A METRIZATION for POWER-SETS and CARTESIAN PRODUCTS TOTH APPLICATIONS to COMBINATORIAL ANALYSIS DISSERTATION Presented in Partia

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A METRIZATION for POWER-SETS and CARTESIAN PRODUCTS TOTH APPLICATIONS to COMBINATORIAL ANALYSIS DISSERTATION Presented in Partia A METRIZATION FOR POWER-SETS AND CARTESIAN PRODUCTS TOTH APPLICATIONS TO COMBINATORIAL ANALYSIS DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University ROBERT SILVERMAN, B. Sc., M. A. ****** The Ohio .State University 1958 Approved by Adviser Department of Mathematics Acknowledgements ®he author wishes to express his sincere appreciation to Professors Marshall Hall, Jr. and Henry 5. Mann for their reading of the dissertation and their suggestions, and especially to his adviser, Professor D. Hansom Whitney, to Professor Herbert J. Terser, and to his wife, Donna, for their continued encouragement and assistance. ii Contents Section Page 1. Introduction ..................................... 1 2. Abstract metric spaces ........................ 1 3. A metrization for power-sets and Cartesian products .• U U> The metric space 5^(n) ........ 5 5. Metric characterizations of some classical configurations and their generalizations ........... 6 6. Some theorems for the metric space S^(n) ........... 18 7. Future research .......................... 31 Bibliography......................... 33 Autobiography......................................... 35 iii 1. Introduction. Virtually every combinatorial configuration may be phrased in terns of certain conditions on families of subclasses of the power-set Ug (the class of all subsets of S) of some abstract set S. In view of this, it would seem worthwhile to investigate systematically some aspects of the behavior of Ug. In this paper a method of structuring the power-set is proposed /by defining a distance function over Ug. Since Cartesian products may be viewed as subsets of power-sets, this definition also leads to a metrization for such sets. The present paper is concerned primarily with an examination of some of the metric properties of Cartesian products and their relation to some of the classical configurations and their generalizations. 2. Abstract metric spaces. In order to reduce to a minimum the introduction of new terminology, wherever feasible the author has adopted that used by ELumenthal [Ul [f>l, whose excellent books also nourished several interesting trains of thought. DEFINITION 1. Given a set M, an r-dimensional metric over M, r > 2, is a mapping which associates with every ordered r-tuple a]_,a2, ...,ar of elements of M, a non-negative real number d(a^,...,ar), termed the distance of the points a^, ...,ar, satisfying: M l . d( a^,..., &p) > 0.* M 2. d(a-j_, ...,ar) = 0 if and only if a-^ = a2 s ... = ar. 1 2 M 3 . (Symmetry) If • • .>ir is any permutation of the integers 1,2,..., r, then d( ap ..., ar) = d(a^, . a ^ ) . M U« (Triangle inequality) For every set of r + 1 points ) «• •» aj. + ]_ of M, d(a^ *«• >ar) < ? d(a^, ...,a^ _ + ^>..»,ar + ^)» The postulate M 2 differs somewhat from that in ELumenthal [U, P* 126], but is more suitable to our purposes. Also, in keeping with the progressive spirit of the times, our "dimension” is one higher than the comparable "dimension” in ELumenthal. In the applications there frequently will be metrics of various dimensions defined over M with connecting conditions. Generally we will use the symbol M to denote either the set M, or the metric space consisting of M and the metric d over M. Wien it is desirable to differentiate explicitly the two concepts, we will symbolize the latter by (M,d). We now define some concepts for conventional (two-dimensional) metric spaces. In most instances the extension to r-dimensional spaces is obvious. In the following, M denotes a metric space, and E a subspace of M. DEFINITION 2. If M ■ £a-^,a2, ...j is countable, it may be completely specified by the symmetric distance matrix A - (ai;j)> ai;j ■ d(a±,a3). 3 DEFINITION 3. For a in M, r > 0, the open sphere aid closed sphere with center a, radius r are defined, respectively, by Note that in general a sphere need not have a unique center or radius. DEFINITION li. The major diameter A(E), of E, and the minor diameter /( E), of E are defined by A(E) ■ l.u.b. d(x,y) for x,y in E, /(E) = g.l.b. d(x,y) for x,y in E, x y. If E contains fewer than two points, define /(E) = 0. DEFINITION E>. The t-extent of E, e(E,t), is the greatest integer m such that E contains m distinct points with minor diameter greater than t. If no two points of E have distance greater than t, set e(E,t) * 1, while if for n arbitrarily large there are n points of E with minor diameter exceeding t, define e(E,t) = + °o. DEFINITION 6. Two metric spaces M and M' are isometric provided there exists a mapping a from M onto M' such that d(x,y) » d(a(x),a(y)) for all x,y in M. We write M * M'. Note that a is biunique since a(x) ■ a(y) implies d(a(x),a(y)) * d(x,y) “ 0. If M = M', the isometry is termed a motion. Two subsets of M are superimposable provided a motion exists that maps one onto the other. u DEFINITION 7. E is a metric basis of M provided each point of M is uniquely deteimined by its distances from the points of E. The basis is irreducible provided no proper subset of E is a metric basis, and is minimal provided M has no metiic basis of smaller cardinality. Finally, the basis is complete provided for each subset E' of M with E “ E', and each subset T' of M containing E", a subset T of M exists such that the isametxy of E with E' can be extended to T S T'. The extension is obviously unique. Also, note that for M finite, for completeness it is sufficient to require simply that E and E' be superimposable for each subset E' of M with E ~ E'. DEFINITION 8. For x in M, the distance of x from E is given ty d(x,E) » g.l.b. d(x,y) for y in E. 3. A metrization for power-sets and Cartesian products. Given a set S, let Ug denote its power set. For A in Ug, let N(A) be the number of elements in A, where + ®o is an admissible value. For A^, •••,Ar in Ug define: DEFINITION 9. d(A!,...,Ar) - N(\JA± - A A i ) / r . THEOREM 1. Under the above definition, d is an r-dimensional metric over Ug. Proof. M 1, M 2, M 3 are immediate. Let A^,...,Aj, + be in Ug, Let a L ° d(A]_, ...,Aj.), R ** 2 d(A]_, .• Aj_ «• i>Aj_ + x* • ••jAp + x^* <■'=/ 5 If R = + «o , then certainly L < R, so we may assume R < + oo . Let x be arbitrary in S. Then x can contribute 0 to R if and only if x is either in all of the r + 1sets or innone. In either case it also contributes 0 to L. In all other cases x contributes at least l/r to R and at most l/r to L. Hence L < R. Thus M U is satisfied. In particular, definition 9 defines an r-dimensional metric for Cartesian products as follows: Given the sets S , ...,,S , X Jx denote by n Si ° Si x S 2 x ... x Sjj ■ ^(s^, ...,sk)» s^ in their Cartesian product of ordered k-tuples. Then it may be regarded as a subclass of Ug(k ) x where 2, ...,kj, by regarding the element (a^,. .^a^) of n as the subset |(l,a1),...,(k,ak )j of S(k) x k* ^*1° metric space S^(n). Let S(n) denote a set with n elements, n > 1. Unless otherwise indicated, S(n) will be taken as the first n positive integers. We denote by S^-(n), k > 1, the k-fold Cartesian product of S(n), S ^ n ) - {(x l , ...,xk); X£ in S(n)j, and assume that S^(n) has been metrized as in the preceding section. Although it appears that higher dimensional metrics will be necessary to characterize such items as the theorem of Desargues, in the present paper we confine our attention to the two- dimensional metric, which for this special case we may restate: For x,y in S^n), x - ( x ^ . ^ ) , y - (y-p ...,yk ), d(x,y) is the number of subscripts i for which x^ / y^, i = 1, ...,k. For 0 < r < k, every set of nr + 1 elements of Sk (n) has minor diameter at most k-r. Hence the k-r extent of every subspace E of S^(n) satisfies e(E, k - r) < nr . We next define terms to describe subspaces which attain this maximum extent. DEFINITION 10. A subspace E of S^(n) is r-orthogonal, 0 < r < k, provided e(E, k -r) = nr. If in addition E contains precisely nr elements, E is termed an L(n,k,r) space. (Thus E is r-orthogonal if and only if E contains an L(n,k,r) space.) For a given subspace E, r-orthogonality does not imply (r-1) -orthogonality. S^(n) always has orthogonality 0,1 and k. Indeed, any point constitutes an L(n,k,0) space/ the points (i,i,...,i), i » 1,...,n comprise an L(n,k,l) space, and S^(n) is itself an L(n,k,k) space. For values between 1 and k the property becomes non-trivial, and, as we shall see in the following section, is related to some of the classical unsolved problems in combinatorial analysis.
Recommended publications
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • A Proof of Cantor's Theorem
    Cantor’s Theorem Joe Roussos 1 Preliminary ideas Two sets have the same number of elements (are equinumerous, or have the same cardinality) iff there is a bijection between the two sets. Mappings: A mapping, or function, is a rule that associates elements of one set with elements of another set. We write this f : X ! Y , f is called the function/mapping, the set X is called the domain, and Y is called the codomain. We specify what the rule is by writing f(x) = y or f : x 7! y. e.g. X = f1; 2; 3g;Y = f2; 4; 6g, the map f(x) = 2x associates each element x 2 X with the element in Y that is double it. A bijection is a mapping that is injective and surjective.1 • Injective (one-to-one): A function is injective if it takes each element of the do- main onto at most one element of the codomain. It never maps more than one element in the domain onto the same element in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is injective iff 8a; b 2 X; f(a) = f(b) ! a = b • Surjective (onto): A function is surjective if it maps something onto every element of the codomain. It can map more than one thing onto the same element in the codomain, but it needs to hit everything in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is surjective iff 8y 2 Y; 9x 2 X; f(x) = y Figure 1: Injective map.
    [Show full text]
  • Useful Relations in Permutations and Combination 1. Useful Relations
    Useful Relations in Permutations and Combination 1. Useful Relations - Factorial n! = n.(n-1)! 2. n퐶푟= n푃푟/r! n n-1 3. Pr = n( Pr-1) 4. Useful Relations - Combinations n n 1. Cr = C(n - r) Example 8 8 C6 = C2 = 8×72×1 = 28 n 2. Cn = 1 n 3. C0 = 1 n n n n n 4. C0 + C1 + C2 + ... + Cn = 2 Example 4 4 4 4 4 4 C0 + C1 + C2 + C3+ C4 = (1 + 4 + 6 + 4 + 1) = 16 = 2 n n (n+1) Cr-1 + Cr = Cr (Pascal's Law) n퐶푟 =n/퐶푟−1=n-r+1/r n n If Cx = Cy then either x = y or (n-x) = y. 5. Selection from identical objects: Some Basic Facts The number of selections of r objects out of n identical objects is 1. Total number of selections of zero or more objects from n identical objects is n+1. 6. Permutations of Objects when All Objects are Not Distinct The number of ways in which n things can be arranged taking them all at a time, when st nd 푃1 of the things are exactly alike of 1 type, 푃2 of them are exactly alike of a 2 type, and th 푃푟of them are exactly alike of r type and the rest of all are distinct is n!/ 푃1! 푃2! ... 푃푟! 1 Example: how many ways can you arrange the letters in the word THESE? 5!/2!=120/2=60 Example: how many ways can you arrange the letters in the word REFERENCE? 9!/2!.4!=362880/2*24=7560 7.Circular Permutations: Case 1: when clockwise and anticlockwise arrangements are different Number of circular permutations (arrangements) of n different things is (n-1)! 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Surviving Set Theory: a Pedagogical Game and Cooperative Learning Approach to Undergraduate Post-Tonal Music Theory
    Surviving Set Theory: A Pedagogical Game and Cooperative Learning Approach to Undergraduate Post-Tonal Music Theory DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Angela N. Ripley, M.M. Graduate Program in Music The Ohio State University 2015 Dissertation Committee: David Clampitt, Advisor Anna Gawboy Johanna Devaney Copyright by Angela N. Ripley 2015 Abstract Undergraduate music students often experience a high learning curve when they first encounter pitch-class set theory, an analytical system very different from those they have studied previously. Students sometimes find the abstractions of integer notation and the mathematical orientation of set theory foreign or even frightening (Kleppinger 2010), and the dissonance of the atonal repertoire studied often engenders their resistance (Root 2010). Pedagogical games can help mitigate student resistance and trepidation. Table games like Bingo (Gillespie 2000) and Poker (Gingerich 1991) have been adapted to suit college-level classes in music theory. Familiar television shows provide another source of pedagogical games; for example, Berry (2008; 2015) adapts the show Survivor to frame a unit on theory fundamentals. However, none of these pedagogical games engage pitch- class set theory during a multi-week unit of study. In my dissertation, I adapt the show Survivor to frame a four-week unit on pitch- class set theory (introducing topics ranging from pitch-class sets to twelve-tone rows) during a sophomore-level theory course. As on the show, students of different achievement levels work together in small groups, or “tribes,” to complete worksheets called “challenges”; however, in an important modification to the structure of the show, no students are voted out of their tribes.
    [Show full text]
  • Power Sets Math 12, Veritas Prep
    Power Sets Math 12, Veritas Prep. The power set P (X) of a set X is the set of all subsets of X. Defined formally, P (X) = fK j K ⊆ Xg (i.e., the set of all K such that K is a subset of X). Let me give an example. Suppose it's Thursday night, and I want to go to a movie. And suppose that I know that each of the upper-campus Latin teachers|Sullivan, Joyner, and Pagani|are free that night. So I consider asking one of them if they want to join me. Conceivably, then: • I could go to the movie by myself (i.e., I could bring along none of the Latin faculty) • I could go to the movie with Sullivan • I could go to the movie with Joyner • I could go to the movie with Pagani • I could go to the movie with Sullivan and Joyner • I could go to the movie with Sullivan and Pagani • I could go to the movie with Pagani and Joyner • or I could go to the movie with all three of them Put differently, my choices for whom to go to the movie with make up the following set: fg; fSullivang; fJoynerg; fPaganig; fSullivan, Joynerg; fSullivan, Paganig; fPagani, Joynerg; fSullivan, Joyner, Paganig Or if I use my notation for the empty set: ;; fSullivang; fJoynerg; fPaganig; fSullivan, Joynerg; fSullivan, Paganig; fPagani, Joynerg; fSullivan, Joyner, Paganig This set|the set of whom I might bring to the movie|is the power set of the set of Latin faculty. It is the set of all the possible subsets of the set of Latin faculty.
    [Show full text]
  • Combinatorics
    Combinatorics Problem: How to count without counting. I How do you figure out how many things there are with a certain property without actually enumerating all of them. Sometimes this requires a lot of cleverness and deep mathematical insights. But there are some standard techniques. I That's what we'll be studying. We sometimes use the bijection rule without even realizing it: I count how many people voted are in favor of something by counting the number of hands raised: I I'm hoping that there's a bijection between the people in favor and the hands raised! Bijection Rule The Bijection Rule: If f : A ! B is a bijection, then jAj = jBj. I We used this rule in defining cardinality for infinite sets. I Now we'll focus on finite sets. Bijection Rule The Bijection Rule: If f : A ! B is a bijection, then jAj = jBj. I We used this rule in defining cardinality for infinite sets. I Now we'll focus on finite sets. We sometimes use the bijection rule without even realizing it: I count how many people voted are in favor of something by counting the number of hands raised: I I'm hoping that there's a bijection between the people in favor and the hands raised! Answer: 26 choices for the first letter, 26 for the second, 10 choices for the first number, the second number, and the third number: 262 × 103 = 676; 000 Example 2: A traveling salesman wants to do a tour of all 50 state capitals. How many ways can he do this? Answer: 50 choices for the first place to visit, 49 for the second, .
    [Show full text]
  • Inclusion‒Exclusion Principle
    Inclusionexclusion principle 1 Inclusion–exclusion principle In combinatorics, the inclusion–exclusion principle (also known as the sieve principle) is an equation relating the sizes of two sets and their union. It states that if A and B are two (finite) sets, then The meaning of the statement is that the number of elements in the union of the two sets is the sum of the elements in each set, respectively, minus the number of elements that are in both. Similarly, for three sets A, B and C, This can be seen by counting how many times each region in the figure to the right is included in the right hand side. More generally, for finite sets A , ..., A , one has the identity 1 n This can be compactly written as The name comes from the idea that the principle is based on over-generous inclusion, followed by compensating exclusion. When n > 2 the exclusion of the pairwise intersections is (possibly) too severe, and the correct formula is as shown with alternating signs. This formula is attributed to Abraham de Moivre; it is sometimes also named for Daniel da Silva, Joseph Sylvester or Henri Poincaré. Inclusion–exclusion illustrated for three sets For the case of three sets A, B, C the inclusion–exclusion principle is illustrated in the graphic on the right. Proof Let A denote the union of the sets A , ..., A . To prove the 1 n Each term of the inclusion-exclusion formula inclusion–exclusion principle in general, we first have to verify the gradually corrects the count until finally each identity portion of the Venn Diagram is counted exactly once.
    [Show full text]
  • Pitch-Class Set Theory: an Overture
    Chapter One Pitch-Class Set Theory: An Overture A Tale of Two Continents In the late afternoon of October 24, 1999, about one hundred people were gathered in a large rehearsal room of the Rotterdam Conservatory. They were listening to a discussion between representatives of nine European countries about the teaching of music theory and music analysis. It was the third day of the Fourth European Music Analysis Conference.1 Most participants in the conference (which included a number of music theorists from Canada and the United States) had been looking forward to this session: meetings about the various analytical traditions and pedagogical practices in Europe were rare, and a broad survey of teaching methods was lacking. Most felt a need for information from beyond their country’s borders. This need was reinforced by the mobility of music students and the resulting hodgepodge of nationalities at renowned conservatories and music schools. Moreover, the European systems of higher education were on the threshold of a harmoni- zation operation. Earlier that year, on June 19, the governments of 29 coun- tries had ratifi ed the “Bologna Declaration,” a document that envisaged a unifi ed European area for higher education. Its enforcement added to the urgency of the meeting in Rotterdam. However, this meeting would not be remembered for the unusually broad rep- resentation of nationalities or for its political timeliness. What would be remem- bered was an incident which took place shortly after the audience had been invited to join in the discussion. Somebody had raised a question about classroom analysis of twentieth-century music, a recurring topic among music theory teach- ers: whereas the music of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries lent itself to general analytical methodologies, the extremely diverse repertoire of the twen- tieth century seemed only to invite ad hoc approaches; how could the analysis of 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND ITS IMPLICATIONS KEVIN BARNUM Abstract. In this paper we will look at the Axiom of Choice and some of the various implications it has. These implications include a number of equivalent statements, and also some less accepted ideas. The proofs discussed will give us an idea of why the Axiom of Choice is so powerful, but also so controversial. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. The Axiom of Choice and Its Equivalents 1 2.1. The Axiom of Choice and its Well-known Equivalents 1 2.2. Some Other Less Well-known Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice 3 3. Applications of the Axiom of Choice 5 3.1. Equivalence Between The Axiom of Choice and the Claim that Every Vector Space has a Basis 5 3.2. Some More Applications of the Axiom of Choice 6 4. Controversial Results 10 Acknowledgments 11 References 11 1. Introduction The Axiom of Choice states that for any family of nonempty disjoint sets, there exists a set that consists of exactly one element from each element of the family. It seems strange at first that such an innocuous sounding idea can be so powerful and controversial, but it certainly is both. To understand why, we will start by looking at some statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice. Many of these equivalences are very useful, and we devote much time to one, namely, that every vector space has a basis. We go on from there to see a few more applications of the Axiom of Choice and its equivalents, and finish by looking at some of the reasons why the Axiom of Choice is so controversial.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq
    Saarland University Faculty of Natural Sciences and Technology I Department of Computer Science Masters Thesis Formal Construction of a Set Theory in Coq submitted by Jonas Kaiser on November 23, 2012 Supervisor Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Advisor Dr. Chad E. Brown Reviewers Prof. Dr. Gert Smolka Dr. Chad E. Brown Eidesstattliche Erklarung¨ Ich erklare¨ hiermit an Eides Statt, dass ich die vorliegende Arbeit selbststandig¨ verfasst und keine anderen als die angegebenen Quellen und Hilfsmittel verwendet habe. Statement in Lieu of an Oath I hereby confirm that I have written this thesis on my own and that I have not used any other media or materials than the ones referred to in this thesis. Einverstandniserkl¨ arung¨ Ich bin damit einverstanden, dass meine (bestandene) Arbeit in beiden Versionen in die Bibliothek der Informatik aufgenommen und damit vero¨ffentlicht wird. Declaration of Consent I agree to make both versions of my thesis (with a passing grade) accessible to the public by having them added to the library of the Computer Science Department. Saarbrucken,¨ (Datum/Date) (Unterschrift/Signature) iii Acknowledgements First of all I would like to express my sincerest gratitude towards my advisor, Chad Brown, who supported me throughout this work. His extensive knowledge and insights opened my eyes to the beauty of axiomatic set theory and foundational mathematics. We spent many hours discussing the minute details of the various constructions and he taught me the importance of mathematical rigour. Equally important was the support of my supervisor, Prof. Smolka, who first introduced me to the topic and was there whenever a question arose.
    [Show full text]
  • STRUCTURE ENUMERATION and SAMPLING Chemical Structure Enumeration and Sampling Have Been Studied by Mathematicians, Computer
    STRUCTURE ENUMERATION AND SAMPLING MARKUS MERINGER To appear in Handbook of Chemoinformatics Algorithms Chemical structure enumeration and sampling have been studied by 5 mathematicians, computer scientists and chemists for quite a long time. Given a molecular formula plus, optionally, a list of structural con- straints, the typical questions are: (1) How many isomers exist? (2) Which are they? And, especially if (2) cannot be answered completely: (3) How to get a sample? 10 In this chapter we describe algorithms for solving these problems. The techniques are based on the representation of chemical compounds as molecular graphs (see Chapter 2), i.e. they are mainly applied to constitutional isomers. The major problem is that in silico molecular graphs have to be represented as labeled structures, while in chemical 15 compounds, the atoms are not labeled. The mathematical concept for approaching this problem is to consider orbits of labeled molecular graphs under the operation of the symmetric group. We have to solve the so–called isomorphism problem. According to our introductory questions, we distinguish several dis- 20 ciplines: counting, enumerating and sampling isomers. While counting only delivers the number of isomers, the remaining disciplines refer to constructive methods. Enumeration typically encompasses exhaustive and non–redundant methods, while sampling typically lacks these char- acteristics. However, sampling methods are sometimes better suited to 25 solve real–world problems. There is a wide range of applications where counting, enumeration and sampling techniques are helpful or even essential. Some of these applications are closely linked to other chapters of this book. Counting techniques deliver pure chemical information, they can help to estimate 30 or even determine sizes of chemical databases or compound libraries obtained from combinatorial chemistry.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 7 1 Overview 2 Sequences and Cartesian Products
    COMPSCI 230: Discrete Mathematics for Computer Science February 4, 2019 Lecture 7 Lecturer: Debmalya Panigrahi Scribe: Erin Taylor 1 Overview In this lecture, we introduce sequences and Cartesian products. We also define relations and study their properties. 2 Sequences and Cartesian Products Recall that two fundamental properties of sets are the following: 1. A set does not contain multiple copies of the same element. 2. The order of elements in a set does not matter. For example, if S = f1, 4, 3g then S is also equal to f4, 1, 3g and f1, 1, 3, 4, 3g. If we remove these two properties from a set, the result is known as a sequence. Definition 1. A sequence is an ordered collection of elements where an element may repeat multiple times. An example of a sequence with three elements is (1, 4, 3). This sequence, unlike the statement above for sets, is not equal to (4, 1, 3), nor is it equal to (1, 1, 3, 4, 3). Often the following shorthand notation is used to define a sequence: 1 s = 8i 2 N i 2i Here the sequence (s1, s2, ... ) is formed by plugging i = 1, 2, ... into the expression to find s1, s2, and so on. This sequence is (1/2, 1/4, 1/8, ... ). We now define a new set operator; the result of this operator is a set whose elements are two-element sequences. Definition 2. The Cartesian product of sets A and B, denoted by A × B, is a set defined as follows: A × B = f(a, b) : a 2 A, b 2 Bg.
    [Show full text]