Adjoints, Naturality, Exactness, Small Yoneda Lemma 1. Hom(X,−) Is Left

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Adjoints, Naturality, Exactness, Small Yoneda Lemma 1. Hom(X,−) Is Left (October 24, 2014) Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma Paul Garrett [email protected] http:=/www.math.umn.edu/egarrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/~garrett/m/repns/notes 2014-15/04b adjoints exactness.pdf] The best way to certify left-exactness or right-exactness of an additive functor [1] is to see that it appears is a right adjoint or left adjoint. Many familiar functors occur in pairs whose adjointness is obvious once observed. MacLane and others have quipped Everything's an adjoint. The proof that left adjoints are right-exact, and that right adjoints are left-exact, uses a small incarnation of Yoneda's Lemma, and illustrates the importance of naturality of isomorphisms. Throughout, we consider only Z-modules, although the arguments apply more generally. • Hom(X; −) is left exact • Adjoints and naturality • A small Yoneda lemma • Half-exactness of adjoints 1. Hom(X; −) is left exact Everything later will reduce to the straightforward left-exactness of Hom(X; −). [1.0.1] Claim: The functor Hom(X; −) is left exact. That is, a short exact sequence i q 0 / A / B / C / 0 gives an exact sequence i◦− q◦− 0 / Hom(X; A) / Hom(X; B) / Hom(X; C) where the induced maps are by the obvious post-compositions with i and q. Similarly, the contravariant Hom functor Hom(−;X) gives an exact sequence −◦q −◦i 0 / Hom(C; X) / Hom(B; X) / Hom(A; X) where the induced maps are the pre-compositions with i and q. Proof: For f 2 Hom(X; A), i ◦ f = 0 implies (i ◦ f)(x) = 0 for all x 2 X, and then f(x) = 0 for all x since i is injective. Thus, Hom(X; A) ! Hom(X; B) is injective, giving exactness at the left joint. Since q ◦ i = 0, any f 2 Hom(X; A) is mapped to 0 2 Hom(X; C) by f ! q ◦ i ◦ f. That is, the image of i ◦ − is contained in the kernel of q ◦ −. On the other hand, for g 2 Hom(X; B) is mapped to q ◦ g = 0 in Hom(X; C), g(X) ⊂ ker q = Imi Since i is injective, it is an isomorphism to its image, so there is an inverse i−1 : i(A) ! A. Since g(X) ⊂ Imi, we can define f = i−1 ◦ g 2 Hom(X; A) [1] A functor F : C −! D of categories whose hom-sets are abelian groups additive when the map on morphisms Hom(A; B) ! Hom(F A; F B) given by F is a homomorphism of abelian groups. This also entails F (A ⊕ B) ≈ FA ⊕ FB. These isomorphisms are required to be natural. 1 Paul Garrett: Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma (October 24, 2014) Certainly i ◦ f = g, so the kernel is contained in the image. This gives exactness at the middle joint, and the left exactness. The exactness of the contravariant Hom is similar. === [1.0.2] Remark: The functor Hom(X; −) is not right exact. For example, with ×n 0 / Z / Z / Z=n / 0 with an integer n > 1, with X = Z=n there is no non-zero map of the torsion abelian group X to the free abelian group Z. That is, the right joint in the following is not exact: ×n 0 / Hom(Z=n; Z) / Hom(Z=n; Z) / Hom(Z=n; Z=n) ___ / 0 0 0 Z=n Similarly, the contravariant Hom(−;X) is not right exact. 2. Adjoints and naturality Two functors R and L (from Z-modules to Z-modules) are mutually adjoint when there is an adjunction, that is, an isomorphism of Z-modules Hom(LA; B) ≈ Hom(A; RB) (for all A; B) The functor R is a right adjoint, and L is a left adjoint. The adjunction isomorphism is required to be natural or functorial, in the sense that, for each pair of morphisms f : A0 ! A and g : B ! B0 (yes, from A0 to A, but from B to B0) we have a commutative diagram [2] ≈ Hom(LA; B) / Hom(A; RB) g◦(−)◦Lf Rg◦(−)◦f ≈ Hom(LA0;B0) / Hom(A0; RB0) where the notation for pre-composition and post-composition is g ◦ (−) ◦ Lf : F −! g ◦ F ◦ Lf (for F 2 Hom(LA; B)) and Rg ◦ (−) ◦ f : F −! Rg ◦ F ◦ f (for F 2 Hom(A; RB)) In categories whose hom sets have additional structure, such as that of Z-modules, the natural isomorphisms of hom sets are required to respect that additional structure, and satisfaction of this requirement is usually obvious. We prove naturality in two examples of adjoint pairs. [2.1] Annihilated and co-annihilated modules Let Λ be a ring with 1. Consider the category of Λ- modules and Λ-module homomorphisms. Fix an ideal I in Λ. A Λ-module N is annihilated by I if i · n = 0 for all i 2 I and n 2 N. For convenience, say that such N is I-null. [2] Assembling these naturality isomorphisms into larger diagrams is critical in the later argument for left/right- exactness from adjointness. 2 Paul Garrett: Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma (October 24, 2014) Given a Λ-module M, M I is a Λ-module with a Λ-module map j : M I ! M through which every map N ! M from an I-null Λ-module N factors. Dually, MI is an Λ-module with Λ-module map q : M ! MI through which every map M ! N to an I-null Λ-module N factors. I Proof of existence, by construction, of M and MI element-wise is easy, as sub-object and quotient, respectively: 8 I < M = fm 2 M : i · m = 0 for all i 2 Ig : MI = M=(I · M) I [2.1.1] Claim: The functors LM = MI and RM = M are mutual adjoints: HomΛ(LA; B) ≈ HomΛ(A; RB) Proof: The isomorphism of hom-sets is the obvious f ! f ◦ q, where q : A ! AI is the quotient map. That I I f ◦ q has image inside the subobject RB = B follows from the fact that f : AI ! B has image inside B , which follows from the fact that I acts by 0 on AI . The issue of interest is the naturality. Let α : A0 ! A and β : B ! B0 be Λ-module homomorphisms. Let 0 0 0 q : A ! AI be the quotient map. That A ! AI is a functor implicitly claims that there is a homomorphism 0 αI : AI ! AI . Indeed, the composite 0 A −! A −! AI 0 0 must factor through AI , by its universal property, yielding a unique αI : AI −! AI fitting into the commutative diagram 0 0 q 0 A / AI α αI A q / AI Similarly, there is βI : BI ! B0I fitting into a commutative diagram, namely, βI is the restriction of β to B: i BI / B βI β B0I / B0 i0 The naturality is the commutativity of ≈ I Hom(AI ;B) / Hom(A; B ) I β◦(−)◦αI β ◦(−)◦α 0 0 ≈ 0 0I Hom(AI ;B ) / Hom(A ;B ) Note that at this point we do not give the top and bottom edge isomorphisms explicitly. This is clarified in the following. The desired commutative diagram expands to a larger diagram upon making explicit the isomorphism whose 3 Paul Garrett: Adjoints, naturality, exactness, small Yoneda lemma (October 24, 2014) naturality is at issue. Namely, we claim that the following is commutative: i◦− −◦q Hom(A ;B) Hom(A ;BI ) Hom(A; BI ) I o ≈ I ≈ / β◦− βI ◦− βI ◦− i◦− −◦q Hom(A ;B0) Hom(A ;B0I ) Hom(A; B0I ) I o ≈ I ≈ / −◦αI −◦αI −◦α i0◦− −◦q0 Hom(A0 ;B0) Hom(A0 ;B0I ) Hom(A0;B0I ) I o ≈ I ≈ / The three horizontal maps on the left half are the definition of (−)I , while the three horizontal maps on the right half are the definition of (−)I . Each vertical map is the image of a morphism by a Hom functor. Commutativity of the upper left square follows from applying Hom(AI ; −) to the square expressing 0I functoriality of (−)I . Similarly, commutativity of the lower right square follows from applying Hom(−;B ) to the square expressing functoriality of (−)I . The upper right and lower left squares commute by associativity of composition of homs. The directions of the horizontal maps in each row are in opposite directions, so they can be composed only because they are isomorphisms. The composition along the top edge, and the composition along the bottom edge, are the isomorphisms in the assertion of adjunction. The adjunction square is obtained by keeping only the four outer corner Homs, and the composite maps along the outer edges. === [2.2] Cartan-Eilenberg adjunction: (−) ⊗ X and Hom(X; −) [2.2.1] Claim: For all Z-modules A; X; B there is a natural isomorphism of Z-modules Hom(A ⊗ X; B) ≈ Hom(A; Hom(X; B)) Proof: Once one knows existence, there is only one possibility that makes sense: given Φ 2 Hom(A ⊗ X; B), define 'Φ 2 Hom(A; Hom(X; B)) by 'Φ(a)(x) = Φ(a ⊗ x) Conversely, given ' 2 Hom(A; Hom(X; B)), there is Φ' 2 Hom(A ⊗ X; B) by Φ'(a ⊗ x) = '(a)(x) and extend by linearity. The maps Φ ! 'Φ and ' ! Φ' are mutual inverses. Naturality of the isomorphism 0 0 ' ! Φ' and Φ ! 'Φ asserts the commutativity of diagrams attached to f : A ! A and g : X ! X: there is a commutative diagram ≈ Hom(A ⊗ X; B) / Hom(A; Hom(X; B)) h◦(−)◦(f⊗g) a0!x0!h(((−)(fa0))(gx0)) Hom(A0 ⊗ X; B0) Hom(A0; Hom(X0;B0)) ≈ / Note the awkwardness on the right-hand side of the diagram, leading to a more verbose description.
Recommended publications
  • Nearly Locally Presentable Categories Are Locally Presentable Is Equivalent to Vopˇenka’S Principle
    NEARLY LOCALLY PRESENTABLE CATEGORIES L. POSITSELSKI AND J. ROSICKY´ Abstract. We introduce a new class of categories generalizing locally presentable ones. The distinction does not manifest in the abelian case and, assuming Vopˇenka’s principle, the same happens in the regular case. The category of complete partial orders is the natural example of a nearly locally finitely presentable category which is not locally presentable. 1. Introduction Locally presentable categories were introduced by P. Gabriel and F. Ulmer in [6]. A category K is locally λ-presentable if it is cocomplete and has a strong generator consisting of λ-presentable objects. Here, λ is a regular cardinal and an object A is λ-presentable if its hom-functor K(A, −): K → Set preserves λ-directed colimits. A category is locally presentable if it is locally λ-presentable for some λ. This con- cept of presentability formalizes the usual practice – for instance, finitely presentable groups are precisely groups given by finitely many generators and finitely many re- lations. Locally presentable categories have many nice properties, in particular they are complete and co-wellpowered. Gabriel and Ulmer [6] also showed that one can define locally presentable categories by using just monomorphisms instead all morphisms. They defined λ-generated ob- jects as those whose hom-functor K(A, −) preserves λ-directed colimits of monomor- phisms. Again, this concept formalizes the usual practice – finitely generated groups are precisely groups admitting a finite set of generators. This leads to locally gener- ated categories, where a cocomplete category K is locally λ-generated if it has a strong arXiv:1710.10476v2 [math.CT] 2 Apr 2018 generator consisting of λ-generated objects and every object of K has only a set of strong quotients.
    [Show full text]
  • AN INTRODUCTION to CATEGORY THEORY and the YONEDA LEMMA Contents Introduction 1 1. Categories 2 2. Functors 3 3. Natural Transfo
    AN INTRODUCTION TO CATEGORY THEORY AND THE YONEDA LEMMA SHU-NAN JUSTIN CHANG Abstract. We begin this introduction to category theory with definitions of categories, functors, and natural transformations. We provide many examples of each construct and discuss interesting relations between them. We proceed to prove the Yoneda Lemma, a central concept in category theory, and motivate its significance. We conclude with some results and applications of the Yoneda Lemma. Contents Introduction 1 1. Categories 2 2. Functors 3 3. Natural Transformations 6 4. The Yoneda Lemma 9 5. Corollaries and Applications 10 Acknowledgments 12 References 13 Introduction Category theory is an interdisciplinary field of mathematics which takes on a new perspective to understanding mathematical phenomena. Unlike most other branches of mathematics, category theory is rather uninterested in the objects be- ing considered themselves. Instead, it focuses on the relations between objects of the same type and objects of different types. Its abstract and broad nature allows it to reach into and connect several different branches of mathematics: algebra, geometry, topology, analysis, etc. A central theme of category theory is abstraction, understanding objects by gen- eralizing rather than focusing on them individually. Similar to taxonomy, category theory offers a way for mathematical concepts to be abstracted and unified. What makes category theory more than just an organizational system, however, is its abil- ity to generate information about these abstract objects by studying their relations to each other. This ability comes from what Emily Riehl calls \arguably the most important result in category theory"[4], the Yoneda Lemma. The Yoneda Lemma allows us to formally define an object by its relations to other objects, which is central to the relation-oriented perspective taken by category theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Friday September 20 Lecture Notes
    Friday September 20 Lecture Notes 1 Functors Definition Let C and D be categories. A functor (or covariant) F is a function that assigns each C 2 Obj(C) an object F (C) 2 Obj(D) and to each f : A ! B in C, a morphism F (f): F (A) ! F (B) in D, satisfying: For all A 2 Obj(C), F (1A) = 1FA. Whenever fg is defined, F (fg) = F (f)F (g). e.g. If C is a category, then there exists an identity functor 1C s.t. 1C(C) = C for C 2 Obj(C) and for every morphism f of C, 1C(f) = f. For any category from universal algebra we have \forgetful" functors. e.g. Take F : Grp ! Cat of monoids (·; 1). Then F (G) is a group viewed as a monoid and F (f) is a group homomorphism f viewed as a monoid homomor- phism. e.g. If C is any universal algebra category, then F : C! Sets F (C) is the underlying sets of C F (f) is a morphism e.g. Let C be a category. Take A 2 Obj(C). Then if we define a covariant Hom functor, Hom(A; ): C! Sets, defined by Hom(A; )(B) = Hom(A; B) for all B 2 Obj(C) and f : B ! C, then Hom(A; )(f) : Hom(A; B) ! Hom(A; C) with g 7! fg (we denote Hom(A; ) by f∗). Let us check if f∗ is a functor: Take B 2 Obj(C). Then Hom(A; )(1B) = (1B)∗ : Hom(A; B) ! Hom(A; B) and for g 2 Hom(A; B), (1B)∗(g) = 1Bg = g.
    [Show full text]
  • Adjoint and Representable Functors
    What underlies dual-process cognition? Adjoint and representable functors Steven Phillips ([email protected]) Mathematical Neuroinformatics Group, Human Informatics Research Institute, National Institute of Advanced Industrial Science and Technology (AIST), Tsukuba, Ibaraki 305-8566 JAPAN Abstract & Stanovich, 2013, for the model and responses to the five criticisms). According to this model, cognition defaults to Despite a general recognition that there are two styles of think- ing: fast, reflexive and relatively effortless (Type 1) versus slow, Type 1 processes that can be intervened upon by Type 2 pro- reflective and effortful (Type 2), dual-process theories of cogni- cesses in response to task demands. However, this model is tion remain controversial, in particular, for their vagueness. To still far from the kinds of formal, computational explanations address this lack of formal precision, we take a mathematical category theory approach towards understanding what under- that prevail in cognitive science. lies the relationship between dual cognitive processes. From our category theory perspective, we show that distinguishing ID Criticism of dual-process theories features of Type 1 versus Type 2 processes are exhibited via adjoint and representable functors. These results suggest that C1 Theories are multitudinous and definitions vague category theory provides a useful formal framework for devel- C2 Type 1/2 distinctions do not reliably align oping dual-process theories of cognition. C3 Cognitive styles vary continuously, not discretely Keywords: dual-process; Type 1; Type 2; category theory; C4 Single-process theories provide better explanations category; functor; natural transformation; adjoint C5 Evidence for dual-processing is unconvincing Introduction Table 2: Five criticisms of dual-process theories (Evans & Intuitively, at least, human cognition involves two starkly dif- Stanovich, 2013).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Category Theory
    {-# LANGUAGE RankNTypes #-} module AbstractNonsense where import Control.Monad 1 Category theory Definition 1. A category consists of • a collection of objects • and a collection of morphisms between those objects. We write f : A → B for the morphism f connecting the object A to B. • Morphisms are closed under composition, i.e. for morphisms f : A → B and g : B → C there exists the composed morphism h = f ◦ g : A → C1. Furthermore we require that • Composition is associative, i.e. f ◦ (g ◦ h) = (f ◦ g) ◦ h • and for each object A there exists an identity morphism idA such that for all morphisms f : A → B: f ◦ idB = idA ◦ f = f Many mathematical structures form catgeories and thus the theorems and con- structions of category theory apply to them. As an example consider the cate- gories • Set whose objects are sets and morphisms are functions between those sets. • Grp whose objects are groups and morphisms are group homomorphisms, i.e. structure preserving functions, between those groups. 1.1 Functors Category theory is mainly interested in relationships between different kinds of mathematical structures. Therefore the fundamental notion of a functor is introduced: 1The order of the composition is to be read from left to right in contrast to standard mathematical notation. 1 Definition 2. A functor F : C → D is a transformation between categories C and D. It is defined by its action on objects F (A) and morphisms F (f) and has to preserve the categorical structure, i.e. for any morphism f : A → B: F (f(A)) = F (f)(F (A)) which can also be stated graphically as the commutativity of the following dia- gram: F (f) F (A) F (B) f A B Alternatively we can state that functors preserve the categorical structure by the requirement to respect the composition of morphisms: F (idC) = idD F (f) ◦ F (g) = F (f ◦ g) 1.2 Natural transformations Taking the construction a step further we can ask for transformations between functors.
    [Show full text]
  • Combinatorial Species and Labelled Structures Brent Yorgey University of Pennsylvania, [email protected]
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 1-1-2014 Combinatorial Species and Labelled Structures Brent Yorgey University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Computer Sciences Commons, and the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Yorgey, Brent, "Combinatorial Species and Labelled Structures" (2014). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1512. http://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1512 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. http://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1512 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Combinatorial Species and Labelled Structures Abstract The theory of combinatorial species was developed in the 1980s as part of the mathematical subfield of enumerative combinatorics, unifying and putting on a firmer theoretical basis a collection of techniques centered around generating functions. The theory of algebraic data types was developed, around the same time, in functional programming languages such as Hope and Miranda, and is still used today in languages such as Haskell, the ML family, and Scala. Despite their disparate origins, the two theories have striking similarities. In particular, both constitute algebraic frameworks in which to construct structures of interest. Though the similarity has not gone unnoticed, a link between combinatorial species and algebraic data types has never been systematically explored. This dissertation lays the theoretical groundwork for a precise—and, hopefully, useful—bridge bewteen the two theories. One of the key contributions is to port the theory of species from a classical, untyped set theory to a constructive type theory. This porting process is nontrivial, and involves fundamental issues related to equality and finiteness; the recently developed homotopy type theory is put to good use formalizing these issues in a satisfactory way.
    [Show full text]
  • Ends and Coends
    THIS IS THE (CO)END, MY ONLY (CO)FRIEND FOSCO LOREGIAN† Abstract. The present note is a recollection of the most striking and use- ful applications of co/end calculus. We put a considerable effort in making arguments and constructions rather explicit: after having given a series of preliminary definitions, we characterize co/ends as particular co/limits; then we derive a number of results directly from this characterization. The last sections discuss the most interesting examples where co/end calculus serves as a powerful abstract way to do explicit computations in diverse fields like Algebra, Algebraic Topology and Category Theory. The appendices serve to sketch a number of results in theories heavily relying on co/end calculus; the reader who dares to arrive at this point, being completely introduced to the mysteries of co/end fu, can regard basically every statement as a guided exercise. Contents Introduction. 1 1. Dinaturality, extranaturality, co/wedges. 3 2. Yoneda reduction, Kan extensions. 13 3. The nerve and realization paradigm. 16 4. Weighted limits 21 5. Profunctors. 27 6. Operads. 33 Appendix A. Promonoidal categories 39 Appendix B. Fourier transforms via coends. 40 References 41 Introduction. The purpose of this survey is to familiarize the reader with the so-called co/end calculus, gathering a series of examples of its application; the author would like to stress clearly, from the very beginning, that the material presented here makes arXiv:1501.02503v2 [math.CT] 9 Feb 2015 no claim of originality: indeed, we put a special care in acknowledging carefully, where possible, each of the many authors whose work was an indispensable source in compiling this note.
    [Show full text]
  • Category Theory in Coq 8.5
    Category Theory in Coq 8.5 Amin Timany Bart Jacobs iMinds-Distrinet KU Leuven 7th Coq Workshop { Sophia Antipolis June 26, 2015 Amin Timany Bart Jacobs Category Theory in Coq 8.5 List of the most important formalized notions basic constructions: terminal/initial object pullbacks/pushouts products/sums exponentials equalizers/coequalizers + a ∆ a × and (− × a) a a− external constructions: comma categories product category for Cat:(Obj := Category, Hom := Functor) cartesian closure initial object for Set:(Obj := Type, Hom := funAB ) A ! B) initial object local cartesian closurey sums completeness equalizers co-completenessy coequalizersy y pullbacks sub-object classifier (Prop : Type) cartesian closure toposy yuses the axioms of propositional extensionality and constructive indefinite description (axiom of choice). the Yoneda lemma 1 Amin Timany Bart Jacobs Category Theory in Coq 8.5 adjunction hom-functor adjunction, unit-counit adjunction, universal morphism adjunction and their conversions duality : F a G ) Gop a F op uniqueness up to natural isomorphism category of adjunctions kan extensions global definition local definition with both hom-functor and cones (along a functor) uniqueness preservation by adjoint functors pointwise kan extensions (preserved by representable functors) (co)limits as (left)right local kan extensions along the unique functor to the terminal category (sum)product-(co)equalizer (co)limits pointwise (as kan extensions) T − (co)algebras (for an endofunctor T ) we use proof functional extensionality we use proof irrelevance
    [Show full text]
  • Tensor Products of Finitely Presented Functors 3
    TENSOR PRODUCTS OF FINITELY PRESENTED FUNCTORS MARTIN BIES AND SEBASTIAN POSUR Abstract. We study right exact tensor products on the category of finitely presented functors. As our main technical tool, we use a multilinear version of the universal property of so-called Freyd categories. Furthermore, we compare our constructions with the Day convolution of arbitrary functors. Our results are stated in a constructive way and give a unified approach for the implementation of tensor products in various contexts. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. Freyd categories and their universal property 3 2.1. Preliminaries: Freyd categories 3 2.2. Multilinear functors 4 2.3. The multilinear 2-categorical universal property of Freyd categories 5 3. Right exact monoidal structures on Freyd categories 9 3.1. Monoidal structures on Freyd categories 9 3.2. F. p. promonoidal structures on additive categories 12 3.3. From f. p. promonoidal structures to right exact monoidal structures 14 4. Connection with Day convolution 17 4.1. Introduction to Day convolution 17 4.2. Day convolution of finitely presented functors 18 5. Applications and examples 20 5.1. Examples in the category of finitely presented modules 20 5.2. Monoidal structures of iterated Freyd categories 21 arXiv:1909.00172v1 [math.CT] 31 Aug 2019 5.3. Free abelian categories 21 5.4. Implementations of monoidal structures 22 References 27 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 18E10, 18E05, 18A25, Key words and phrases. Freyd category, finitely presented functor, computable abelian category. The work of M. Bies is supported by the Wiener-Anspach foundation. M. Bies thanks the University of Siegen and the GAP Singular Meeting and School for hospitality during this project.
    [Show full text]
  • A NOTE on DIRECT PRODUCTS and EXT1 CONTRAVARIANT FUNCTORS 1. Introduction Commuting Properties of Hom and Ext Functors with Resp
    A NOTE ON DIRECT PRODUCTS AND EXT1 CONTRAVARIANT FUNCTORS FLAVIU POP AND CLAUDIU VALCULESCU Abstract. In this paper we prove, using inequalities between infinite car- dinals, that, if R is an hereditary ring, the contravariant derived functor 1 ExtR(−;G) commutes with direct products if and only if G is an injective R-module. 1. Introduction Commuting properties of Hom and Ext functors with respect to direct sums and direct products are very important in Module Theory. It is well known that, if G is an R-module (in this paper all modules are right R-modules), the covariant Hom-functor HomR(G; −) : Mod-R ! Mod-Z preserves direct products, i.e. the natural homomorphism Y Y φF : HomR(G; Ni) ! HomR(G; Ni) i2I i2I Q induced by the family HomR(G; pi), where pi : j2I Nj ! Ni are the canonical projections associated to direct product, is an isomorphism, for any family of R- modules F = (Ni)i2I . On the other hand, the contravariant Hom-functor HomR(−;G) : Mod-R ! Mod-Z does not preserve, in general, the direct products. More precisely, if F = (Mi)i2I is a family of R-modules, then the natural homomorphism Y Y F : HomR( Mi;G) ! HomR(Mi;G) i2I i2I Q induced by the family HomR(ui;G), where ui : Mi ! j2I Mj are the canonical injections associated to the direct product, is not, in general, an isomorphism. We Q note that if we replace direct products i2I Mi by direct sums ⊕i2I Mi, a similar discussion about commuting properties leads to important notions in Module The- ory: small and self-small modules, respectively slender and self-slender modules, and the structure of these modules can be very complicated (see [3], [9], [11]).
    [Show full text]
  • Category Theory Course
    Category Theory Course John Baez September 3, 2019 1 Contents 1 Category Theory: 4 1.1 Definition of a Category....................... 5 1.1.1 Categories of mathematical objects............. 5 1.1.2 Categories as mathematical objects............ 6 1.2 Doing Mathematics inside a Category............... 10 1.3 Limits and Colimits.......................... 11 1.3.1 Products............................ 11 1.3.2 Coproducts.......................... 14 1.4 General Limits and Colimits..................... 15 2 Equalizers, Coequalizers, Pullbacks, and Pushouts (Week 3) 16 2.1 Equalizers............................... 16 2.2 Coequalizers.............................. 18 2.3 Pullbacks................................ 19 2.4 Pullbacks and Pushouts....................... 20 2.5 Limits for all finite diagrams.................... 21 3 Week 4 22 3.1 Mathematics Between Categories.................. 22 3.2 Natural Transformations....................... 25 4 Maps Between Categories 28 4.1 Natural Transformations....................... 28 4.1.1 Examples of natural transformations........... 28 4.2 Equivalence of Categories...................... 28 4.3 Adjunctions.............................. 29 4.3.1 What are adjunctions?.................... 29 4.3.2 Examples of Adjunctions.................. 30 4.3.3 Diagonal Functor....................... 31 5 Diagrams in a Category as Functors 33 5.1 Units and Counits of Adjunctions................. 39 6 Cartesian Closed Categories 40 6.1 Evaluation and Coevaluation in Cartesian Closed Categories. 41 6.1.1 Internalizing Composition................. 42 6.2 Elements................................ 43 7 Week 9 43 7.1 Subobjects............................... 46 8 Symmetric Monoidal Categories 50 8.1 Guest lecture by Christina Osborne................ 50 8.1.1 What is a Monoidal Category?............... 50 8.1.2 Going back to the definition of a symmetric monoidal category.............................. 53 2 9 Week 10 54 9.1 The subobject classifier in Graph.................
    [Show full text]
  • A Concrete Introduction to Category Theory
    A CONCRETE INTRODUCTION TO CATEGORIES WILLIAM R. SCHMITT DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS THE GEORGE WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY WASHINGTON, D.C. 20052 Contents 1. Categories 2 1.1. First Definition and Examples 2 1.2. An Alternative Definition: The Arrows-Only Perspective 7 1.3. Some Constructions 8 1.4. The Category of Relations 9 1.5. Special Objects and Arrows 10 1.6. Exercises 14 2. Functors and Natural Transformations 16 2.1. Functors 16 2.2. Full and Faithful Functors 20 2.3. Contravariant Functors 21 2.4. Products of Categories 23 3. Natural Transformations 26 3.1. Definition and Some Examples 26 3.2. Some Natural Transformations Involving the Cartesian Product Functor 31 3.3. Equivalence of Categories 32 3.4. Categories of Functors 32 3.5. The 2-Category of all Categories 33 3.6. The Yoneda Embeddings 37 3.7. Representable Functors 41 3.8. Exercises 44 4. Adjoint Functors and Limits 45 4.1. Adjoint Functors 45 4.2. The Unit and Counit of an Adjunction 50 4.3. Examples of adjunctions 57 1 1. Categories 1.1. First Definition and Examples. Definition 1.1. A category C consists of the following data: (i) A set Ob(C) of objects. (ii) For every pair of objects a, b ∈ Ob(C), a set C(a, b) of arrows, or mor- phisms, from a to b. (iii) For all triples a, b, c ∈ Ob(C), a composition map C(a, b) ×C(b, c) → C(a, c) (f, g) 7→ gf = g · f. (iv) For each object a ∈ Ob(C), an arrow 1a ∈ C(a, a), called the identity of a.
    [Show full text]