8 2.1. Bargain for exchange is the test of good consideration ............................ 8 2.2. Past consideration is no good consideration.............................................. 9 2.3. Moral promise could be enforced under material benefit rule................ 9 2.4. Illusory promise is no good consideration ................................................. 9 2.5. Conditional promise could be good consideration.................................. 10 2.6. Good consideration could be implied......................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Good Faith and Reasonable Expectations
    Good Faith and Reasonable Expectations Jay M. Feinman* I. INTRODUCTION The recognition that there is an obligation of good faith in every contract has been regarded as one of the most important advances in contract law in the twentieth century. Nevertheless, a half-century after the doctrine’s incorporation into the Restatement (Second) of Contracts and the Uniform Commercial Code, great controversy and confusion remain about it. Recent articles describe the doctrine as “a revered relic,” “a (nearly) empty vessel,” and “an underenforced legal norm.”1 A scholarly dispute about the nature of the doctrine framed more than thirty years ago has hardly been advanced, much less resolved.2 More importantly, although nearly every court has announced its support of the doctrine, often using similar language and familiar sources, many judicial opinions are confusing or confused.3 The controversy and confusion stem from a fundamental misunderstanding about the nature of the good faith obligation. That misunderstanding is a belief that good faith is a special doctrine that does not easily fit within the structure of contract law. Indeed, the doctrine is seen as potentially dangerous, threatening to undermine more fundamental doctrines and the transactions that they are designed to uphold. As a result, good * Distinguished Professor of Law, Rutgers School of Law‒Camden. The author thanks David Campbell and especially Danielle Kie Hart for their comments. This article is for Arkansas lawyer David Solomon and his son, Ray. 1. See generally Harold Dubroff, The Implied Covenant of Good Faith in Contract Interpretation and Gap-Filling: Reviling a Revered Relic, 80 ST.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Consideration Melvin Aron Eisenberg
    Cornell Law Review Volume 67 Article 2 Issue 4 April 1982 Principles of Consideration Melvin Aron Eisenberg Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Melvin Aron Eisenberg, Principles of Consideration, 67 Cornell L. Rev. 640 (1982) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol67/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PRINCIPLES OF CONSIDERATION* Melvin Aron Eisenbergt A promise, as such, is not legally enforceable. The first great ques- tion of contract law, therefore, is what kinds of promises should be en- forced. The answer to that question traditionally has been subsumed under the heading "consideration." Properly understood, that term merely stands for the set of general principles defining the conditions that make promises enforceable, and it might profitably be replaced by the more descriptive term "enforceability." Over the last hundred years or so, however, a more confined approach developed, under which con- sideration doctrine was made to turn on a bargain pivot, and was articu- lated through a set of highly particularized rules. This approach was part of a school that was characterized by an attempt to derive contract law through logical deduction from received axioms. The purpose of this Article is to reconstruct applicable doctrine along modern lines. To this end, I shall develop an analysis in which bargain is only one of several alternative conditions of enforceability, and the law concerning the enforceability of promises is expressed in principles that are suffi- ciently open-textured to account for human reality, and to permit growth of doctrine as principles unfold and social facts change over time.' Two propositions underlie the analysis and should be stated at the outset.
    [Show full text]
  • An Empirical Analysis, 46 Ind. L. Rev. 797 (2013)
    UIC School of Law UIC Law Open Access Repository UIC Law Open Access Faculty Scholarship 2013 Dysfunctional Contracts and the Laws and Practices That Enable Them: An Empirical Analysis, 46 Ind. L. Rev. 797 (2013) Debra Pogrund Stark John Marshall Law School, [email protected] Jessica M. Choplin Eileen Linnabery Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.uic.edu/facpubs Part of the Consumer Protection Law Commons, Contracts Commons, Housing Law Commons, Law and Psychology Commons, and the Property Law and Real Estate Commons Recommended Citation Debra Pogrund Stark, Jessica M. Choplin & Eileen Linnabery, Dysfunctional Contracts and the Laws and Practices That Enable Them: An Empirical Analysis, 46 Ind. L. Rev. 797 (2013) https://repository.law.uic.edu/facpubs/431 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by UIC Law Open Access Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in UIC Law Open Access Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of UIC Law Open Access Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DYSFUNCTIONAL CONTRACTS AND THE LAWS AND PRACTICES THAT ENABLE THEM: AN EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS DEBRA POGRUND STARK* DR. JESSICA M. CHOPLIN** EILEEN LINNABERY*** INTRODUCTION A review of purchase agreement forms used by condominium developers in Chicago, Illinois from 2003-2008 (the "Condo Contracts Study"') discovered that 79% contained highly unfair, one-sided remedies clauses. Specifically, as detailed in Part I, these forms provided that the buyer's sole remedy in the event of the seller's breach was the return of the buyer's own earnest money.2 This is not a meaningful remedy because it does not cover any of the losses buyers would normally be entitled to under the law due to a breach of the contract, creating-as one court put it--"heads-I-win, tails-you-lose" illusory agreements.3 In essence, these clauses constitute a waiver of the right to recover benefits of the bargain/expectation damages, consequential damages, reliance-type damages, and * Professor of Law, The John Marshall Law School.
    [Show full text]
  • Stop Teaching Consideration
    20 NEV. L.J. 503 STOP TEACHING CONSIDERATION Alan M. White* TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 504 I. CONSIDERATION: THE FAILED UNIFIED THEORY OF CONTRACT ........ 505 II. THE CORE AND THE COROLLARIES—TACKLING THE ISSUES ............. 507 A. The Non-Exchange Economy—Charitable Subscriptions, Free Services, and Gift Promises ........................................................ 508 1. The Problem and the Values at Stake ................................... 508 2. Choice of Rules ..................................................................... 509 3. The State of the Law.............................................................. 511 B. The Post-Contract Modification ................................................. 513 1. The Problem and the Values at Stake ................................... 513 2. Choice of Rules ..................................................................... 518 3. The State of the Law.............................................................. 519 C. The Firm Offer or Option Contract ............................................ 521 1. The Problem and Competing Values .................................... 521 2. Choice of Rules ..................................................................... 521 3. The State of the Law.............................................................. 522 D. Discharged Past Debts and Promises Recognizing Past Benefits .......................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Unilateral-Modification Provisions in Employment Arbitration Agreements Michael L
    Hofstra Labor and Employment Law Journal Volume 24 | Issue 1 Article 3 2006 Unilateral-Modification Provisions in Employment Arbitration Agreements Michael L. DeMichele Richard A. Bales Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlelj Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation DeMichele, Michael L. and Bales, Richard A. (2006) "Unilateral-Modification Provisions in Employment Arbitration Agreements," Hofstra Labor and Employment Law Journal: Vol. 24: Iss. 1, Article 3. Available at: http://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/hlelj/vol24/iss1/3 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Labor and Employment Law Journal by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DeMichele and Bales: Unilateral-Modification Provisions in Employment Arbitration Agre UNILATERAL-MODIFICATION PROVISIONS IN EMPLOYMENT ARBITRATION AGREEMENTS Michael L. DeMichele*and RichardA. Bales** I. INTRODUCTION ....................................................................... 63 II. BACKGROUND ....................................................................... 65 A. ENACTMENT OF THE FEDERAL ARBITRATION A C T ............................................................................. 65 B. ROLE OF STATE CONTRACT LAW .............................. 67 III. ENFORCING UNILATERAL-MODIFICATION CLAUSES - TH E SPLIT ........................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • United States District Court Southern District of Texas Corpus Christi Division
    Case 2:14-cv-00265 Document 32 Filed in TXSD on 01/16/15 Page 1 of 12 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF TEXAS CORPUS CHRISTI DIVISION TNT CRANE & RIGGING INC, § § Plaintiff, § VS. § CIVIL ACTION NO. 2:14-CV-265 § JOHN ATKINSON, et al , § § Defendants. § ORDER Before the Court are Defendants’ nearly identical motions for summary judgment (D.E. 23, 26), challenging Plaintiff’s claims to the extent that they rely on the enforceability of non-compete agreements between Plaintiff TNT Crane & Rigging, Inc. (TNT) and Defendant John Atkinson (Atkinson). TNT responds that the motions are improper because they are not specific in challenging any particular legal theory and because Defendant Allegiance Crane & Equipment, LLC (Allegiance) does not have standing to challenge contracts to which it was not a party. TNT further responds that the non-compete agreements are fully enforceable. For the reasons set out below, the motions are DENIED. BACKGROUND TNT employed Atkinson as a crane operator in February 2006. In March 2012, TNT promoted Atkinson to a position as Sales Representative. In December 2013, as part of his promotion and pursuant to a Long-Term Incentive Plan, TNT agreed to provide Atkinson with equity interests in the TNT partnership that would vest over a 1 / 12 Case 2:14-cv-00265 Document 32 Filed in TXSD on 01/16/15 Page 2 of 12 period of years so long as Atkinson remained employed and complied with certain restrictive covenants. Among the covenants were non-compete, non-solicitation of TNT employees, and confidentiality agreements. As a Sales Representative, Atkinson was provided with access to a wealth of TNT’s confidential information.
    [Show full text]
  • The Illusory Promise of Stakeholder Governance
    \\jciprod01\productn\C\CRN\106-1\CRN102.txt unknown Seq: 1 16-FEB-21 10:54 THE ILLUSORY PROMISE OF STAKEHOLDER GOVERNANCE Lucian A. Bebchuk† & Roberto Tallarita‡ To address growing concerns about the negative effects of corporations on their stakeholders, supporters of stakeholder governance (“stakeholderism”) advocate a governance model that encourages and relies on corporate leaders to serve the interests of stakeholders and not only those of shareholders. We conduct a conceptual, economic, and empirical analysis of stakeholderism and its expected consequences. Stakeholder- ism, we conclude, is an inadequate and substantially counter- productive approach to addressing stakeholder concerns. To assess the promise of stakeholderism to protect stakeholders, we analyze the full array of incentives facing corporate lead- ers; empirically investigate whether they have in the past used discretion to protect stakeholders; and show that recent † James Barr Ames Professor of Law, Economics, and Finance, and Director of the Program on Corporate Governance, Harvard Law School. Professor Bebchuk is serving as an advisor to the American Law Institute’s project on the Restatement of the Law, Corporate Governance, which is examining the subjects of corporate purpose and social responsibility. ‡ Terence M. Considine Senior Fellow in Law and Economics, and Associate Director of the Program on Corporate Governance, Harvard Law School. This Article is part of the Project on Stakeholder Capitalism of the Harvard Law School Program on Corporate Governance. Responses to this Article by Einer Elhauge (Harvard Law School), Colin Mayer (Oxford University), and Aneil Kovvali and William Savitt (University of Chicago and Wachtell Lipton, respectively), are expected to be published in issue 7 of the Cornell Law Review, Volume 106, 2021.
    [Show full text]
  • A Trend Toward Enforceability: Covenants Not to Compete in At
    A Trend Toward Enforceability Covenants Not to Compete in At-Will Employment Relationships Following Sheshunoff and Mann Frankfort By Eric Behrens exas statute provides that every “contract, combination, or ees. 5 This was particularly troubling to employers who had pro - Tconspiracy in restraint of trade or commerce is unlawful.” 1 vided their at-will employees with confidential information in Although a covenant not to compete by its nature is a restraint reliance on such covenants, and yet were unable to enforce them on trade, Section 15.50(a) of the Texas Business & Commerce when their employees took job positions with competitors. Code provides that such covenants are enforceable if they satis - The Texas Supreme Court’s 2006 and 2009 decisions in Alex fy the narrow criteria dictated in the statute. 2 Since Section Sheshunoff Management Services, L.P. v. Johnson 6 and Mann 15.50(a)’s enactment in 1989, employers across Texas have Frankfort Stein & Lipp Advisors, Inc. v. Fieldin g 7 have now abro - relied on those criteria as a guide for drafting covenants not to gated several of those decisions, clarifying Section 15.50(a)’s compete in at-will employment relationships. criteria in a manner that would cause earlier rulings to be decid - A 1994 decision by the Texas Supreme Court in Light v. Cen - ed differently today. Consistent with the Texas Legislature’s tel Cellular Company of Texa s3 was initially perceived as having original intention that Section 15.50 expand the enforceability “blueprinted” contractual language that of covenants not to compete, 8 the Court’s reinterpretation of would satisfy Section 15.50(a)’s require - Section 15.50(a) in Sheshunoff and Mann Frankfort should ments.
    [Show full text]
  • Promissory Fraud Without Breach
    PROMISSORY FRAUD WITHOUT BREACH IAN AYRES* & GREGORY KLASS** INTRODUCTION It is no doubt wrong to conflate promise breaking and lying. What parent has not heard a child say with no small degree of indignation, "You lied to me; you promised you would .... " Accusations of this kind can be evidence of conceptual confusion: You might be a scoundrel for breaking your promise, but you are not thereby a liar- someone who knowingly misrepresents an existing fact. The act of promising to do, or to refrain from doing, something in the future does not, by itself, give the promisor even the opportunity to lie.' But the action for promissory fraud suggests that our impulse to call certain promise-breakers "liars" is often correct. Promising is a single act with multiple meanings. According to the literal meaning, the speaker of the words "I promise to . ." puts herself under a certain obligation-an obligation to do the act promised. In many contexts, however, a promise to do something also represents an intent to do it. And as Lord Bowen stated in an early promissory fraud case, "the state of a man's mind is as much a fact as the state of his digestion.",2 By saying something about the promisor's present intent, the act of promising creates the opportunity to lie. We call this category of falsehoods "promissory misrepresentations" or "insincere promises."' 3 The idea is a familiar one in literature and popular culture. Consider the following episode * Townsend Professor, Yale Law School, [email protected]. ** Assistant Solicitor General, Office of the New York Attorney General, [email protected].
    [Show full text]