The Role of Rhetoric and Delight in the Theology of Saint Augustine of Hippo

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Role of Rhetoric and Delight in the Theology of Saint Augustine of Hippo Durham E-Theses Eloquent Wisdom: The Role of Rhetoric and Delight in the Theology of Saint Augustine of Hippo CLAVIER, MARK,FORBES,MORETON How to cite: CLAVIER, MARK,FORBES,MORETON (2011) Eloquent Wisdom: The Role of Rhetoric and Delight in the Theology of Saint Augustine of Hippo, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/601/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 Eloquent Wisdom: The Role of Rhetoric and Delight in the Theology of Saint Augustine of Hippo The Rev. Mark Forbes Moreton Clavier Submitted for PhD University of Durham Department of Theology and Religion 2010 Abstract This study examines Augustine’s conception of the role of delight (delectatio ) in the divine acts of creation and redemption. In the first part of the dissertation, I argue that Augustine, who was trained as a rhetor and taught rhetoric before his conversion, came to conceive of theology as the fulfilment of Cicero’s conviction that wisdom and eloquence ought to be united. His approach to Cicero’s rhetorical theory as found in De inventione , De oratore , and Orator shares many similarities with that of Late Antique rhetors (especially Marius Victorinus) in whose works the orator functions less as a statesman than as a physician of the soul. Accordingly, an orator’s role is not to sway the senate or deliberate in law courts (as in Cicero’s thought) but to inform and persuade people towards a fruitful return to the divine. In the second part of the dissertation, I demonstrate how this approach influenced Augustine’s understanding of redemption. He conceives of God as Cicero’s ideal orator, in whom wisdom and eloquence are perfectly united. God engages in a rhetorical contest with the devil whom Augustine portrays in terms of the false orators in Cicero’s De inventione . The devil’s rhetoric comprises an illicit delight in actual sin and an inordinate delight in created goods, both of which exert their power over the human will through suggestion, delight and persuasion and result in a bondage to sin and death. By contrast, God ‘utters’ creation as a delightful song and opposes death’s nihilistic rhetoric by pouring his own delight into the hearts of the faithful; this delight persuades the will to move towards a joyful participation in the divine that is the happy life for which all people long. Ultimately, Augustine identifies this spiritual delight most closely with the Holy Spirit who functions as God’s eternal eloquence. 2 Statement of Copyright The copyright of this thesis rests with the author. No quotation from it should be published without the prior written consent and information derived from it should be acknowledged. 3 Table of Contents Abbreviations 6 1. Introduction 8 A Beleaguered Rhetor in a Beleaguered City 8 ‘...now I have grown old ’ 11 Augustine: Rhetor and Theologian 14 Delight 18 A Rhetorical Theology 25 PART I: RHETORIC 2. The Ideal Orator 38 Late Republican Rhetoric 42 ‘... quidam eloquens ’: Cicero 48 Late Roman Rhetoric 58 ‘...cuius...eloquia strenue ministrabant...populo tuo ’: Bishops 67 3. The Philosophical Rhetor 73 Marius Victorinus 73 Augustine and Cicero 83 Augustine’s Education 85 Augustine’s Conversion 92 De doctrina Christiana 98 PART II: DELIGHT 4. Participation 117 Participatory Existence 118 Creatio and Formatio 124 Conversio 128 Permaneo 132 Participatory Redemption 139 4 Earlier Texts 140 Expositio epistulae ad Galatas and Confessiones 149 Participatory Redemption in Augustine’s Sermons 154 Book IV of De Trinitate 4 158 Participatory Life 160 5. Worldly Delights 163 Introduction—Delectatio 163 Worldly Delight 169 Illicit Delight 171 Temporal Delight 180 Consuetudo 193 6. Delectatio Domini 206 ‘... to contemplate the Lord’s delight ’ 207 Delight and Creation 216 De ordine and De musica 217 ‘Measure, number and order ’ 228 Beata Vita 237 Participation and the Happy Life 240 7. Beata Delectatio 250 The Holy Spirit 252 Communio 252 Dilectio et Caritas 257 Donum Dei 262 The Rhetorical Contest 267 Romans 5.5 270 Romans 7 278 De spiritu et littera 296 Delectatio Victrix 298 Conclusion 300 Bibliography 304 5 Abbreviations Series CCL Corpus Christianorum, Series Latin (Turnhout: Brepols, 1953-) CSEL Corpus Scriptorum Ecclesiasticorum Latinorum (Vienna: Tempsky, 1865-) LCL Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) PL Patrologia Latina, Cursus Completus ed. by J.-P. Migne (Paris: 1857-1866) Ancient Works Augustine b. vita De beata vita c. Jul. imp. Contra Julianum opus imperfectum conf. Confessiones diu. qu. 83 De diuersis quaestionibus 83 doc. chr. De doctrina Christiana en. Ps. Ennarationes in Psalmos ep. Epistulae ex. Gal. Expositio Epistulae ad Galatos ex. prop. Rm. Expositio quarundam propositionum ex epistula ad Romanos fid. et sym. De fide et symbolo Gn. adu. Man. De Genesi aduersus Manicheos Gn. litt. De Genesi ad litteram Gn. litt. imp. De Genesi ad litteram imperfectus liber Jo. eu. tr. In Johannis euangelium Tractatus lib. arb. De libero arbitrio mor. De moribus ecclesiae Catholicae et de moribus Manichaeorum mus. De musica ord. De ordine quant. De quantitate animae retr. Retractationes s. Sermones s. Dom. mon. De sermone Domini in monte Simpl. Ad Simplicianum 6 spir. et litt. De spiritu et litteram trin. De trinitate vera. rel. De vera religione Cicero De inv. De inventione De orat. De oratore Off. De officiis Juvenal Sat. Saturae Seneca the Elder Con. Controversiae Marius Victorinus In Cic. Rhet. Explanationes in Ciceronis Rhetoricam 7 1 Introduction A Beleaguered Rhetor in a Beleaguered City By summer of 384, Augustine had been vexed beyond endurance. His experience of Rome had been a disagreeable one and he was eager to escape from the Eternal City. The omens had been poor from the start. First, he had to endure the tearful entreaties of his mother Monica to remain in North Africa or, if he must go, to take her with him. 1 Next, no sooner had he arrived than he fell seriously ill and believed himself to be ‘on the way to the underworld’. 2 Perhaps worst of all for a man schooled in rhetoric and whose reputation and position in life were due entirely to his teaching of rhetoric, he found his new situation in Rome, which he had admired from afar, very disappointing. Apparently, Augustine’s reputation and influential contacts were such that he had little trouble attracting pupils. Infuriatingly, however, he soon discovered that the well-heeled Roman students had a disagreeable habit of transferring to a new rhetor once payment of their fees was due. 3 No wonder Augustine was ready to endorse the decision of so many prominent Romans— including the emperors—and return to enjoying the idea of Rome from afar instead of its reality from close proximity. Fortunately, Augustine had come into the orbit of one of the most prominent men of late Roman society: Quintus Aurelius Symmachus, an immensely powerful senator, vocal defender of traditional paganism, and profuse litterateur. 4 By his own 1 conf. 5.8.15. 2 conf. 5.9.16. 3 conf. 5.12.22. 4 On Symmachus, see John Matthews, Western Aristocracies and Imperial Court AD 364-425 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 1-31; John Matthews, The Roman Empire of Ammianus 8 account, Augustine caught Symmachus’s attention partly through the networking of his Manichean friends and partly through an impromptu oration he delivered before Symmachus. 5 As a result, the old senator, still smarting perhaps from his recent political duel with Ambrose over the removal of the Altar of Victory, selected Augustine to become the new rhetor in Milan. 6 With his travel expenses covered by the imperial court, Augustine bade farewell to Rome and, though he did not yet know it, his former life. His move from the orbit of Symmachus into the orbit of Ambrose marked the beginning of his own conversion to Christianity; although he owed his advancement to the help of his Manichean friends, already he had come to reject the religion that he had shared for nine years. 7 Milan of the fourth century was with Trier one of the two administrative centres of the Western Empire. 8 When Augustine arrived in the autumn of 384, the court of the young emperor Valentinian II had for seven years resided defenceless at Milan. Though Augustine now taught rhetoric near the centre of western authority, he had come to an unhappy and beleaguered city. The empire itself was in disarray following the crushing defeat of Valens at the Battle of Adrianople (378), and even as Augustine contemplated leaving Rome, in far away Britain Magnus Maximus (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989), passim ; and Neil B. McLynn, Ambrose of Milan: Church and Court in a Christian Capital (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994), passim . 5 conf. 5.13.23. 6 McLynn, Ambrose of Milan , 169-170 proposes that the fact that Symmachus had been asked to find a rhetor for Milan and that he chose an unknown provincial for the post highlights the political weakness of the adolescent emperor.
Recommended publications
  • The Ramist Style of John Udall: Audience and Pictorial Logic in Puritan Sermon and Controversy
    Oral Tradition, 2/1 (1987): 188-213 The Ramist Style of John Udall: Audience and Pictorial Logic in Puritan Sermon and Controversy John G. Rechtien With Wilbur Samuel Howell’s Logic and Rhetoric in England, 1500-1700 (1956), Walter J. Ong’s Ramus, Method, and the Decay of Dialogue (1958) helped establish the common contemporary view that Ramism impoverished logic and rhetoric as arts of communication.1 For example, scholars agree that Ramism neglected audience accomodation; denied truth as an object of rhetoric by reserving it to logic; rejected persuasion about probabilities; and relegated rhetoric to ornamentation.2 Like Richard Hooker in Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity (I.vi.4), these scholars criticize Ramist logic as simplistic. Their objections identify the consequences of Ramus’ visual analogy of logic and rhetoric to “surfaces,” which are “apprehended by sight” and divorced from “voice and hearing” (Ong 1958:280). As a result of his analogy of knowledge and communication to vision rather than to sound, Ramus left rhetoric only two of its fi ve parts, ornamentation (fi gures of speech and tropes) and delivery (voice and gesture). He stripped three parts (inventio, dispositio, and memory) from rhetoric. Traditionally shared by logic and rhetoric, the recovery and derivation of ideas (inventio) and their organization (dispositio) were now reserved to logic. Finally, Ramus’ method of organizing according to dichotomies substituted “mental space” for memory (Ong 1958:280). In the context of this new logic and the rhetoric dependent on it, a statement was not recognized as a part of a conversation, but appeared to stand alone as a speech event fi xed in space.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of the Séance: the Scientific Theory of the Spiritualist Movement in Victorian America
    1 Hannah Gramson Larry Lipin HIST 491 March 6, 2013 The Science of the Seance: The Scientific Theory of the Spiritualist Movement in Victorian America In 1869, twenty one years after the first “spirit rappings” were heard in the bedroom of two young girls in upstate New York, a well-known Spiritualist medium by the name of Emma Hardinge Britten wrote a book that chronicled the first two decades of a religion she characterized as uniquely American, and what made this religion exceptional was its basis in scientific theory. “[We] are not aware of any other country than America,” Britten claimed, “where a popular religion thus appeals to the reason and requires its votaries to do their own thinking, or of any other denomination than 'American Spiritualists' who base their belief on scientific facts, proven by living witnesses.”1 Britten went on to claim that, as a “unique, concrete, and...isolated movement,” Spiritualism demanded “from historic justice a record as full, complete, and independent, as itself.”2 Yet, despite the best efforts of Spiritualism's followers to carve out a place for it alongside the greatest scientific discoveries in human history, Spiritualism remains a little understood and often mocked religion that, to those who are ignorant 1 Emma Hardinge Britten, Modern American Spiritualism: A Twenty Years' Record of the Communion Between Earth and the World of Spirits,(New York, 1869) 2 Britten, Modern American Spiritualism 2 of it, remains a seemingly paradoxical movement. Although it might be difficult for some to comprehend today, prior to the Civil War, religion and science were not considered adversaries by any means, but rather, were understood to be traveling down a shared path, with ultimately the same destination.
    [Show full text]
  • Inverting the Metaphor of Slavery and Freedom in Cicero
    Inverting the Metaphor of Slavery and Freedom in Cicero Particularly in the wake of Caesar’s ascension Cicero appeals regularly to the ideas of freedom and slavery in a civic context. Caesar’s dominion imposes on the Romans a kind of joint political slavery, restricting their thoughts and actions. But Cicero uses the metaphor to invert typical understandings of what slavery and freedom mean. Rather than forcing others to serve him, Caesar instead prohibits Romans from serving others, or, more specifically, from having a social environment in which to offer kindness (beneficia) to others. This rhetorical inversion ultimately aligns slavery with self-focused behavior and freedom with behavior oriented toward others. In making this inversion Cicero advocates a very particular kind of free citizenship that cannot exist under any form of autocrat, no matter how good or skilled he is. Cicero’s championing of liberty reaches its climax in the tenth Philippic, where he decries the lifeless lot of the slave and states unequivocally that death is to be preferred to slavery. In the short window between Caesar’s death and his own, Cicero speaks as one freed from the civic slavery of Caesar’s rule and apprehensive about further Roman autocracy on the horizon. He juxtaposes other nations’ willingness to suffer slavery in order to avoid pain with the Roman’s preference for virtue and honor. The comparison revisits one of the prominent themes of Cicero’s in his dialogues, namely the priority of virtue and the un-Romanness of those who prefer a pleasure/pain-oriented philosophy, viz.
    [Show full text]
  • Teachers' Pay in Ancient Greece
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) University Studies of the University of Nebraska 5-1942 Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece Clarence A. Forbes Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/univstudiespapers Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University Studies of the University of Nebraska at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Papers from the University Studies series (The University of Nebraska) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Teachers' Pay In Ancient Greece * * * * * CLARENCE A. FORBES UNIVERSITY OF NEBRASKA STUDIES Ma y 1942 STUDIES IN THE HUMANITIES NO.2 Note to Cataloger UNDER a new plan the volume number as well as the copy number of the University of Nebraska Studies was discontinued and only the numbering of the subseries carried on, distinguished by the month and the year of pu blica tion. Thus the present paper continues the subseries "Studies in the Humanities" begun with "University of Nebraska Studies, Volume 41, Number 2, August 1941." The other subseries of the University of Nebraska Studies, "Studies in Science and Technology," and "Studies in Social Science," are continued according to the above plan. Publications in all three subseries will be supplied to recipients of the "University Studies" series. Corre­ spondence and orders should be addressed to the Uni­ versity Editor, University of Nebraska, Lincoln. University of Nebraska Studies May 1942 TEACHERS' PAY IN ANCIENT GREECE * * * CLARENCE A.
    [Show full text]
  • The Protrepticus of Clement of Alexandria: a Commentary
    Miguel Herrero de Jáuregui THE PROTREPTICUS OF CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA: A COMMENTARY to; ga;r yeu'do" ouj yilh'/ th'/ paraqevsei tajlhqou'" diaskedavnnutai, th'/ de; crhvsei th'" ajlhqeiva" ejkbiazovmenon fugadeuvetai. La falsedad no se dispersa por la simple comparación con la verdad, sino que la práctica de la verdad la fuerza a huir. Protréptico 8.77.3 PREFACIO Una tesis doctoral debe tratar de contribuir al avance del conocimiento humano en su disciplina, y la pretensión de que este comentario al Protréptico tenga la máxima utilidad posible me obliga a escribirla en inglés porque es la única lengua que hoy casi todos los interesados pueden leer. Pero no deja de ser extraño que en la casa de Nebrija se deje de lado la lengua castellana. La deuda que contraigo ahora con el español sólo se paliará si en el futuro puedo, en compensación, “dar a los hombres de mi lengua obras en que mejor puedan emplear su ocio”. Empiezo ahora a saldarla, empleándola para estos agradecimientos, breves en extensión pero no en sinceridad. Mi gratitud va, en primer lugar, al Cardenal Don Gil Álvarez de Albornoz, fundador del Real Colegio de España, a cuya generosidad y previsión debo dos años provechosos y felices en Bolonia. Al Rector, José Guillermo García-Valdecasas, que administra la herencia de Albornoz con ejemplar dedicación, eficacia y amor a la casa. A todas las personas que trabajan en el Colegio y hacen que cumpla con creces los objetivos para los que se fundó. Y a mis compañeros bolonios durante estos dos años. Ha sido un honor muy grato disfrutar con todos ellos de la herencia albornociana.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
    The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678).
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 4-12-2006 Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Neste, Berit Van, "Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea" (2006). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3782 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea by Berit Van Neste A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Religious Studies College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: James F. Strange, Ph.D. Paul G. Schneider, Ph.D. Michael J. Decker, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 12, 2006 Keywords: theology, philosophy, politics, patristic, medieval © Copyright 2006 , Berit Van Neste For Elizabeth and Calista Table of Contents Abstract ii Chapter 1 1 Introduction 1 Cicero’s Influence on Augustine 7 Chapter 2 13 Justice 13 Natural and Temporal Law 19 Commonwealth 34 Chapter 3 49 Just War 49 Chapter 4 60 Conclusion 60 References 64 i Cicero and St.
    [Show full text]
  • Machiavelli's Critique of Classical Philosophy and His Case for The
    Perspectives on Political Science ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/vpps20 Machiavelli’s Critique of Classical Philosophy and His Case for The Political Life Rasoul Namazi To cite this article: Rasoul Namazi (2021): Machiavelli’s Critique of Classical Philosophy and His Case for The Political Life, Perspectives on Political Science, DOI: 10.1080/10457097.2021.1894057 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2021.1894057 Published online: 19 Mar 2021. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=vpps20 PERSPECTIVES ON POLITICAL SCIENCE https://doi.org/10.1080/10457097.2021.1894057 Machiavelli’s Critique of Classical Philosophy and His Case for The Political Life Rasoul Namazi Division of Social Sciences, Duke Kunshan University, Suzhou, China ABSTRACT This article illuminates how Machiavelli’s critique of classical philosophy is fundamental to his teaching. It will argue that Machiavelli criticized classical philosophy for its ineffective- ness and its endorsement of the leisurely philosophic life as the best way of life. In contrast, Machiavelli’s optimistic depiction of the scope of human power in controlling chance and his critique of the life of contemplation promote his new understanding of the best life, in which political life and its glory occupy the highest rank. I will then contend that in Machiavelli’s writings there is a coherent and powerful defense of the political life as the alternative for the philosophical life of contemplation. Although Niccolo Machiavelli is commonly studied as work on Cyrus the Great (P XVI.60; D II.2.130, a major political philosopher, the idea that he is a II.13.155, III.20.262, III.22.266, III.22.267, III.39.298, philosopher simply or even has something to say III.39.298).
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine of Hippo City of God Pdf
    Augustine of hippo city of god pdf Continue Early Catholic theologian, philosopher, church father, bishop and Christian Saint Augustine, St. Augustine and Augustine are redirected here. For other uses, see Augustine (disambigation), St. Augustine (disambigation) and Augustine (disambigation). SaintAugustine of HippoBishop Hippo Regius Triumph of St. Augustine written by Claudio Coello, about. 1664Bishop and The Church DoctorBorn13 AD 354 AD, Numidia Tsirtensis, Western Roman Empire (modern Suk Ahras, Algeria)Died28 August 430 AD (age 75)Hippo Regis, Numidia Tsirtensis, Western Roman Empire (modern Annaba, Algeria) Resting PlacePavia, ItalyBased in All Christian denominations that revere the saintsCunianized PrecticaMajor shrineSan Pietro in Ciel d'Oro, Pavia, Italy 28 August (Latin church, Western Christianity)15 June (Eastern Christianity)4 November (Assyrian)AttributesChildDovePenEGeShell , Printers, Theologians, Eye PainBridgeport, Connecticut, Cagayan de Ano, Philippines, San Agustin, Isabella, Mendes, Cavita, Tanza, Cavite Augustine HippoPortite St. Augustine Hippo receiving the most sacred heart of Jesus, Philippe de Champaign, c. 17th CenturyBornAurelius AugustinusNationalityRoman AfricanNage workConfe Christian DoctrineOn TrinityCity GodEraAncient PhilosophyMediaregionWestern PhilosophyThe West PhilosophySchool AugustinianIsm Famous StudentsPaul Orosius (Basic Interests Anthropology Biblical Criticism Epistemology Ethics Metaphysics Pedagogy Philosophy of Religion Theology Theology Famous Ideas Filioque Theory of War No Good 2
    [Show full text]
  • Iamblichus and Julian''s ''Third Demiurge'': a Proposition
    Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf To cite this version: Adrien Lecerf. Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition . Eugene Afonasin; John M. Dillon; John F. Finamore. Iamblichus and the Foundations of Late Platonism, 13, BRILL, p. 177-201, 2012, Ancient Mediterranean and Medieval Texts and Contexts. Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition, 10.1163/9789004230118_012. hal-02931399 HAL Id: hal-02931399 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02931399 Submitted on 6 Sep 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Iamblichus and Julian‟s “Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris, France [email protected] ABSTRACT. In the Emperor Julian's Oration To the Mother of the Gods, a philosophical interpretation of the myth of Cybele and Attis, reference is made to an enigmatic "third Demiurge". Contrary to a common opinion identifying him to the visible Helios (the Sun), or to tempting identifications to Amelius' and Theodorus of Asine's three Demiurges, I suggest that a better idea would be to compare Julian's text to Proclus' system of Demiurges (as exposed and explained in a Jan Opsomer article, "La démiurgie des jeunes dieux selon Proclus", Les Etudes Classiques, 71, 2003, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant
    On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant Myriam Renaud I. Why Moral Duties? Aren‟t We Done With That Conversation? For the purposes of this paper, I will rely on the following definition of moral duty (or obligation): an action which is required (imperative) and which is guided by certain moral rules and principles. In every day language, we capture the concept of duty or obligation when we say things like, “I should [or „ought‟] to do this because it‟s the right thing to do,” or “I want to do right by so and so.” These ordinary expressions reflect the view that awareness of the rightness of an action may be enough to provide the impetus to carry through that action—namely, that “in acting from a motive attached to a moral principle,”—in acting on what we take to be the right thing to do—“the moral rightness of the action gives the agent reason for action” [Herman, 30]. Admittedly, the word alone—duty—is likely to cause unpleasant shivers to course down the spines of most Unitarian Universalists. It brings to mind something we have to do, something we‟d rather not do, something we‟re made to do, probably at the expense of some activity we would actually enjoy. But, if we push past the unpleasant shiver, we recognize that duty, or obligation, is tied to the moral structure which governs our lives and which we try to impart to our children both at home and in the religious education classes offered in our congregations.
    [Show full text]
  • Spiritualism: a Source of Prevention from Fatal Pandemic (A General Estimate) Dr
    International Journal of English Literature and Social Sciences, 5(3) May-Jun 2020 |Available online: https://ijels.com/ Spiritualism: A Source of Prevention from Fatal Pandemic (A General Estimate) Dr. Vanshree Godbole Associate Professor, English, Govt. M. L. B. Girl’s P. G. College, Indore, M.P., India Abstract— Spiritualismis a life Spring of Indian Philosophy, Culture and Religion.Philosophy shows the cause for the inescapable experiences of sorrow and suffering that has engulfed mankind today. The period following the outbreak of fatal pandemic Covid -19 has become the age of disillusionment, chaos, disbelief , utter despair, loss, and disorder in an individual’s life. Hinduism is the only religion that is universal, It is a revealed religion, the priceless truth discovered by intuitive spiritual experiences. Need of the hour is to understand the psychology of commonman, his social condition and to help them regain confidence that has shaken the whole human race. Keywords— Spiritualism, disillusionment, fatal, despair, confidence. Spiritualism is a life Spring of Indian Philosophy, Culture The unrest of the age and passion for reform and solution and Religion “Every human being is a potential spirit and to the present day up- rootedness of human race can be represents, as has been well said, ahope of GOD and is not traced in Indian Philosophical system, that includes whole mere fortuitous concourse of episodes like the changing of mankind from all walks of life whether cultured, forms of clouds or patterns of a kalideoscope.”(1) As we ignorant or learned. To quote Dr.Radhakrishnn “Religion know that the literature is replete with the writings of Men, from the beginning, is the bearer of human culture.
    [Show full text]