Fictions of Friendship in the Eighteenth-Century Novel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fictions of Friendship in the Eighteenth-Century Novel NOTES CHAPTER 1 1. Samuel Richardson, Selected Letters of Samuel Richardson, ed. John Carroll (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1964), 66–67. 2. Richardson, Selected Letters, 65. 3. Richardson, Selected Letters, 65. 4. Bradshaigh to Richardson, 25 September, 1753, Forster Collection Manuscripts, Victoria and Albert Museum, XI, f. 26v. All future citations appear as Forster MSS. 5. Denis Diderot, “Eulogy of Richardson” in Clarissa: The Eighteenth Century Response: 1747–1804: Volume 1, Reading Clarissa, ed. Lois Bueler (New York: AMS Press, Inc. 2010), 393. 6. Diderot, “Eulogy of Richardson,” 395. 7. Diderot, “Eulogy of Richardson,” 398. As Mary Helen McMurran observes, the initial problems with Prevost’s translation seemed to provoke a connec- tion between fidelity of translation and fidelity to the sentimental heroine. Richardson himself called Prevost’s translation a “mutilation,” a label that in McMurran’s words, “deploy[s] the thematic of the novel itself to hint that injuries to the text are an immoral violation of the heroine’s body.” See McMurran, The Spread of Novels: Translation and Prose Fiction in the Eighteenth Century (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2010), 123–124. Although McMurran does not focus on the discourse of friendship, she reads Diderot’s “Eloge” as envisioning a “spatial and © The Author(s) 2017 217 B. Mangano, Fictions of Friendship in the Eighteenth-Century Novel, Palgrave Studies in the Enlightenment, Romanticism and the Cultures of Print, DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-48695-6 218 NOTES temporal universality of readership” (The Spread of Novels, 127), an angle I also explore through the narrower scope of language pertaining to amity. 8. Georg Lukács, The Theory of the Novel: A Historico-Philosophical Essay on the Forms of Great Epic Literature, trans. Anna Bostock (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971), 67. Lukács contrasts the novel’s necessary reflexivity, ironic self-reference, and formal self-justification with the epic voice’s confidence in the cultural context to ensure the transmission of meaning, which appears textually as indifference toward the responsiveness of the audience. 9. Ronald. A. Sharp, Friendship and Literature: Spirit and Form (Durham, North Carolina: Duke University Press, 1986), 9, 51. Sharp’s argument is that friendship, like literature, requires mediation of both creative forms and rituals, despite the fact that the rhetoric of modern friendship is often plagued by fallacious idioms of pure expressivity and total transparency. Throughout the book, Sharp links various authors who have represented the necessity of drawing on form in creative ways to forge successful friend- ships. I entirely concur with Sharp’s emphasis on the role of mediating forms, but I focus more directly on the reciprocity between an author’s depiction of creative friendships and their own creative engagement with audiences. 10. Wayne Booth, The Rhetoric of Fiction, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 218. 11. Henry Fielding, The History of Tom Jones, A Foundling, ed. Sheridan Baker (New York: Norton, 1995), 595. 12. Fielding, Tom Jones, 596. 13. See also Booth, The Company We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988). In this text, Booth sketches out a methodology for evaluating literary forms on the basis of their proffered friendship. Booth’s treatment of friendship is partly Aristotelian, partly his own amalgamation of ethical virtues. While I also owe great debts to this work, I am here pursuing an historically situated discussion of what defines friendship ideals in the eighteenth century. 14. Laurence Sterne, The Life and Opinions of Tristram Shandy, Gentleman, ed. Melvin New and Joan New, The Florida Edition of the Works of Laurence Sterne, vols 1 and 2 (Gainesville: University of Florida Press, 1978), 9. Future in-text page references are to this edition. 15. Lukács, Theory of the Novel, 76. 16. Roland Barthes, S/Z, trans. Richard Miller (New York: Hill and Wang, 1974), 20. 17. Garrett Stewart, Dear Reader: The Conscripted Audience in Nineteenth- Century British Fiction (Baltimore and London: The John Hopkins University Press, 1996), 16. NOTES 219 18. Naomi Tadmor, Family and Friends in Eighteenth-Century England: Household, Kinship, and Patronage (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). 19. In the final part of her study, Tadmor discusses but deals briefly with the legacy of classical friendship norms in eighteenth-century life. Tadmor, Family and Friends, 239–245. 20. Jacques Derrida, The Politics of Friendship, trans. George Collins (New York: Verso, 1997). 21. Laurie Shannon, Sovereign Amity: Figures of Friendship in Shakespearean Contexts (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002), 9. 22. Shannon, Sovereign Amity,8. 23. Tadmor, Family and Friends, 239–245.Tadmor reveals how the seven- teenth-century theologian Jeremy Taylor’s treatise on friendship, widely read throughout the eighteenth century by authors and general readers, embodies precisely this effort to synthesize Christian and classical friendship ideals with various spheres of eighteenth-century life. 24. Janet Todd, Women’s Friendship in Literature (New York: Columbia University Press, 1980). 25. Todd, Women’s Friendship,3. 26. Although manipulative and erotic friendship often stand in tension with idealizations of friendship, they also serve to shadow the pursuit of friend- ships that are defined against eroticism (Chapter 5), that are paranoid about deception (Chapter 4), and that depend on deception for didactic purposes (Chapter 2). 27. Clifford Siskin and William B. Warner, “This is Enlightenment: An Invitation in the Form of an Argument” in This is Enlightenment, ed. Clifford Siskin and William B. Warner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2010), 1–33. 28. Siskin and Warner, “This is Enlightenment,” 32–33. 29. Marta Kvande, “Printed in a Book: Negotiating Print and Manuscript Cultures in Fantomina and Clarissa,” Eighteenth-Century Studies 46.2 (2013): 240. 30. Lori Nandrea, Misfit Forms: Paths Not Taken by the British Novel (New York: Fordham University Press, 2014). 31. Jody Greene, “Captain Singleton: An Epic of Mitsein?” The Eighteenth- Century: Theory and Interpretation 52.3–4 (2011): 403–421. 32. Michael McKeon, The Origins of the English Novel: 1600–1740 (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1987). In McKeon’s well-known account, questions of truth reflect a dialectic between romance, empiricism and skepticism, and questions of virtue reflect a dialectic between aristocracy, progressive individu- alism, and conservatism. The quixotic idealism of many eighteenth-century 220 NOTES friendships may seem to fit under the heading of “romance idealism,” but McKeon’s dialectic of virtue does not implicitly accommodate the presence of friendship ideals and their influence on narrative forms. His notion of conserva- tive ideology, as a tenuous negation of both aristocratic and progressive ideol- ogies, offers the closest approximation; though, even in this case, it is not clear that conservative ideology, in its association with “extreme skepticism,” can account for the faith that binds characters in friendship. The value of a collectiv- ity without hierarchy or kinship often presented by the period’s friendship ideals does not fit neatly into the categories of virtue that McKeon offers. 33. Ronald Paulson, Don Quixote in England: The Aesthetics of Laughter (Baltimore: John Hopkins Press, 1998); Scott Paul Gordon, ThePracticeofQuixotism:Post- Modern Theory and Eighteenth-Century Women’sWriting(New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006); Susan Staves, “Don Quixote in Eighteenth-Century England,” Comparative Literature 24.3 (1972): 193–215. 34. Gordon, The Practice of Quixotism,34–40. 35. J.G.A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975); Virtue, Commerce, and History: Essays on Political Thought and History, Chiefly in the Eighteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). 36. Emrys D. Jones, Friendship and Allegiance in Eighteenth-Century Literature: The Politics of Private Virtue in the Age of Walpole (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013). 37. Catherine Gallagher observes that literary authorship in mid-eighteenth- century Britain becomes less explicitly political as women authors help to transform scandal and political allegory into fictions about “nobodies.” Thus, the general de-politicization of fictional characters makes the notion of readers “befriending” a character appear politically neutral, or at least non-partisan. See especially Gallagher’s discussion of Delarivier Manley and Charlotte Lennox in Chapters 3 and 4 of Nobody’s Story: The Vanishing Acts of Women Writers in the Marketplace, 1670–1820 (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1994). 38. The economic relation between authors and readers is almost always less direct than the implied virtual friendship cultivated by the rhetoric of fiction. In each case study, I attend to the differing professional circumstances that underlie the rhetoric of amity. 39. Allan Silver, “Friendship in Commercial Society: Eighteenth-Century Social Theory and Modern Sociology,” American Journal of Sociology 95.6 (1990): 1479. Silver bases his argument primarily on the writings of Adam Smith, David Hume, Francis Hutcheson, and Adam Ferguson. Of course, even this notion of the individual as an end-in-itself, detached from com- merce, must be thoroughly scrutinized. NOTES 221 40. Tadmor argues that Richardson’s
Recommended publications
  • Was Aristotle a Naïve Realist? by Michael Makled
    Was Aristotle a Naïve Realist? by Michael Makled A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2016 Advisor: Professor Victor Caston Second Reader: Professor Tad Schmaltz 1 2 Contents 1. Realism and Naïve Realism 2. Aristotle’s Theory of Perception in De Anima: how do sensibles cause perception? 3. Contrary Appearances and Metaphysics Gamma V: is the world as it appears to be? 4. Conclusion 3 Introduction Realism and Naïve Realism In the Assayer, Galileo advocates a mathematical approach to scientific inquiry that leads him to striking conclusions about the relationship between the world and our perceptions of it. Considering the concept of heat, for instance, he says: “I suspect that people in general have a concept of this which is very remote from the truth. For they believe that heat is a real phenomenon or property, or quality, which actually resides in the material by which we feel ourselves warmed.”1 In this vein, Galileo makes a paradigmatic statement of what is called, in the philosophy of perception, eliminativism: Hence I think that tastes, odors, colors, and so on are no more than mere names so far as the object in which we place them is concerned, and that they reside only in the consciousness. Hence if the living creature were removed, all these qualities would be wiped away and annihilated. (Galileo, The Assayer, p. 274)2 Galileo thinks that a number of the qualities that figure most prominently in our experience of the world are merely subjective.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    curriculum vitæ Victor Caston April 2013 Personal Born 02 February 1963, in Montgomery, Alabama. Citizen of the United States. Home address: 1117 Lincoln St, Ann Arbor, MI 48104. w: 734 764 6882 h: 734 222 9927 (On leave 2012/13: +44 01223 743103) f: 734 763 8071 e: [email protected] Employment University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. Professor of Philosophy & Classical Studies, 2005–present. University of California, Davis. Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2000–2005. Brown University. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 1991–1998; Associate Professor, 1998–2000. area of specialization: Ancient areas of competence: Medieval, Austrian, Mind Education The University of Texas at Austin. M. A. (philosophy), Ph. D. (philosophy), 1984–1992. Yale University. B. A., summa cum laude, with honors in philosophy, FBK, 1980–1984. academic exchanges: University of Arizona, Tucson, Spring 1989. King’s College London, 1985–1987. dissertation: Aristotle on Intentionality (A. P. D. Mourelatos, advisor) foreign languages: Greek, Latin, German, French Honors and Awards Fellowships, awards & prizes American Council of Learned Societies Fellowship, 2012/13. Michigan Humanities Award, 2012/13. Fellowships awarded, but declined (2012/13): National Humanities Center Fellowship; Solmsen Fel- lowship at the Institute for Research in the Humanities, University of Wisconsin at Madison; Loeb Classical Library Fellowship. Rackham Spring/Summer Research Grant, 2009. Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 2003/04. Burkhardt Fellow, American Council of Learned Societies, 2003/04. Junior Fellow, Center for Hellenic Studies (Washington, D. C.), 1998/99. Fellowships awarded, but declined (1998/99): Institute for Advanced Study; National Humanities Cen- ter; Stanford Humanities Center. neh Fellowship for University Teachers, 1994/95.
    [Show full text]
  • Desiring the Good: Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, Princeton
    Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com 1 Fall 2015, PHI 501/CLA 519, Te Philosophy of Aristotle, Princeton University PHI 501/CLA 519 Location: 201 Marx Time: Fall 2015, Wednesday 10am-12:50pm Value, Motivation, and Agency in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 1. Course Description Te course explores central themes in Aristotle’s ethics: happiness, motivation, agency, excellence, deliberation, and the nature and subject matter of ethics. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle asks “what is the good?”. He approaches this question from the perspective of agency. From this perspective, the good is the end, that which motivates action. Activities such as going to the market or studying or swimming aim at some good. Tey also aim, or so Aristotle argues, at the good: the good life. Aristotle envisages agents who are already on board with wanting to get things right. When they aim for a good life, they aim for a life that really is good, not only good by their lights. Te task of ethics is to fgure out what a good life looks like and what is needed to attain it. As one thinks through these questions, puzzles about the nature of agency, psychology and motivation, and the sphere in which we act may arise. One may wonder what decisions and pursuits are, and even more basically, what actions are. One may wonder whether the goings-on in human life are necessary or contingent. One may ask to what extent excellence in thinking matters to leading a good life, and how it relates to more familiar excellences, such as justice, courage, and moderation.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Professor Brad Inwood Updated July 2020
    Curriculum Vitae Professor Brad Inwood Updated July 2020 1. Contact Information William Lampson Professor of Philosophy and of Classics Department of Classics Yale University 344 College Street P.O. Box 208266 New Haven CT 06520-8266 2. Degrees B.A. Classics, Brock University, St. Catharines, Ont., 1974. M.A. Classics, University of Toronto, 1975. Ph.D. Classics, University of Toronto, 1981. 3. Awards, Honours and Scholarships Canada Council Doctoral Fellowships: 1976-9. Queen Elizabeth II Ontario Scholarship: 1980. Mellon Post-Doctoral Fellowship, Stanford University: 1981. SSHRCC Research Grant: $14,660 for work on Stoic ethics, 1991-94. Elected Fellow of the Royal Society of Canada, April 1994. Fellow, National Humanities Centre (US$10,000 for work on Seneca), 1995-6. Canada Research Chair in Ancient Philosophy, 2000-2015. Connaught Research Fellowship, University of Toronto, 2001. SSHRCC Research Grant: 2001-2004 ‘Reading Seneca’ $29,484. Fellow, Centre for Advanced Study in the Behavioural Sciences, 2004-5. (Grant: US$10,000) February 2007 A.E. Taylor lecturer at the University of Edinburgh. Elected University Professor, University of Toronto, May 2007. Easter term 2008: Malcolm Bowie Distinguished Visitor at Christ's College, Cambridge February 2009 Eberhard L. Faber Memorial lecturer, Princeton University. Winner of the Northrop Frye Award (teaching), University of Toronto, 2010. April 2011 Carl Newell Jackson lecturer, Harvard University. SSHRCC Research Grant: $70,750 ‘Ethics after Aristotle’, 2011. October 2016 Crake lecturer in Classics, Mount Allison University. April 2018 Gregory Vlastos Memorial Lecturer, Queen’s University, Kingston, Ontario October 2018 James Bradley Memorial Lecturer, Memorial University of Newfoundland Elected to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, April 2109.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76844-3 - Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf Edited by James G. Lennox and Robert Bolton Frontmatter More information BEING, NATURE, AND LIFE IN ARISTOTLE This volume of essays explores major connected themes in Aristo- tle’s metaphysics, philosophy of nature, and ethics, especially themes related to essence, definition, teleology, activity, potentiality, and the highest good. The volume is united by the belief that all aspects of Aristotle’s work need to be studied together if any one of the areas of thought is to be fully understood. Many of the chapters were contributions to a conference at the University of Pittsburgh enti- tled “Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle,” to honor Professor Allan Gotthelf’s many contributions to the field of ancient philosophy; a few are contributions from those who were invited but could not attend. The contributors, all longstanding friends of Professor Gott- helf, are among the most accomplished scholars in the field of ancient philosophy today. james g. lennox is Professor of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh. He has published many articles in professional journals and edited volumes, and his most recent books are Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals, Translation with Introduction and Commentary (2001), and Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science (Cambridge, 2001). robert bolton is Professor of Philosophy at Rutgers University. He is author or editor of numerous books and articles on topics in ancient philosophy, particularly those concerning questions in episte- mology and philosophy of mind, and those concerning philosophical and scientific methods and their applications in natural science, meta- physics, and ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • MICHAEL PAKALUK Department of Philosophy Ave Maria University
    MICHAEL PAKALUK Department of Philosophy Ave Maria University Ave Maria, FL 34142 [email protected], [email protected] 239-348-4704 (o), 617-710-2757 (c) APPOINTMENTS Professor of Philosophy Ave Maria University, 2010-present Adjunct Research Scholar Institute for the Psychological Sciences, 2010-present Professor of Philosophy and Director of Integrative Research Institute for the Psychological Sciences, 2008-2010 Associate Professor of Philosophy Clark University 1995-2008 Assistant Professor of Philosophy Clark University 1988-1994 VISITING APPOINTMENTS Visiting Professor of Philosophy Pontificia Università della Santa Croce (Rome, Italy) Visiting Associate Professor of Philosophy The Catholic University of America, 2007-9 Brown University 1998, 2000, 2005 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy Brown University 1994 VISITING SCHOLAR Cambridge University, 2003 (Classics) Harvard University, 2002-3 (Philosophy) University of St. Andrews, 1997 (Public Philosophy) Brown University, 1996-7 (Classics and Philosophy) EDUCATION Ph.D., Philosophy, 1988, Harvard University “Aristotle’s Theory of Friendship” (dissertation) John Rawls, Sarah Broadie, Alison McIntyre (committee) M.Litt., Philosophy, 1982, University of Edinburgh “Hume’s Naturalism and the Argument from Design” (thesis) Ronald Hepburn, Peter Jones (committee) Anthony Flew (external examiner) A.B., Philosophy, 1980, Harvard College “Philosophical Interpretations of Psychiatry” (thesis) Burton Dreben (supervisor) AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Aristotle; Plato; Ancient Philosophy; Hume and Scottish Philosophy; Philosophical Psychology; Ethics; Political Philosophy; Rawls; Aquinas AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Psychology; History of Moral Philosophy; History of Modern Philosophy; Medieval Philosophy; Early Analytic Philosophy; Quine PUBLICATIONS (select) Books Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle (with Giles Pearson), Oxford University Press, 2011. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction, Cambridge University Press, 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitæ Victor Caston April 2017
    curriculum vitæ Victor Caston April 2017 Personal Born 02 February 1963, in Montgomery, Alabama. Citizen of the United States. Home address: 1117 Lincoln St, Ann Arbor, MI 48104. w: 734 764 6882 h: 734 369 2699 f: 734 763 8071 e: [email protected] Employment University of Michigan, Ann Arbor. Professor of Philosophy & Classical Studies, 2005–present. University of California, Davis. Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2000–2005. Brown University. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 1991–1998; Associate Professor, 1998–2000. area of specialization: Ancient areas of competence: Medieval, Austrian, Mind Education The University of Texas at Austin. M. A. (philosophy), Ph. D. (philosophy), 1984–1992. Yale University. B. A., summa cum laude, with honors in philosophy, ΦΒΚ, 1980–1984. academic exchanges: University of Arizona, Tucson, Spring 1989. King’s College London, 1985–1987. dissertation: Aristotle on Intentionality (A. P. D. Mourelatos, advisor) foreign languages: Greek, Latin, German, French Honors and Awards Guggenheim Fellowship, 2016/17. National Endowment for the Humanities (neh) Fellowship for University Teachers, 2016/17. American Council of Learned Societies Fellowship, 2012/13. Michigan Humanities Award, 2012/13. Fellowships awarded, but declined (2012/13): National Humanities Center; Solmsen Fellowship, Insti- tute for Research in the Humanities, Univ. Wisconsin-Madison; Loeb Classical Library Fellowship. Rackham Spring/Summer Research Grant, 2009. Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 2003/04. Burkhardt Fellow, American Council of Learned Societies, 2003/04. Junior Fellow, Center for Hellenic Studies (Washington, D. C.), 1998/99. Fellowships awarded, but declined (1998/99): Institute for Advanced Study; National Humanities Cen- ter; Stanford Humanities Center. National Endowment for the Humanities (neh) Fellowship for University Teachers, 1994/95.
    [Show full text]