Hilary Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hilary Putnam: Meaning and Reference Meaning and Reference 21 HILARY PUTNAM Unclear as it is, the traditional doctrine that intension. Interestingly, no argument for this the notion "meaning" possesses the extension/ impossibility was ever offered. Probably it intension ambiguity has certain typical conse- reflects the tradition of the ancient and medi- quences. The doctrine that the meaning of a eval philosophers, who assumed that the term is a concept carried the implication that concept corresponding to a term was just a meanings are mental entities. Frege, however, conjunction of predicates, and hence that the rebelled against this "psychologism." Feeling concept corresponding to a term must always that meanings are public property-that the provide a necessary and sufficient condition same meaning can be "grasped" by more than for falling into the extension of the term. For one person and by persons at different philosophers like Carnap, who accepted the times-he identified concepts (and hence "in- verifiability theory of meaning, the concept tensions" or meanings) with abstract entities corresponding to a term provided (in the ideal rather than mental entities. However, "grasp- case, where the term had "complete mean- ing" these abstract entities was still an individ- ing") a criterion for belonging to the extension ual psychological act. None of these philoso- (not just in the sense of "necessary and phers doubted that understanding a word sufficient condition," but in the strong sense (knowing its intension) was just a matter of of way of recognizing whether a given thing being in a certain psychological state (some- falls into the extension or not). So theory of what in the way in which knowing how to meaning came to rest on two unchallenged factor numbers in one's head is just a matter assumptions: of being in a certain very complex psychologi- cal state). (1) That knowing the meaning of a term is Secondly, the timeworn example of the two just a matter of being in a certain terms 'creature with a kidney' and 'creature psychological state (in the sense of with a heart' does show that two terms can "psychological state," in which states of have the same extension and yet differ in memory and belief are "psychological intension. But it was taken to be obvious that states"; no one thought that knowing the reverse is impossible: two terms cannot the meaning of a word was a continu- differ in extension and have the same ous state of consciousness, of course). From The journal of Philosophy, volume 70 (1973), pp. 699-711. Presented in an APA symposium on Reference, December 28, 1973. A very much expanded version of this paper appeared under the title "The Meaning of 'Meaning' " in Language, Mind, and Knowledge, Keith Gunderson, ed. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1975), pp. 131-93. 284 NAMES AND DEMONSTRATIVES 285 (2) That the meaning of a term determines Earth is XYZ, and the Earthian space ship its extension (in the sense that same- will report somewhat as follows. ness of intension entails sameness of extension). "On Twin Earth the word 'water' means XYZ." Symmetrically, if a space ship from Twin I shall argue that these two assumptions are Earth ever visits Earth, then the supposition not jointly satisfied by any notion, let alone at first will be that the word 'water' has the any notion of meaning. The traditional con- same meaning on Twin Earth and on Earth. cept of meaning is a concept which rests on a This supposition will be corrected when it is false theory. discovered that "water" on Earth is H20, and the Twin Earthian space ship will report: ARE MEANINGS IN THE HEAD? "On Earth the word 'water' means H 20." For the purpose of the following science- Note that there is no problem about the fiction examples, we shall suppose that some- extension of the term 'water': the word simply where there is a planet we shall call Twin has two different meanings (as we say); in the Earth. Twin Earth is very much like Earth: in sense in which it is used on Twin Earth, the fact, people on Twin Earth even speak En- sense of waterTE• what we call "water" simply glish. In fact, apart from the differences we isn't water, while in the sense in which it is shall specify in our science-fiction examples, used on Earth, the sense of waterE, what the the reader may suppose that Twin Earth is Twin Earthians call "water" simple isn't wa- exactly like Earth. He may even suppose that ter. The extension of 'water' in the sense of he has a Doppelganger-an identical copy- waterE is the set of all wholes consisting of on Twin Earth, if he wishes, although my H 20 molecules, or something like that; the stories will not depend on this. extension of water in the sense of waterTE is Although some of the people on Twin the set of all wholes consisting of XYZ Earth (say, those who call themselves "Ameri- molecules, or something like that. cans" and those who call themselves "Canadi- Now let us roll the time back to about 1750. ans" and those who call themselves "English- The typical Earthian speaker of English did men," etc.) speak English, there are, not not know that water consisted of hydrogen surprisingly, a few tiny differences between and oxygen, and the typical Twin-Earthian the dialects of English spoken on Twin Earth speaker of English did not know that "water" and standard English. consisted of XYZ. Let Oscar 1 be such a typical One of the peculiarities of Twin Earth is Earthian English speaker, and let Oscar2 be that the liquid called "water" is not H 20 but a his counterpart on Twin Earth. You may different liquid whose chemical formula is suppose that there is no belief that Oscar 1 had very long and complicated. I shall abbreviate about water that Oscar2 did not have about this chemical formula simply as XYZ. I shall "water." If you like, you may even suppose suppose that XYZ is indistinguishable from that Oscar1 and Oscar2 were exact duplicates water at normal temperatures and pressures. in appearance, feelings, thoughts, ·interior Also, I shall suppose that the oceans and lakes monologue, etc. Yet the extension of the term and seas of Twin Earth contain XYZ and not 'water' was just as much H20 on Earth in 1750 water, that it rains XYZ on Twin Earth and as in 1950; and the extension of the term not water, etc. 'water' was just as much XYZ on Twin Earth If a space ship from Earth ever visits Twin in 1750 as in 1950. Oscar1 and Oscar2 under- Earth, then the supposition at first will be that stood the term 'water' differently in 1750 'water' has the same meaning on Earth and on although they were in the same psychological Twin Earth. This supposition will be corrected state, and although, given the state of science when it is discovered that "water" on Twin at the time, it would have taken their scientific 286 THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE communities about fifty years to discover that I shall suppose that molybdenum pots and they understood the term 'water' differently. pans can't be distinguished from aluminum Thus the extension of the term 'water' (and, in pots and pans save by an expert. (This could fact, its "meaning" in the intuitive preanaly- be true for all I know, and, a fortiori, it could tical usage of that term) is not a function of the be true for all I know by virtue of "knowing psychological state of the speaker by itsel£. 1 the meaning" of the words aluminum and But, it might be objected, why should we molybdenum.) We will now suppose that accept it that the term 'water' had the same molybdenum is as common on Twin Earth as extension in 1750 and in 1950 (on both aluminum is on Earth, and that aluminum is as Earths)? Suppose I point to a glass of water rare on Twin Earth as molybdenum is on and say "this liquid is called water." My Earth. In particular, we shall assume that "ostensive definition" of water had the follow- "aluminum" pots and pans are made of ing empirical presupposition: that the body of molybdenum on Twin Earth. Finally, we shall liquid I am pointing to bears a certain same- assume that the words 'aluminum' and 'molyb- ness relation (say, xis the same liquid as y, or x denum' are switched on Twin Earth: 'alumi- is the sameLas y) to most of the stuff I and num' is the name of molybdenum, and 'molyb- other speakers in my linguistic community denum' is the name of aluminum. If a space have on other occasions called "water." If this ship from Earth visited Twin Earth, the presupposition is false because, say, I am- visitors from Earth probably would not sus- unknown to me-pointing to a glass of gin and pect that the "aluminum" pots and pans on not a glass of water, then I do not intend my Twin Earth were not made of aluminum, ostensive definition to be accepted. Thus the especially when the Twin Earthians said they ostensive definition conveys what might be were. But there is one important difference called a "defeasible" necessary and sufficient between the two cases. An Earthian metallur- condition: the necessary and sufficient condi- gist could tell very easily that "aluminum" was tion for being water is bearing the relation molybdenum, and a Twin Earthian metallur- sameL to the stuff in the glass; but this is the gist could tell equally easily that aluminum necessary and sufficient condition only if the was "molybdenum." (The shudder quotes in empirical presupposition is satisfied.
Recommended publications
  • Indexicality
    Workshop proposal for the 54th Annual Meeting of the Societas Linguistica Europaea (National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, 31 August – 3 September 2021) Indexicality Convenors: Peter Juul Nielsen (University of Southern Denmark) & María Sol Sansiñena (University of Leuven) Proposal The concept of indexicality – originating in the semiotics of C.S. Peirce and his triad symbol, icon and index – has been applied in the description of a broad range of linguistic phenomena, from the internal workings of phonology and morphology via relations within syntactic constructions and lexical and grammatical elements designed to hook on to features outside the clause, to the choice of linguistic variants in social interaction. In morphology, indexicality has been employed to describe the semiotic function of bound allomorphs (Anttila 1975, Andersen 2008: 29, see also Andersen 2010, Carstairs-McCarthy 2001, Enger 2019). Case in languages such as Modern German have been analysed as having indexical meaning, as in (1), where the nominative, accusative and dative case index the ditransitive predicate empfehlen ‘recommend’ that assigns argument status and semantic roles to the case-marked DPs (Heltoft 2019: 154-155). (1) der Rechtsanwalt hat dem Klient-en den Börsenmakler empfohlen the.NOM attorney has the.DAT client-OBL the.ACC stockbroker recommended ‘the attorney recommended the client the stockbroker’ Deictic elements, e.g. personal pronouns and deictic temporal adverbs such as now, are a classic example of linguistic indexicality (shifters, cf. Jakobson 1957) as the encoded meaning of the deictic element points beyond the internal structure of the utterance for interpretation. The term indexicality is also well established in sociolinguistics in analyses of how linguistic choices may index aspects of speaker or addressee identity, such as in-group identification, gender etc.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Logic of Two-Dimensional Semantics
    Matrices and Modalities: On the Logic of Two-Dimensional Semantics MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Peter Fritz (born March 4, 1984 in Ludwigsburg, Germany) under the supervision of Dr Paul Dekker and Prof Dr Yde Venema, and submitted to the Board of Examiners in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MSc in Logic at the Universiteit van Amsterdam. Date of the public defense: Members of the Thesis Committee: June 29, 2011 Dr Paul Dekker Dr Emar Maier Dr Alessandra Palmigiano Prof Dr Frank Veltman Prof Dr Yde Venema Abstract Two-dimensional semantics is a theory in the philosophy of language that pro- vides an account of meaning which is sensitive to the distinction between ne- cessity and apriority. Usually, this theory is presented in an informal manner. In this thesis, I take first steps in formalizing it, and use the formalization to present some considerations in favor of two-dimensional semantics. To do so, I define a semantics for a propositional modal logic with operators for the modalities of necessity, actuality, and apriority that captures the relevant ideas of two-dimensional semantics. I use this to show that some criticisms of two- dimensional semantics that claim that the theory is incoherent are not justified. I also axiomatize the logic, and compare it to the most important proposals in the literature that define similar logics. To indicate that two-dimensional semantics is a plausible semantic theory, I give an argument that shows that all theorems of the logic can be philosophically justified independently of two-dimensional semantics. Acknowledgements I thank my supervisors Paul Dekker and Yde Venema for their help and encour- agement in preparing this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Identity, Indexicality, and the Appropriation of Slurs
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XVII, No. 50, 2017 Social Identity, Indexicality, and the Appropriation of Slurs KATHERINE RITCHIE City College of New York, CUNY, New York, USA Slurs are expressions that can be used to demean and dehumanize tar- gets based on their membership in racial, ethnic, religious, gender, or sexual orientation groups. Almost all treatments of slurs posit that they have derogatory content of some sort. Such views—which I call content- based—must explain why in cases of appropriation slurs fail to express their standard derogatory contents. A popular strategy is to take ap- propriated slurs to be ambiguous; they have both a derogatory content and a positive appropriated content. However, if appropriated slurs are ambiguous, why can only members in the target group use them to ex- press a non-offensive/positive meaning? Here, I develop and motivate an answer that could be adopted by any content-based theorist. I argue that appropriated contents of slurs include a plural fi rst-person pronoun. I show how the semantics of pronouns like ‘we’ can be put to use to explain why only some can use a slur to express its appropriated content. More- over, I argue that the picture I develop is motivated by the process of appropriation and helps to explain how it achieves its aims of promoting group solidarity and positive group identity. Keywords: Slurs, appropriation, reclamation, indexicals, social groups. Slurs are expressions that can be used to demean and dehumanize tar- gets based on their membership in social groups based on, e.g., race, * I thank audiences at the Dartmouth Mind and Language Workshop and the Dubrovnik Inter-University Center Philosophy of Language and Linguistics Workshop where I presented earlier versions of this paper for their helpful feedback.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Meaning: Social Indexicality, Variation, and the Cline of Interiority
    The limits of meaning: Social indexicality, variation, and the cline of interiority Penelope Eckert Language, Volume 95, Number 4, December 2019, pp. 751-776 (Article) Published by Linguistic Society of America For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/743105 Access provided at 17 Dec 2019 23:13 GMT from Linguistic Society of America THE LIMITS OF MEANING: SOCIAL INDEXICALITY, VARIATION, AND THE CLINE OF INTERIORITY Penelope Eckert Stanford University The structural focus of linguistics has led to a static and modular treatment of meaning. View - ing language as practice allows us to transcend the boundaries of subdisciplines that deal with meaning and to integrate the social indexicality of variation into this larger system. This article presents the expression of social meaning as a continuum of decreasing reference and increasing performativity, with sociolinguistic variation at the performative extreme. The meaning potential of sociolinguistic variables in turn is based in their form and their social source, constituting a cline of ‘interiority’ from variables that index public social facts about the speaker to more inter - nal, personal affective states.* Keywords : variation, social meaning, semantics, pragmatics, iconicity, indexicality, semiotics ‘I have resisted the term sociolinguistics for many years, since it implies that there can be a successful linguistic theory or practice which is not social.’ (Labov 1972:13) 1. Introduction . Language is a social practice, a dialectic between structure and agency: structure constrains action, and action in turn reproduces structure. As Giddens (1984:2) puts it, ‘In and through their activities agents reproduce the conditions that make these activities possible’.
    [Show full text]
  • A Changing Cinema: Re-Conceptualizing Indexicality and Digital Technologies
    A Changing Cinema: Re-conceptualizing Indexicality and Digital Technologies by Jennifer Elizabeth Dobbs, B.A. (Honours) A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Film Studies Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario ©2012 Jennifer Elizabeth Dobbs Library and Archives Bibliotheque et Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du 1+1 Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A0N4 Ottawa ON K1A 0N4 Canada Canada Your file Votre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-93555-2 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-93555-2 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library and permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par I'lnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans le loan, distrbute and sell theses monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, sur worldwide, for commercial or non­ support microforme, papier, electronique et/ou commercial purposes, in microform, autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in this et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. Ni thesis. Neither the thesis nor la these ni des extraits substantiels de celle-ci substantial extracts from it may be ne doivent etre imprimes ou autrement printed or otherwise reproduced reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Frames and Simulated Documents: Indexicality in Documentary Videogames
    Frames and Simulated Documents: Indexicality in Documentary Videogames Cindy Poremba Concordia University [email protected] Abstract Traffic Games’ controversial 2003 documentary videogame JFK Reloaded—based on the assassination of JFK—has always fallen back in defense on its “documentary” status– specifically, that the core simulation at the heart of the gameplay, and supporting game elements such as vantage points, are based meticulously on real Warren Commission data. I will argue a strong indexical relation in JFKR lies between the game and the documents—not the historic act itself. As such, the game’s primary strength as a documentary work is in re-engaging the archive, rather than simulating history. Author Keywords Documentary videogames, indexicality, JFK Reloaded, simulation, docugames “I would love to see computer, faced with the problems of probabilities of the assassination taking place the way it did, with all these strange incidents which to place before and are continuing to take place after the assassination.” Penn Jones, Rush to Judgment (1967 documentary)1 DALLAS, TEXAS 12:30 pm, November 22, 1963. The Texas School Book Depository, sixth floor. The weather is fine. You have a rifle. JFK Reloaded (2003 Traffic Games) Often the most well known documentary videogames are the most controversial. JFK Reloaded—a game based on the assassination of American president John F. Kennedy—is one of the better known examples. When it rose to public attention in 2004, the game added fuel to a growing outcry over violence and inappropriate content in videogames. It was explicitly condemned by the Kennedy family—and even used to signify the moral vacuum of digital games in an episode of the television series Law and Order2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Syntactic Expression of Tense
    The Syntactic Expression of Tense Tim Stowell UCLA Tim Stowell UCLA Linguistics Department, 405 Hilgard Ave., Los Angeles, CA 90095-1543 USA [email protected] 1 Abstract In this article I defend the view that many central aspects of the semantics of tense are determined by independently-motivated principles of syntactic theory. I begin by decomposing tenses syntactically into a temporal ordering predicate (the true tense, on this approach) and two time-denoting arguments corresponding to covert a reference time (RT) argument and an eventuality time (ET) argument containing the verb phrase. Control theory accounts for the denotation of the RT argument, deriving the distinction between main clause and subordinate clause tenses. The theory of covert movement is used to account for the independent/indexical interpretation of relative clause tenses, and for the correlation between independent tense interpretation and a de re construal of the relative clause. A theory of “past polarity”, based on traditional negative polarity theory, accounts both for the simultaneous “sequence of tense” construal of past tenses in subordinate clauses embedded within past tense contexts, and for the obligatory indexical/independent interpretation of present tense in a relative clause embedded within a past tense context. Combined with the copy theory of movement, the polarity theory also provides an account of the semantics of double access sentences, treating them as involving a special kind of reconstruction effect. Key Words: Tense, Temporal control, Past polarity, De dicto/de re, Double Access 2 1. Tense and syntactic theory In this article I defend the view that many central aspects of the semantics of tense are determined by independently motivated principles of syntactic theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Challenges for Indexicalism LENNY CLAPP
    Three Challenges for Indexicalism LENNY CLAPP Abstract: Indexicalism is a strategy for defending truth-conditional semantics from under-determination arguments. According to indexicalism the class of indexical expres- sions includes not only the obvious indexicals, e.g. demonstratives and personal pronouns, but also unobvious indexical expressions, expressions which allegedly have been discovered to be indexicals. This paper argues that indexicalism faces significant obstacles that have yet to be overcome. The issue that divides indexicalism and truth-conditional pragmatics is first clarified. And then three general problems for indexicalism are presented, and some potential solutions that have been proposed in its defense are criticized. 1. Introduction The fundamental idea behind the family of views known as truth-conditional semantics is the following simple principle of truth-conditional compositionality: The truth-conditions expressed by an utterance of a declarative sentence S are determined by only two factors: (i) the logical form (LF) of S, and (ii) the semantic contents of the lexical items in S. Because of the influential work of Kaplan (1989) it is now a familiar point that in order to account for sentences that contain obvious indexicals—e.g. ‘I’, ‘now’, ‘she’, ‘that’ and perhaps some ‘relational terms’ such as ‘local’—a defender of truth-conditional semantics must reject this simple principle of truth-conditional compositionality in favor of a relativized principle: The truth-conditions expressed by an utterance of a declarative sentence Sina context c are determined by only two factors: (i) the logical form (LF) of S,and (ii) the semantic contents of the lexical items of Sinc.
    [Show full text]
  • Compositionality and Concepts in Linguistics and Psychology Language, Cognition, and Mind
    Language, Cognition, and Mind James A. Hampton Yoad Winter Editors Compositionality and Concepts in Linguistics and Psychology Language, Cognition, and Mind Volume 3 Series editor Chungmin Lee, Seoul National University, Seoul, South Korea Editorial board members Tecumseh Fitch, University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria Peter Gaerdenfors, Lund University, Lund, Sweden Bart Geurts, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands Noah D. Goodman, Stanford University, Stanford, USA Robert Ladd, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, UK Dan Lassiter, Stanford University, Stanford, USA Edouard Machery, Pittsburgh University, Pittsburgh, USA This series takes the current thinking on topics in linguistics from the theoretical level to validation through empirical and experimental research. The volumes published offer insights on research that combines linguistic perspectives from recently emerging experimental semantics and pragmatics as well as experimental syntax, phonology, and cross-linguistic psycholinguistics with cognitive science perspectives on linguistics, psychology, philosophy, artificial intelligence and neuroscience, and research into the mind, using all the various technical and critical methods available. The series also publishes cross-linguistic, cross-cultural studies that focus on finding variations and universals with cognitive validity. The peer reviewed edited volumes and monographs in this series inform the reader of the advances made through empirical and experimental research in the language-related cognitive science disciplines.
    [Show full text]
  • A Two-Dimensional Logic for Two Paradoxes of Deontic Modality
    A Two-Dimensional Logic for Two Paradoxes of Deontic Modality Melissa Fusco and Arc Kocurek March 6, 2021 Abstract In this paper, we axiomatize the deontic logic in Fusco 2015, which uses a Stalnaker-inspired account of diagonal acceptance and a two-dimensional account of disjunction to treat Ross’s Paradox and the Puzzle of Free Choice Permission. On this account, disjunction-involving validities are a priori rather than necessary. We show how to axiomatize two-dimensional disjunc- tion so that the introduction/elimination rules for boolean disjunciton can be viewed as one-dimensional projections of more general two-dimensional rules. These completeness results help make explicit the restrictions Fusco’s account must place on free-choice inferences. They are also of independent interest, as they raise difficult questions about how to ‘lift’ a Kripke frame for a one-dimensional modal logic into two dimensions. 1 Introduction The validity of or -introduction seems to be a basic rule of natural language disjunction: from ), one may infer ) or #.1 Or-Intro. ) ( ¹) or #º Yet the rule apparently fails in the scope of deontic modals. For example, the nonentailment known as Ross’s Puzzle illustrates the failure of Or-Intro in the scope of ‘ought’ (henceforth $)(Ross, 1941): Ross’s Puzzle. $) * $¹) or #º As an illustration, observe that (1-a), famously, does not seem to entail (1-b): 1Throughout, we use ‘(’ for the intuitive entailment. Subscripted turnstiles will denote entail- ment relative to a specific semantics. 1 (1) a. You ought to post the letter. b. You ought to post the letter or burn it.
    [Show full text]
  • Contextual Two-Dimensionalism
    Contextual two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks November 30, 2009 1 Two two-dimensionalist system of The Conscious Mind .............. 1 1.1 Primary and secondary intensions . 2 1.2 The necessary a posteriori, the contingent a priori, and indexicality . 2 1.2.1 Puzzles about the necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori . 3 1.2.2 The necessary a posteriori and conceivability arguments . 4 1.3 Explanatory ambitions of contextual two-dimensionalism . 5 1.4 The semantics of names and natural kind terms . 5 2 Objections to contextual two-dimensionalism . 7 2.1 Problems with the rigidification of names and kind terms . 7 2.1.1 Problems with ‘actually’-rigidified descriptions . 7 2.1.2 Problems with ‘dthat’-rigidified descriptions . 8 2.1.3 Problems finding descriptions to rigidify . 9 2.2 Problems with the semantics of attitude ascriptions . 9 2.2.1 Option 1: attitude ascriptions report relations to primary intensions 10 2.2.2 Option 2: attitude ascriptions report relations to secondary intensions 10 2.2.3 Option 3: hybrid views . 11 2.3 Misclassification of sentences as a priori . 11 There are two main varieties of two-dimensionalism, which (following Chalmers) I'll call contextual and epistemic two-dimensionalism. 1 Two two-dimensionalist system of The Conscious Mind A good representative of contextual two-dimensionalism is the theory presented by Chalmers in The Conscious Mind. On p. 56 of The Conscious Mind, Chalmers turns to consideration of a popular objection to conceivability arguments for dualism: the objection that the relationship between mental and physical properties might be necessary, though only discoverable a posteriori.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Modality, Mind, and Mathematics
    Epistemic Modality, Mind, and Mathematics Hasen Khudairi June 20, 2017 c Hasen Khudairi 2017, 2021 All rights reserved. 1 Abstract This book concerns the foundations of epistemic modality. I examine the nature of epistemic modality, when the modal operator is interpreted as concerning both apriority and conceivability, as well as states of knowledge and belief. The book demonstrates how epistemic modality relates to the computational theory of mind; metaphysical modality; the types of math- ematical modality; to the epistemic status of undecidable propositions and abstraction principles in the philosophy of mathematics; to the modal pro- file of rational intuition; and to the types of intention, when the latter is interpreted as a modal mental state. Chapter 2 argues for a novel type of expressivism based on the duality between the categories of coalgebras and algebras, and argues that the duality permits of the reconciliation be- tween modal cognitivism and modal expressivism. Chapter 3 provides an abstraction principle for epistemic intensions. Chapter 4 advances a two- dimensional truthmaker semantics, and provides three novel interpretations of the framework along with the epistemic and metasemantic. Chapter 5 applies the modal µ-calculus to account for the iteration of epistemic states, by contrast to availing of modal axiom 4 (i.e. the KK principle). Chapter 6 advances a solution to the Julius Caesar problem based on Fine’s "cri- terial" identity conditions which incorporate conditions on essentiality and grounding. Chapter 7 provides a ground-theoretic regimentation of the pro- posals in the metaphysics of consciousness and examines its bearing on the two-dimensional conceivability argument against physicalism.
    [Show full text]