Borel Determinacy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Borel Determinacy Borel Determinacy Serge Grigorieff LIAFA, CNRS & Universit´eDenis Diderot-Paris 7 Groupe de travail Calculabilit´e,Complexit´eet Hasard April 12-18th 2012 1 / 65 Alternations of quantifier versus Games 2 / 65 Alternations of quantifier F (~z) ≡ 9x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 9x4 P(x0;:::; x4;~z) The human mind seems limited in its ability to understand and vizualize beyond four or five alternations of quantifier. Indeed, it can be argued that the inventions, subtheories and central lemmas of various parts of mathematics are devices for assisting the mind in dealing with one or two additional alternations of quantifier. Hartley Rogers \Theory of recursive functions and effective computability" (1967) (cf. page 322 x14.7) Another (partial) explanation: 0 ! complexity ≥ Σ4(! ) ; Higher set theory!!! 3 / 65 Alternations of quantifier versus Games F (~z) ≡ 9x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 9x4 P(x0;:::; x4;~z) Roland Fra¨ıss´e'sidea (1954) Relate F (~z) to a game move 0 : I plays some x Two players 0 move 1 : II plays some x I 1 move 2 : I plays some x and 2 move 3 : II plays some x II 3 move 4 : I plays some x4 Who wins? I wins iff P(x0;:::; x4;~z) holds F (~z) () player I has a winning strategy 4 / 65 Strategies move 0 : I plays some x0 The xi 's in X move 1 : II plays some x1 move 2 : I plays some x2 I wins move 3 : II plays some x3 iff move 4 : I plays some x4 P(x0;:::; x4;~z) 2 Strategy for I = σI : fnilg [ X [ X −! X 2 Strategy for II = σI : X [ X −! X 8 x = σ (nil) < 0 I I follows strategy σI if x2 = σI(x1) : x4 = σI(x1; x3) x1 = σII(x0) II follows strategy σII if x3 = σII(x0; x1) Winning strategy: ALWAYS wins 5 / 65 Alternations of quantifier and games F (~z) ≡9 x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 9x4 P(x0;:::; x4;~z) ≡ player I has a winning strategy for the game where I wins if (x0;:::; x4) 2 P :F (~z) ≡8 x0 9x1 8x2 9x3 8x4 :P(x0;:::; x4;~z) ≡ player II has a winning strategy for the game where I wins if (x0;:::; x4) 2 P Law of Excluded Middle: either F (~z) or :F (~z) Hence either I has a winning strategy or II has a winning strategy 6 / 65 Infinitely many alternations of quantifier 9x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 ::: P((xi )i2N;~z) Moschovakis' game quantifier αG P(α;~z) 8x0 9x1 8x2 9x3 ::: :P((xi )i2N;~z) What does this mean? Infinite game Two players Iand II Rule move 2i : I plays x2i I wins iff move 2i + 1 : II plays x2i+1 (xi )i2N 2 A where A = f(xi )i2N j P((xi )i2N;~z)g 7 / 65 Two players I and II Rule move 2i : I plays x2i I wins iff move 2i + 1 : II plays x2i+1 P((xi )i2N;~z) <! Strategy for I = σI : X −! X <! Strategy for II = σII :(X n fnilg) −! X I follows σI if 8i 2 N x2i = σI((x2j+1)j<i ) II follows σII if 8i 2 N x2i+1 = σII((x2j )j≤i ) Winning strategy: ALWAYS wins 9x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 ::: P((xi )i2N;~z) ≡ I has a winning strategy 8x0 9x1 8x2 9x3 ::: :P((xi )i2N;~z) ≡ II has a winning strategy Need X well-ordered or Axiom of dependent choices 8 / 65 Excluded middle and determinacy 9x0 8x1 9x2 8x3 ::: P((xi )i2N;~z) ≡ I has a winning strategy 8x0 9x1 8x2 9x3 ::: :P((xi )i2N;~z) ≡ II has a winning strategy Fact. 8 : (9x 8x 9x 8x ::: P((x ) ;~z)) < 0 1 2 3 i i2N is equivalent to : 8x0 9x1 8x2 9x3 ::: :P((xi )i2N;~z) if and only the game is determined (one of the players has a winning strategy) 9 / 65 Which sets are determined? 10 / 65 Countable sets are determined Infinite game G(A) Two players I and II Rule move 2i : I plays x2i I wins iff move 2i + 1 : II plays x2i+1 (xi )i2N 2 A Fact. If A ⊂ X ! is countable then II has a winning strategy in G(A) Proof. Diagonal argument. If A = ffi j i 2 Ng, 2i + 1 player II plays x2i+1 6= fi (2i + 1) Are all sets determined? NO (requires the axiom of choice) 11 / 65 Borel subsets of X ! Discrete topology on X Product topology on X ! metrics d(f ; g) = 2− maxfnj8i<n f (i)=g(i)g Basis of clopen sets: the uX ! for u 2 X <! Care. if X uncountable, open sets may be unions of uncountably many clopen sets But metrizability implies closed set are G in X <! :::δ (G = intersection of countably many open sets) :::δ This allows for the usual definition of Borel sets 0 ! Σ::1(X ) = open sets 0 ! S 0 ! Σ::α(X ) = countable unions of sets in β<α Π::β(X ) 0 ! 0 ! Π::α(X ) = complements of sets in Σ::α(X ) 12 / 65 Borel determinacy Theorem. (Donald Martin, 1975) All Borel subsets of X ! are determined (whatever big is X ) Find simple winning strategies in G(A)? 1;S Alas. best (general) complexity is ∆2 if A is Borel with code S 1;S Upper bound proof. The set of ws for I is Π1 : σI is ws ≡ 8g σI ? g 2 A 1;S 1;S and every Π1 family contains some ∆2 set (cf. Rogers x16.7 Coro. XLV(c), p. 430) 13 / 65 Determinacy in classical mathematics • 1953, Gale & Stewart Boolean combinations of open subsets of X ! 0 ! 0 ! • 1955, Philip Wolfe Σ::2(X ) and Π::2(X ) sets 0 ! 0 ! • 1964, Morton Davis Σ::3(X ) and Π::3(X ) sets Results proved in 2d-order arithmetic ≡ mathematics of N and P(N) ≡ classical set theory for mathematicians (with N and P(N) one can encode reals, continuous functions,. ) 14 / 65 Determinacy in higher set theory 1 ! • 1970, Donald Martin Σ: 1(! ) in ZF + large cardinal axiom 1 ! Σ: 1(X ) in ZF + stronger large cardinal axiom 0 ! 0 ! • 1972, Jeff B. Paris Σ: 4(X ) and Π: 4(X ) sets in ZF (set theory with cardinal (2@0 )+ is enough hence 3rd-order arithmetic is enough) • 1975, Donald Martin Borel subsets of X ! in ZF • 1985, Donald Martin Much simpler proof (by far. ) in ZF Higher set theory (in ZF) is required!!! • 1971, Harvey Friedman 0 ! For Σ: 5(! ) and beyond, 2d-order arithmetic NOT ENOUGH 0 ! For Σ: 5+α(! ) need α iterations of set exponentiation • ∼2010, Donald Martin 0 ! For Σ: 4(! ) 2d-order arithmetic NOT ENOUGH 15 / 65 A few simple results about determinacy and strategies 16 / 65 Determinacy and complementation If A ⊆ X ! then the shift of A is XA = f(x; x0; x1; x2;:::) j (x0; x1; x2;:::) 2 A)g Let A ⊆ P(X !) be closed under shift: A 2 A =) xA 2 A 8A 2 A A is determined () 8A 2 A X ! n A is determined I has a ws in G(XA) =) II has a ws in G(X ! n A) II has a ws in G(XA) =) I has a ws in G(X ! n A) 17 / 65 Winning strategies viewed as trees <! Strategy σI for I ≡ tree SσI ⊆ X of all plays when I follows σ I u 2 SσI ^ juj even =) 9!x ux 2 SσI u 2 SσI ^ juj odd =) 8x ux 2 SσI (Thus, I always has exactly one possible move and there is no constraint for II-moves) <! Strategy σII for II ≡ tree SσII ⊆ X of all plays when II follows σ II u 2 SσII ^ juj odd =) 9!x ux 2 SσII u 2 SσII ^ juj even =) 8x ux 2 SσII (Thus, II always has exactly one possible move and there is no constraint for I-moves) σI winning for I () [SσI ] ⊆ A ! σII winning for II () [SσII ] ⊆ X n A ([S] = set of infinite branches of S) 18 / 65 Non deterministic winning strategies <! ND strategy σI for I ≡ tree SσI ⊆ X of all plays when I follows σ I SσI is pruned: 8u 2 SσI 9x ux 2 SσI u 2 SσI ^ juj odd =) 8x ux 2 SσI (Thus, I always has some move and there is no constraint for II-moves) <! ND strategy σII for II ≡ tree SσII ⊆ X of all plays when II follows σ II SσI is pruned: 8u 2 SσII 9x ux 2 SσI u 2 SσII ^ juj even =) 8x ux 2 SσII (Thus, II always has some move and there is no constraint for I-moves) σI winning for I () [SσI ] ⊆ A ! σII winning for II () [SσII ] ⊆ X n A 19 / 65 Winning strategies and positions <! ! ! u 2 X A ⊆ X Au = A \ clopen set uX Fact. If juj is odd (next move for II) then II has no winning strategy in G(Au) iff 8x 2 X II has no winning strategy in G(Aux ) (No \miracle" move x for player II) 20 / 65 Winning and Defensive strategies <! ! ! u 2 X A ⊆ X Au = A \ clopen set uX Fact. Let juj even (next move for player I) II has no winning strategy in G(Au) iff 9x 2 X II has no winning strategy in G(Aux ) (Player I has a move x so that II still has no ws afterwards) Always choosing such an x = Defensive strategy for player I CARE: defensive strategy 6) winning strat. 21 / 65 Gale & Stewart's results about 0 ! Σ::: 1(X ) they contain many core ideas of the theory 22 / 65 0 ! 0 ! Determinacy of Σ:: 1(X ) and Π:: 1(X ) Theorem.
Recommended publications
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory, Including the Axiom of Choice) Plus the Negation of CH
    ANNALS OF ~,IATltEMATICAL LOGIC - Volume 2, No. 2 (1970) pp. 143--178 INTERNAL COHEN EXTENSIONS D.A.MARTIN and R.M.SOLOVAY ;Tte RockeJ~'ller University and University (.~t CatiJbrnia. Berkeley Received 2 l)ecemt)er 1969 Introduction Cohen [ !, 2] has shown that tile continuum hypothesis (CH) cannot be proved in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Levy and Solovay [9] have subsequently shown that CH cannot be proved even if one assumes the existence of a measurable cardinal. Their argument in tact shows that no large cardinal axiom of the kind present;y being considered by set theorists can yield a proof of CH (or of its negation, of course). Indeed, many set theorists - including the authors - suspect that C1t is false. But if we reject CH we admit Gurselves to be in a state of ignorance about a great many questions which CH resolves. While CH is a power- full assertion, its negation is in many ways quite weak. Sierpinski [ 1 5 ] deduces propcsitions there called C l - C82 from CH. We know of none of these propositions which is decided by the negation of CH and only one of them (C78) which is decided if one assumes in addition that a measurable cardinal exists. Among the many simple questions easily decided by CH and which cannot be decided in ZF (Zerme!o-Fraenkel set theory, including the axiom of choice) plus the negation of CH are tile following: Is every set of real numbers of cardinality less than tha't of the continuum of Lebesgue measure zero'? Is 2 ~0 < 2 ~ 1 ? Is there a non-trivial measure defined on all sets of real numbers? CIhis third question could be decided in ZF + not CH only in the unlikely event t Tile second author received support from a Sloan Foundation fellowship and tile National Science Foundation Grant (GP-8746).
    [Show full text]
  • Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics
    Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics The Sci.Math FAQ Team. Editor: Alex L´opez-Ortiz e-mail: [email protected] Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 Why a list of Frequently Asked Questions? . 4 1.2 Frequently Asked Questions in Mathematics? . 4 2 Fundamentals 5 2.1 Algebraic structures . 5 2.1.1 Monoids and Groups . 6 2.1.2 Rings . 7 2.1.3 Fields . 7 2.1.4 Ordering . 8 2.2 What are numbers? . 9 2.2.1 Introduction . 9 2.2.2 Construction of the Number System . 9 2.2.3 Construction of N ............................... 10 2.2.4 Construction of Z ................................ 10 2.2.5 Construction of Q ............................... 11 2.2.6 Construction of R ............................... 11 2.2.7 Construction of C ............................... 12 2.2.8 Rounding things up . 12 2.2.9 What’s next? . 12 3 Number Theory 14 3.1 Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.1 History of Fermat’s Last Theorem . 14 3.1.2 What is the current status of FLT? . 14 3.1.3 Related Conjectures . 15 3.1.4 Did Fermat prove this theorem? . 16 3.2 Prime Numbers . 17 3.2.1 Largest known Mersenne prime . 17 3.2.2 Largest known prime . 17 3.2.3 Largest known twin primes . 18 3.2.4 Largest Fermat number with known factorization . 18 3.2.5 Algorithms to factor integer numbers . 18 3.2.6 Primality Testing . 19 3.2.7 List of record numbers . 20 3.2.8 What is the current status on Mersenne primes? .
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture Notes
    MEASURE THEORY AND STOCHASTIC PROCESSES Lecture Notes José Melo, Susana Cruz Faculdade de Engenharia da Universidade do Porto Programa Doutoral em Engenharia Electrotécnica e de Computadores March 2011 Contents 1 Probability Space3 1 Sample space Ω .....................................4 2 σ-eld F .........................................4 3 Probability Measure P .................................6 3.1 Measure µ ....................................6 3.2 Probability Measure P .............................7 4 Learning Objectives..................................7 5 Appendix........................................8 2 Chapter 1 Probability Space Let's consider the experience of throwing a dart on a circular target with radius r (assuming the dart always hits the target), divided in 4 dierent areas as illustrated in Figure 1.1. 4 3 2 1 Figure 1.1: Circular Target The circles that bound the regions 1, 2, 3, and 4, have radius of, respectively, r , r , 3r , and . 4 2 4 r Therefore, the probability that a dart lands in each region is: 1 , 3 , 5 , P (1) = 16 P (2) = 16 P (3) = 16 7 . P (4) = 16 For this kind of problems, the theory of discrete probability spaces suces. However, when it comes to problems involving either an innitely repeated operation or an innitely ne op- eration, this mathematical framework does not apply. This motivates the introduction of a measure-theoretic probability approach to correctly describe those cases. We dene the proba- bility space (Ω; F;P ), where Ω is the sample space, F is the event space, and P is the probability 3 measure. Each of them will be described in the following subsections. 1 Sample space Ω The sample space Ω is the set of all the possible results or outcomes ! of an experiment or observation.
    [Show full text]
  • Borel Structure in Groups and Their Dualso
    BOREL STRUCTURE IN GROUPS AND THEIR DUALSO GEORGE W. MACKEY Introduction. In the past decade or so much work has been done toward extending the classical theory of finite dimensional representations of com- pact groups to a theory of (not necessarily finite dimensional) unitary repre- sentations of locally compact groups. Among the obstacles interfering with various aspects of this program is the lack of a suitable natural topology in the "dual object"; that is in the set of equivalence classes of irreducible representations. One can introduce natural topologies but none of them seem to have reasonable properties except in extremely special cases. When the group is abelian for example the dual object itself is a locally compact abelian group. This paper is based on the observation that for certain purposes one can dispense with a topology in the dual object in favor of a "weaker struc- ture" and that there is a wide class of groups for which this weaker structure has very regular properties. If .S is any topological space one defines a Borel (or Baire) subset of 5 to be a member of the smallest family of subsets of 5 which includes the open sets and is closed with respect to the formation of complements and countable unions. The structure defined in 5 by its Borel sets we may call the Borel structure of 5. It is weaker than the topological structure in the sense that any one-to-one transformation of S onto 5 which preserves the topological structure also preserves the Borel structure whereas the converse is usually false.
    [Show full text]
  • Subgame-Perfect Ε-Equilibria in Perfect Information Games With
    Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit Citation for published version (APA): Flesch, J., & Predtetchinski, A. (2016). Subgame-Perfect -Equilibria in Perfect Information Games with Common Preferences at the Limit. Mathematics of Operations Research, 41(4), 1208-1221. https://doi.org/10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document status and date: Published: 01/11/2016 DOI: 10.1287/moor.2015.0774 Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Document license: Taverne Please check the document version of this publication: • A submitted manuscript is the version of the article upon submission and before peer-review. There can be important differences between the submitted version and the official published version of record. People interested in the research are advised to contact the author for the final version of the publication, or visit the DOI to the publisher's website. • The final author version and the galley proof are versions of the publication after peer review. • The final published version features the final layout of the paper including the volume, issue and page numbers. Link to publication General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal.
    [Show full text]
  • MS Word Template for CAD Conference Papers
    382 Title: Regularized Set Operations in Solid Modeling Revisited Authors: K. M. Yu, [email protected], The Hong Kong Polytechnic University K. M. Lee, [email protected], The Hong Kong Polytechnic University K. M. Au, [email protected], HKU SPACE Community College Keywords: Regularised Set Operations, CSG, Solid Modeling, Manufacturing, General Topology DOI: 10.14733/cadconfP.2019.382-386 Introduction: The seminal works of Tilove and Requicha [8],[13],[14] first introduced the use of general topology concepts in solid modeling. However, their works are brute-force approach from mathematicians’ perspective and are not easy to be comprehended by engineering trained personnels. This paper reviewed the point set topological approach using operational formulation. Essential topological concepts are described and visualized in easy to understand directed graphs. These facilitate subtle differentiation of key concepts to be recognized. In particular, some results are restated in a more mathematically correct version. Examples to use the prefix unary operators are demonstrated in solid modeling properties derivations and proofs as well as engineering applications. Main Idea: This paper is motivated by confusion in the use of mathematical terms like boundedness, boundary, interior, open set, exterior, complement, closed set, closure, regular set, etc. Hasse diagrams are drawn by mathematicians to study different topologies. Instead, directed graph using elementary operators of closure and complement are drawn to show their inter-relationship in the Euclidean three- dimensional space (E^3 is a special metric space formed from Cartesian product R^3 with Euclid’s postulates [11] and inheriting all general topology properties.) In mathematics, regular, regular open and regular closed are similar but different concepts.
    [Show full text]
  • STAT 571 Assignment 1 Solutions 1. If Ω Is a Set and C a Collection Of
    STAT 571 Assignment 1 solutions 1. If Ω is a set and a collection of subsets of Ω, let be the intersection of all σ-algebras that contain . ProveC that is the σ-algebra generatedA by . C A C Solution: Let α α A be the collection of all σ-algebras that contain , and fA j 2 g C set = α. We first show that is a σ-algebra. There are three things to A \ A A α A prove. 2 (a) For every α A, α is a σ-algebra, so Ω α, and hence Ω α A α = . 2 A 2 A 2 \ 2 A A (b) If B , then B α for every α A. Since α is a σ-algebra, we have c 2 A 2 A 2 A c B α. But this is true for every α A, so we have B . 2 A 2 2 A (c) If B1;B2;::: are sets in , then B1;B2;::: belong to α for each α A. A A 2 Since α is a σ-algebra, we have 1 Bn α. But this is true for every A [n=1 2 A α A, so we have 1 Bn . 2 [n=1 2 A Thus is a σ-algebra that contains , and it must be the smallest one since α for everyA α A. C A ⊆ A 2 2. Prove that the set of rational numbers Q is a Borel set in R. Solution: For every x R, the set x is the complement of an open set, and hence Borel.
    [Show full text]
  • Tic-Tac-Toe Is Not Very Interesting to Play, Because If Both Players Are Familiar with the Game the Result Is Always a Draw
    CMPSCI 250: Introduction to Computation Lecture #27: Games and Adversary Search David Mix Barrington 4 November 2013 Games and Adversary Search • Review: A* Search • Modeling Two-Player Games • When There is a Game Tree • The Determinacy Theorem • Searching a Game Tree • Examples of Games Review: A* Search • The A* Search depends on a heuristic function, which h(y) = 6 2 is a lower bound on the 23 s distance to the goal. x 4 If x is a node, and g is the • h(z) = 3 nearest goal node to x, the admissibility condition p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 on h is that 0 ≤ h(x) ≤ d(x, g). p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 Review: A* Search • Suppose we have taken y off of the open list. The best-path distance from the start s to the goal g through y is d(s, y) + d(y, h(y) = 6 g), and this cannot be less than 2 23 d(s, y) + h(y). s x 4 • Thus when we find a path of length k from s to y, we put y h(z) = 3 onto the open list with priority k p(y) = 23 + 2 + 6 = 31 + h(y). We still record the p(z) = 23 + 4 + 3 = 30 distance d(s, y) when we take y off of the open list. Review: A* Search • The advantage of A* over uniform-cost search is that we do not consider entries x in the closed list for which d(s, x) + h(x) h(y) = 6 is greater than the actual best- 2 23 path distance from s to g.
    [Show full text]
  • (Measure Theory for Dummies) UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008
    A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 UWEE Technical Report Number UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Department of Electrical Engineering University of Washington Box 352500 Seattle, Washington 98195-2500 PHN: (206) 543-2150 FAX: (206) 543-3842 URL: http://www.ee.washington.edu A Measure Theory Tutorial (Measure Theory for Dummies) Maya R. Gupta {gupta}@ee.washington.edu Dept of EE, University of Washington Seattle WA, 98195-2500 University of Washington, Dept. of EE, UWEETR-2006-0008 May 2006 Abstract This tutorial is an informal introduction to measure theory for people who are interested in reading papers that use measure theory. The tutorial assumes one has had at least a year of college-level calculus, some graduate level exposure to random processes, and familiarity with terms like “closed” and “open.” The focus is on the terms and ideas relevant to applied probability and information theory. There are no proofs and no exercises. Measure theory is a bit like grammar, many people communicate clearly without worrying about all the details, but the details do exist and for good reasons. There are a number of great texts that do measure theory justice. This is not one of them. Rather this is a hack way to get the basic ideas down so you can read through research papers and follow what’s going on. Hopefully, you’ll get curious and excited enough about the details to check out some of the references for a deeper understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model*
    A Note on Woodford's Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Title Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model(Nonlinear Analysis and Mathematical Economics) Author(s) Shigoka, Tadashi Citation 数理解析研究所講究録 (1994), 861: 51-66 Issue Date 1994-03 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/83844 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University 数理解析研究所講究録 第 861 巻 1994 年 51-66 51 A Note on Woodford’s Conjecture: Constructing Stationary Sunspot Equilibria in a Continuous Time Model* Tadashi Shigoka Kyoto Institute of Economic Research, Kyoto University, Yoshidamachi Sakyoku Kyoto 606 Japan 京都大学 経済研究所 新後閑 禎 Abstract We show how to construct stationary sunspot equilibria in a continuous time model, where equilibrium is indeterninate near either a steady state or a closed orbit. Woodford’s conjecture that the indeterminacy of equilibrium implies the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria remains valid in a continuous time model. 52 Introduction If for given equilibrium dynamics there exist a continuum of non-stationary perfect foresight equilibria all converging asymptoticaUy to a steady state (a deterministic cycle resp.), we say the equilibrium dynamics is indeterminate near the steady state (the deterministic cycle resp.). Suppose that the fundamental characteristics of an economy are deterministic, but that economic agents believe nevertheless that equihibrium dynamics is affected by random factors apparently irrelevant to the fundamental characteristics (sunspots). This prophecy could be self-fulfilling, and one will get a sunspot equilibrium, if the resulting equilibrium dynamics is subject to a nontrivial stochastic process and confirns the agents’ belief. See Shell [19], and Cass-Shell [3]. Woodford [23] suggested that there exists a close relation between the indetenninacy of equilibrium near a deterministic steady state and the existence of stationary sunspot equilibria in the immediate vicinity of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Set Theory
    Descriptive Set Theory David Marker Fall 2002 Contents I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 2 1 Polish Spaces 2 2 Borel Sets 14 3 E®ective Descriptive Set Theory: The Arithmetic Hierarchy 27 4 Analytic Sets 34 5 Coanalytic Sets 43 6 Determinacy 54 7 Hyperarithmetic Sets 62 II Borel Equivalence Relations 73 1 8 ¦1-Equivalence Relations 73 9 Tame Borel Equivalence Relations 82 10 Countable Borel Equivalence Relations 87 11 Hyper¯nite Equivalence Relations 92 1 These are informal notes for a course in Descriptive Set Theory given at the University of Illinois at Chicago in Fall 2002. While I hope to give a fairly broad survey of the subject we will be concentrating on problems about group actions, particularly those motivated by Vaught's conjecture. Kechris' Classical Descriptive Set Theory is the main reference for these notes. Notation: If A is a set, A<! is the set of all ¯nite sequences from A. Suppose <! σ = (a0; : : : ; am) 2 A and b 2 A. Then σ b is the sequence (a0; : : : ; am; b). We let ; denote the empty sequence. If σ 2 A<!, then jσj is the length of σ. If f : N ! A, then fjn is the sequence (f(0); : : :b; f(n ¡ 1)). If X is any set, P(X), the power set of X is the set of all subsets X. If X is a metric space, x 2 X and ² > 0, then B²(x) = fy 2 X : d(x; y) < ²g is the open ball of radius ² around x. Part I Classical Descriptive Set Theory 1 Polish Spaces De¯nition 1.1 Let X be a topological space.
    [Show full text]