Binary Relations on the Power Set of an N-Element Set

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Binary Relations on the Power Set of an N-Element Set 1 2 Journal of Integer Sequences, Vol. 12 (2009), 3 Article 09.2.6 47 6 23 11 Binary Relations on the Power Set of an n-Element Set Ross La Haye 955 Coppens Road Green Bay, WI 54303 USA [email protected] Abstract We define six binary relations on the power set of an n-element set and describe their basic structure and interrelationships. An auxiliary relation is noted that will assist in determining the cardinalities of each. We also indicate an eighth relation that may be of interest. We conclude the second section by computing several quantities related to walks in the graph of the sixth relation. In the third section we turn our attention to the basic structure and cardinalities of the auxiliary relation noted in section two and several additional relations. We also compute seven sums associated with these relations and indicate connections four relations have with Wieder’s conjoint and disjoint k-combinations. 1 Introduction Combinatorial interest has generally focused on the enumeration of various types of relations or associated structures such as topologies and graphs. In this paper we will be interested in the generally more tractable problem of defining and enumerating several binary relations on the power set of an n-element set and computing various quantities associated with them. We will conclude by indicating connections four relations have with Wieder’s conjoint and disjoint k-combinations. The motivation here is to suggest some ways in which sets of k- subsets of some set may be studied under the rubric of asymmetric k-ary relations on the same. To the author’s knowledge, the results of this paper or related results do not appear in the existing literature, except when so noted. 1 2 The six initial relations 2.1 Definitions and structure Let P (A) be the power set of an n-element set A1. Then B = P (A) × P (A) is just the Cartesian product of P (A) with itself and the following binary relations on P (A) are, of course, just subsets of B: R0 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ⊆ y ∨ y ⊆ x}, R1 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ⊂ y ∨ y ⊂ x}, R2 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ≺ y ∨ y ≺ x}, R3 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ⊆ y}, R4 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ⊂ y}, and R5 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x ≺ y}. Note that x ≺ y denotes that x ⊂ y and |y|−|x| =1[2]. As R3 has been defined to be a partial order relation on P (A), this just means that R5 is the corresponding covering relation [2]. R4 is the corresponding strict order [2]. Also, observe that B is a reflexive, symmetric, and transitive relation on P (A) and so is an equivalence relation on the same. R0 R1 R2 R3 R4 R5 reflexive yes no no yes no no irreflexive no yes yes no yes yes symmetric yes yes yes no no no asymmetric no no no no yes yes antisymmetric no no no yes yes yes transitive no no no yes yes no intransitive no no yes no no yes Table 1: Basic properties of R0 – R5 Tables 1, 2, and 3 list some basic information with regard to R0 – R5. While entries =, ⊆, and ⊇ in Table 3 are easily enough understood, we explain an entry of ∩ as follows. Given a row relation Rr and a column relation Rc in Table 3, an entry of ∩ indicates that, while Rr 6⊆ Rc and Rc 6⊆ Rr, we still have that Rr ∩ Rc =6 ∅. Examples. With A = {1, 2}, P (A)= {∅, {1} , {2} , {1, 2}}, and R4 = {(∅, {1}), (∅, {2}), (∅, {1, 2}), ({1} , {1, 2}), ({2} , {1, 2})}, R5 = {(∅, {1}), (∅, {2}), ({1} , {1, 2}), ({2} , {1, 2})}. 1For convenience we may assume that A = {1, 2, 3,...,n}. 2 R0 R1 R2 R3 R4 R5 reflexive closure R0 R3 reflexive reduction R1 R4 symmetric closure R0 R1 R2 symmetric reduction R3 R4 R5 transitive closure R4 transitive reduction R5 Table 2: Closures and reductions of R0 – R5 R0 R1 R2 R3 R4 R5 R0 = ⊇⊇⊇⊇⊇ R1 ⊆ = ⊇ ∩ ⊇ ⊇ R2 ⊆ ⊆ = ∩ ∩ ⊇ R3 ⊆ ∩ ∩ = ⊇ ⊇ R4 ⊆ ⊆ ∩ ⊆ = ⊇ R5 ⊆⊆⊆⊆⊆ = Table 3: Inclusion and intersection relationships, R0 – R5 Define the partial order relation E = {(p,q): p,q ∈ {R0,R1,...,R5} ,p ⊆ q} so that G may be defined to be the (directed) graph of the covering relation corresponding to E. Then most of the information in Tables 1, 2, and 3 is illustrated in Figure 1. Observe that we have labelled the edges of G in the diagram to indicate the closure and reduction relationships that obtain between the vertices of this graph, i.e., R0,R1 etc. For example, an edge labelled s and directed from vertex u to vertex v indicates that u is the symmetric reduction of v (and v the symmetric closure of u); we can also deduce from this that v is a symmetric relation. Similar observations hold for the other two edge labels. Finally, note that if a walk exists from u to v, then u ⊆ v. However, if there is neither a walk from u to v nor a walk from v to u, then, while u 6⊆ v and v 6⊆ u, it is still the case that u ∩ v =6 ∅. R 0 B ||> ` BB s || BB || r BB || B R R 3 B 1 B ` BB ||> ` BB BB s || BB r BB || BB B || B R R 4 B 2 ` BB ||> BB s || t BB || B || R5 Figure 1: Hasse diagram of G 3 2.2 The cardinalities of R0 – R5 In determining the cardinalities of R0 – R5 it will be useful to recall [1] that |P (A)| =2n. (1) To see this, consider that in enumerating a subset of A, i.e., an element of P (A), we decide on a case by case basis which elements of A to include in the subset. As there are 2 outcomes possible for each of the elements of A – include in the subset or exclude from the subset – and n elements of A, there are 2n subsets of A altogether. Now recall that the (x,y) ∈ R3 are such that x ⊆ y. It is not hard to see that enumerating each subset of each subset of A will enumerate the elements of R3. We may do so by deciding on a case by case basis which elements of A to 1. include in both x and y, 2. exclude from both x and y, or 3. exclude from x and include in y. As there are 3 outcomes possible for each of the n elements of A, we see that n |R3| =3 . (2) −1 The cardinalities of R0, R1, and R4 are determined as follows. Let Ri denote the inverse relation of Ri [3]. Then, define R11 = {(x,y): x,y ∈ P (A),x = y} = {(x,x): x ∈ P (A)}. It should be clear that R11 ⊂ R3. Moreover, it is obvious that n |R11| =2 . (3) It then follows that n n |R0| =2 · 3 − 2 , (4) −1 as, by definition, R0 = R3 ∪ R3 , and R11 should only be counted once in this union. Similarly, we see that n n |R4| =3 − 2 , (5) as, by definition, R4 = R3 \ R11. Furthermore, n n |R1| =2 · (3 − 2 ), (6) −1 as, by definition, R1 = R4 ∪ R4 . Recall that for each (x,y) ∈ R5, we have that x ⊂ y and |y|−|x| = 1. This suggests the following enumeration of this relation. First, select one of the n elements of A to add to x (to get y). Then x is constructed from the remaining elements of A, and this can be done in 2n−1 ways. As y is now completely determined, we have that n−1 |R5| = n · 2 . (7) 4 It is then easy to see that n |R2| = n · 2 , (8) −1 as, by definition, R2 = R5 ∪ R5 . Before concluding here we note one additional relation that may be of interest: R6 = R4 \ R5. R6 is an irreflexive, asymmetric, antisymmetric, and transitive relation and so a strict order. We also note that this relation is a proper subset of R0, R1, R3, and R4. Finally, that n n n−1 |R6| =3 − 2 − n · 2 (9) is easily deduced from Eqns. (5) and (7). Relation Cardinality Sequence Sequence Sequence n n R0 2 · 3 − 2 A027649(n) A090888(n, 3) n n R1 2 · (3 − 2 ) A056182(n) n R2 n · 2 A036289(n) n R3 3 A000244(n) A090888(n, 2) A112626(n, 0) n n R4 3 − 2 A001047(n) A090888(n, 1) A112626(n, 1) n−1 R5 n · 2 A001787(n) A090802(n, 1) n n n−1 R6 3 − 2 − n · 2 A066810(n) A112626(n, 2) Table 4: The cardinalities of R0 – R6 Table 4 lists the cardinalities of R0 – R6 with references to the corresponding integer sequences in Sloane’s Encyclopedia [5]. 2.3 Walks and lengths of walks in the graph of R5 Let H be the (directed) graph of R5 and recall that P (A) is the power set of an n-element set A. Also, let C(n, k) denote the binomial coefficient, i.e., the number of ways to select k elements from an n-element set. We begin by counting the number of k-length walks w(n, k) in H [3]. As the vertices of H are just elements of P (A), a little thought shows that a k-length walk in H begins at some x ∈ P (A) and adds k elements of A not in x to x, where the order of addition is important.
Recommended publications
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • A Proof of Cantor's Theorem
    Cantor’s Theorem Joe Roussos 1 Preliminary ideas Two sets have the same number of elements (are equinumerous, or have the same cardinality) iff there is a bijection between the two sets. Mappings: A mapping, or function, is a rule that associates elements of one set with elements of another set. We write this f : X ! Y , f is called the function/mapping, the set X is called the domain, and Y is called the codomain. We specify what the rule is by writing f(x) = y or f : x 7! y. e.g. X = f1; 2; 3g;Y = f2; 4; 6g, the map f(x) = 2x associates each element x 2 X with the element in Y that is double it. A bijection is a mapping that is injective and surjective.1 • Injective (one-to-one): A function is injective if it takes each element of the do- main onto at most one element of the codomain. It never maps more than one element in the domain onto the same element in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is injective iff 8a; b 2 X; f(a) = f(b) ! a = b • Surjective (onto): A function is surjective if it maps something onto every element of the codomain. It can map more than one thing onto the same element in the codomain, but it needs to hit everything in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is surjective iff 8y 2 Y; 9x 2 X; f(x) = y Figure 1: Injective map.
    [Show full text]
  • Power Sets Math 12, Veritas Prep
    Power Sets Math 12, Veritas Prep. The power set P (X) of a set X is the set of all subsets of X. Defined formally, P (X) = fK j K ⊆ Xg (i.e., the set of all K such that K is a subset of X). Let me give an example. Suppose it's Thursday night, and I want to go to a movie. And suppose that I know that each of the upper-campus Latin teachers|Sullivan, Joyner, and Pagani|are free that night. So I consider asking one of them if they want to join me. Conceivably, then: • I could go to the movie by myself (i.e., I could bring along none of the Latin faculty) • I could go to the movie with Sullivan • I could go to the movie with Joyner • I could go to the movie with Pagani • I could go to the movie with Sullivan and Joyner • I could go to the movie with Sullivan and Pagani • I could go to the movie with Pagani and Joyner • or I could go to the movie with all three of them Put differently, my choices for whom to go to the movie with make up the following set: fg; fSullivang; fJoynerg; fPaganig; fSullivan, Joynerg; fSullivan, Paganig; fPagani, Joynerg; fSullivan, Joyner, Paganig Or if I use my notation for the empty set: ;; fSullivang; fJoynerg; fPaganig; fSullivan, Joynerg; fSullivan, Paganig; fPagani, Joynerg; fSullivan, Joyner, Paganig This set|the set of whom I might bring to the movie|is the power set of the set of Latin faculty. It is the set of all the possible subsets of the set of Latin faculty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND ITS IMPLICATIONS KEVIN BARNUM Abstract. In this paper we will look at the Axiom of Choice and some of the various implications it has. These implications include a number of equivalent statements, and also some less accepted ideas. The proofs discussed will give us an idea of why the Axiom of Choice is so powerful, but also so controversial. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. The Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents 1 2.1. The Axiom of Choice and its Well-known Equivalents 1 2.2. Some Other Less Well-known Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice 3 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice 5 3.1. Equivalence Between The Axiom of Choice and the Claim that Every Vector Space has a Basis 5 3.2. Some More Applications of the Axiom of Choice 6 4. Controversial Results 10 Acknowledgments 11 References 11 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice states that for any family of nonempty disjoint sets, there exists a set that consists of exactly one element from each element of the family. It seems strange at first that such an innocuous sounding idea can be so powerful and controversial, but it certainly is both. To understand why, we will start by looking at some statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Many of these equivalences are very useful, and we devote much time to one, namely, that every vector space has a basis. We go on from there to see a few more applications of the Axiom of Choice and its equivalents, and finish by looking at some of the reasons why the Axiom of Choice is so controversial.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is the Theory Zfc Without Power Set?
    WHAT IS THE THEORY ZFC WITHOUT POWER SET? VICTORIA GITMAN, JOEL DAVID HAMKINS, AND THOMAS A. JOHNSTONE Abstract. We show that the theory ZFC-, consisting of the usual axioms of ZFC but with the power set axiom removed|specifically axiomatized by ex- tensionality, foundation, pairing, union, infinity, separation, replacement and the assertion that every set can be well-ordered|is weaker than commonly supposed and is inadequate to establish several basic facts often desired in its context. For example, there are models of ZFC- in which !1 is singular, in which every set of reals is countable, yet !1 exists, in which there are sets of reals of every size @n, but none of size @!, and therefore, in which the col- lection axiom fails; there are models of ZFC- for which theLo´stheorem fails, even when the ultrapower is well-founded and the measure exists inside the model; there are models of ZFC- for which the Gaifman theorem fails, in that there is an embedding j : M ! N of ZFC- models that is Σ1-elementary and cofinal, but not elementary; there are elementary embeddings j : M ! N of ZFC- models whose cofinal restriction j : M ! S j " M is not elementary. Moreover, the collection of formulas that are provably equivalent in ZFC- to a Σ1-formula or a Π1-formula is not closed under bounded quantification. Nev- ertheless, these deficits of ZFC- are completely repaired by strengthening it to the theory ZFC−, obtained by using collection rather than replacement in the axiomatization above. These results extend prior work of Zarach [Zar96].
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected]
    Boise State University ScholarWorks Mathematics Undergraduate Theses Department of Mathematics 5-2014 Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.boisestate.edu/ math_undergraduate_theses Part of the Set Theory Commons Recommended Citation Rahim, Farighon Abdul, "Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice" (2014). Mathematics Undergraduate Theses. Paper 1. Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Advisor: Samuel Coskey Boise State University May 2014 1 Introduction Sets are all around us. A bag of potato chips, for instance, is a set containing certain number of individual chip’s that are its elements. University is another example of a set with students as its elements. By elements, we mean members. But sets should not be confused as to what they really are. A daughter of a blacksmith is an element of a set that contains her mother, father, and her siblings. Then this set is an element of a set that contains all the other families that live in the nearby town. So a set itself can be an element of a bigger set. In mathematics, axiom is defined to be a rule or a statement that is accepted to be true regardless of having to prove it. In a sense, axioms are self evident. In set theory, we deal with sets. Each time we state an axiom, we will do so by considering sets. Example of the set containing the blacksmith family might make it seem as if sets are finite.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 310 Class Notes 1: Axioms of Set Theory
    MATH 310 CLASS NOTES 1: AXIOMS OF SET THEORY Intuitively, we think of a set as an organization and an element be- longing to a set as a member of the organization. Accordingly, it also seems intuitively clear that (1) when we collect all objects of a certain kind the collection forms an organization, i.e., forms a set, and, moreover, (2) it is natural that when we collect members of a certain kind of an organization, the collection is a sub-organization, i.e., a subset. Item (1) above was challenged by Bertrand Russell in 1901 if we accept the natural item (2), i.e., we must be careful when we use the word \all": (Russell Paradox) The collection of all sets is not a set! Proof. Suppose the collection of all sets is a set S. Consider the subset U of S that consists of all sets x with the property that each x does not belong to x itself. Now since U is a set, U belongs to S. Let us ask whether U belongs to U itself. Since U is the collection of all sets each of which does not belong to itself, thus if U belongs to U, then as an element of the set U we must have that U does not belong to U itself, a contradiction. So, it must be that U does not belong to U. But then U belongs to U itself by the very definition of U, another contradiction. The absurdity results because we assume S is a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Set (Mathematics) from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Set (mathematics) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia A set in mathematics is a collection of well defined and distinct objects, considered as an object in its own right. Sets are one of the most fundamental concepts in mathematics. Developed at the end of the 19th century, set theory is now a ubiquitous part of mathematics, and can be used as a foundation from which nearly all of mathematics can be derived. In mathematics education, elementary topics such as Venn diagrams are taught at a young age, while more advanced concepts are taught as part of a university degree. Contents The intersection of two sets is made up of the objects contained in 1 Definition both sets, shown in a Venn 2 Describing sets diagram. 3 Membership 3.1 Subsets 3.2 Power sets 4 Cardinality 5 Special sets 6 Basic operations 6.1 Unions 6.2 Intersections 6.3 Complements 6.4 Cartesian product 7 Applications 8 Axiomatic set theory 9 Principle of inclusion and exclusion 10 See also 11 Notes 12 References 13 External links Definition A set is a well defined collection of objects. Georg Cantor, the founder of set theory, gave the following definition of a set at the beginning of his Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre:[1] A set is a gathering together into a whole of definite, distinct objects of our perception [Anschauung] and of our thought – which are called elements of the set. The elements or members of a set can be anything: numbers, people, letters of the alphabet, other sets, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Sections 1.3 and 1.4: Subsets and Power Sets
    Sections 1.3 and 1.4: Subsets and power sets Definition The set A is a subset of the set B if every element of A is an element of B, and this is denoted by writing A ⊆ B. Otherwise, if A contains an element that is not in B, then A is not a subset of B, and we write A 6⊆ B. Definition The set A is a subset of the set B if every element of A is an element of B, and this is denoted by writing A ⊆ B. Otherwise, if A contains an element that is not in B, then A is not a subset of B, and we write A 6⊆ B. Examples: 1 f2; 1g ⊆ f1; 2g 2 f2; 1g ⊆ f1; 2; 4g 3 f2; 1g 6⊆ ff1; 2g; 4g 4 N ⊆ Z ⊆ Q ⊆ R Theorem For any set A, we have ? ⊆ A. Theorem For any set A, we have ? ⊆ A. Definition The set A is a subset of the set B if every element of A is an element of B, and this is denoted by writing A ⊆ B. Otherwise, if A contains an element that is not in B, then A is not a subset of B, and we write A 6⊆ B. Theorem For any set A, we have ? ⊆ A. Definition The set A is a subset of the set B if every element of A is an element of B, and this is denoted by writing A ⊆ B. Otherwise, if A contains an element that is not in B, then A is not a subset of B, and we write A 6⊆ B.
    [Show full text]
  • On Cantor's Theorem
    On Cantor's Theorem W. Mückenheim University of Applied Sciences, Baumgartnerstraße 16, D-86161 Augsburg, Germany [email protected] ________________________________________________________ Abstract. The famous contradiction of a bijection between a set and its power set is a consequence of the impredicative definition involved. This is shown by the fact that a simple mapping between equivalent sets does also fail to satisfy the critical requirement. 1. Introduction There is no surjection of the set Ù of all natural numbers on its power set P(Ù). This proof was first given by Hessenberg [1]. Though Zermelo [2], calling it Cantor's theorem, attributed it to Cantor [3] himself, Cantor's most famous paper [3] does not contain the notion power set (Potenzmenge) at all. But the expression "Cantor's theorem" has become generally accepted. If there was a surjective mapping of Ù on its power set, s: Ù Ø P(Ù), then some natural numbers n œ Ù might be mapped on subsets s(n) not containing n. Call these numbers n "non-generators" to have a convenient abbreviation. The subset M of all non-generators M = {n œ Ù | n – s(n)} belongs to P(Ù) as an element, whether containing numbers or being empty. But there is no m œ Ù available to be mapped on M. If m is not in M, then m is a non-generator, but then M must contain m and vice versa: m œ M fl m – M fl m œ M fl ... This condition, however, has nothing to do with the cardinal numbers of Ù and P(Ù) but it is simply a paradox request: m has to be mapped by s on a set which does not contain it, if it contains it.
    [Show full text]
  • Basics of Set Theory
    2.2. THE BASICS OF SET THEORY In this section we explain the importance of set theory and introduce its basic concepts and definitions. We also show the notation with sets that has become standard throughout mathematics. The Importance of Set Theory One striking feature of humans is their inherent propensity, and ability, to group objects according to specific criteria. Our prehistoric ancestors were hunter-gatherers who grouped tools based on their survival needs. They eventually settled and formed strict hierarchical societies where a person belonged to one class and not another. Today, many of us like to sort our clothes at home or group the songs on our computer into playlists. As we look at the accomplishments of science at the dawn of this new millennium, we can point to many impressive classifications. In chemistry there is Mendeleev’s periodic table, which lists all the known chemical elements in our universe and groups them based on common structural characteristics (alkaline metals, noble gases, etc.) In biology there is now a vast taxonomy that systematically sorts all living organisms into specific hierarchies: kingdoms, orders, phyla, genera, etc. In physics, all the subatomic particles and the four fundamental forces of nature have now been classified under an incredibly complex and refined theory called the Standard Model. This model – the most accurate scientific theory ever devised – surely ranks as one of mankind’s greatest achievements. The idea of sorting out certain objects into similar groupings, or sets, is the most fundamental concept in modern mathematics. The theory of sets has, in fact, been the unifying framework for all mathematics since the German mathematician Georg Cantor formulated it in the 1870’s.
    [Show full text]