The Concept of Statutory Law in EU Perspective

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Concept of Statutory Law in EU Perspective Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies Volume 12 Issue 2 Article 8 Summer 2005 The Concept of Statutory Law in EU Perspective Francesico Bilancia University of Chieti-Pescara Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ijgls Part of the European Law Commons, International Law Commons, and the Legislation Commons Recommended Citation Bilancia, Francesico (2005) "The Concept of Statutory Law in EU Perspective," Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies: Vol. 12 : Iss. 2 , Article 8. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ijgls/vol12/iss2/8 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Concept of Statutory Law in EU Perspective FRANCESCO BILANCIA* I. THE HISTORICAL-POLITICAL MEANING OF LAW IN THE CONSTITUTIONAL TRADITION OF CONTINENTAL EUROPE A. From Liberal State to the 1930s The current meaning of the political concept of law is the result of a long and complex historical evolution. The underlying premise is that law does not always follow the development of democratic values. On the contrary, the politi- cal datum of the central role of law is constant in the system of the sources of the right of the state, as law is usually the most important source. Thus, our reflec- tion must look for the political roots of the centrality of the law in contemporary legal systems. We must understand why the doctrines of constitutionalism have assigned to the centrality of the law a role and meaning of fundamental instru- ment for the democratic construction of the state's legal system. In order to narrow the scope of our analysis, I would start from the liberal state of the nineteenth century. Therefore, I avoid confronting, for example, the study of the concept of law according to the historical-political doctrines of vol- untarism (Volontarismo), or the study of the ethical-religious foundations of law-theories that we still find applied today in both totalitarian and theocratic systems. In different contexts, the law can find its foundation in institutional pluralism,' *Doctorate in Public and Constitutional Law, University of Rome "La Sapienza," 1994; Attor- ney at Law; Professore straordinario di Diritto costituzionale, University of Chieti-Pescara "G. D'Annunzio." This comment was delivered at a symposium on Back to Government? The Plural- istic Deficit in the Decisionmaking Processes and Before the Courts, June 2004, in response to Francesca Bignami, Pluralism, Corporatism and Republicanism in Domestic Public Law: The Impli- cationsfor a European Right to Civil Society Participation. 1. See, e.g., MAGNA CARTA arts. 12, 39 (1215). The Magna Carta was granted by King John in 1215 and established the seeds of the political foundations of the current notion of the rule of law. Indeed, article 12 established the principle "no taxation without representation," and article 39 based every restriction of the rights of barons on the judgment of their peers according to the law of their land. FRANCESCO BILANCIA in common law,2 or in its own representative character. But from the bourgeois state on, the law assumes the essential meaning of the political and legal center of the system of the sources of rights. As it is well known, the stabilization of the legal doctrine founded on the centrality of the political concept of law arose especially in France and Germany between the middle of the nineteenth century and the 1930s. However, the sub- stantial meaning of this political act, an act enforcing the political choices of gov- ernment, was still not the one presupposed by the contemporary theories of democracy. This is particularly true in Germany, where the supremacy of the law is due to its attribution to the state, to the sovereign body (the will), and to the supreme institutions. In the first meaning, the centrality of law is justified inasmuch as it is the child of the sovereignty of the Reich-"the law is the expression of the power of the State"' (of the Staatsgewalt)4-regardless of how the sovereign functions are differentiated and allocated by the legal system. In this context, the role of the representative body (Parliament) and of the monarch complicate the exercise of the sovereign function. While the former is responsible for defining the content of laws, the latter holds the actual power of adoption through the sanction of the act of command directed at the subjects, in the form of law. 5 The famous conflict between the Parliament and the Crown, which oc- curred in Germany in the second half of the nineteenth century, yielded the cat- 2. The laws of the Parliament themselves-or even better, of the King in Parliament-cannot be entirely compared to the laws of the continental system. Every binding act of the Parliament, in fact, even if it is not prescriptive, is reconverted according to a hermeneutic (airtight) process in the logic of the system of common law (above the mixed English Government). See Giuseppe G. Floridia, Fortuna e crisi del governo misto nella Costituzione inigese, in MATERIALI PER UNA STORIA DELLA CULTURA GIURIDICA 305 (2000). 3. Paul Laband, Das Budgetrecht nach den Bestimmungen der Preussischen Vefassungsurkunde unter besonderer Beriicksichtigungder Verfassung des Norddeutschen Bundes, in ZEIT FUR GESETZ- GEBUNG UND RECHTSPFLEFE IN PREUSSEN 625 (1870). 4. Staatsgewalt translates to the power of the State, in the sense that it is used in this paragraph. 5. The famous conflict between Parliament and Crown is comprised of two distinct events: the conflict between Landtag and Crown, 1862-1866; and the conflict between Reichstag and Govern- ment, 1878. See Carlo Esposito, Legge, in Nuovo DIGESTO ITALIANO 720 (Mariano d'Amelio ed., 1938). See also Carlo Roehrssen, GOVERNO, LEGGE, POLITICA 135 (1969) and Clementine Forte, Pre- sentazione to Rudolph Gneist & Georg Jellinek, Legge e bilancio & Legge e decreto, in CONTROVERSiE COSTITUZIONALI IN BASE ALLA CRISI DEL GOVERNO PRUSSIANO DEL MARZO 1878, at v (Clemente Forte trans., ed., 1997) (1879) on the meaning and value of "budget decision." This was the responsibility of Parliament, but it was approved in a different way than the law, which was adopted together by mmmm STATUTORY LAW IN EU PERSPECTIVE egories of formal and material law. The comparison between these two concepts will successively illustrate the interpretation of the historical evolution of the re- lations between law, parliament, and government, concerning the approval of the state budget. The political concept of state will be linked to the formal con- cept of law because "only the Sovereign or the supreme State power can issue laws."6 The circumstance in which only the sovereign or the supreme state power can adopt formal legislative acts does not theoretically follow from the concept of law, but from the notion of a state's effective establishment in a given political community. On the contrary, laws in a material sense can be qualified as all the sources authorized by the system to issue legal norms or rules-hence, also the sources of autonomy. From this context derives, as an immediate consequence, the legal relevance of the form of the act of will that integrates the law. Thus, while in a material sense, legislative right can be considered as a concept equivalent tojus scriptum, in a formal sense, such equivalence will only be true for the written law adopted on the basis of the public consensus (Zustimmung). This leads to a meaningful conclusion: laws, in a formal sense, are also those acts ascribed to the state's will (Willensakte des Staates), for which the consensus of the representative organs (the Parliament) is necessary; yet, they are acts that could not have normative content. Paul Laband claims this model has its own underlying political justification in the theory of division of powers. But, according to Laband's theory, the politi- cal concept of representation, in reality, does not assume a central role in the cat- egorization of the law, which is instead based on the mere form of the act. In fact, the word "law," in the end, assumes the mere formal meaning of an "act pro- duced resorting to a specific procedure,"' on the basis of the political representa- the King and Landtag. From this situation came the theoretical problem of the distinction between "formal law" and "material law." See Rudolph Gneist, Legge e bilancio, in CONTROVERSIE COSTITUZIONALI IN BASE ALLA CRISI DEL GOVERNO PRUSSIANO DEL MARZO 1878,supra, at 25, 36, 44, 85, 89; see also Georg Jellinek, Legge edecreto, in CONTROVERSIE COSTITUZIONAI IN BASE ALLA CRISI DEL GOVERNO PRUSSIANO DEL MARZO 1878, supra, at 230, 237, 254. In opposition to Laband, see the doc- trine of Hermann Heller, Il concetto di legge della Costituzionedi Weimar, in LA SOVRANITA ED ALTRI SCRITTI SULLA DOTTRINA DEL DIRITTO E DELLO STATo 314,340 (Pasquale Pasquino trans., 1987) (1928). 6. PAUL LABAND, DAS STAATSRECHT DES DEUTSCHEN REICHES 11 (4th ed. 1991). 7. On the conceptual difference between "law in a formal meaning" and "law in a material meaning," see also Jellinek,supra note 5, at 230, 237; Heller, supra note 5, at 314, 340. 8. LABAND,SUpra note 6, at 29, 32, 42. FRANCESCO BILANCIA tion (the Parliament) that expresses its own consensus about the content of the state's declarations of will. This value, though, results only because the laws are adopted through the sanction of the Kaiser, regardless of the content of such acts. The two concepts are radically different: one indicative of the form of the decla- ration of will, and the other indicative of its content.
Recommended publications
  • Industrial Property
    ANNUAL SURVEY OF CANADIAN LAW INDUSTRIAL PROPERTY William L. Hayhurst, Q.C. * I. INTRODUCTION ....................................... 394 II. RECENT LEGISLATION ................................. 395 III. PROPOSED LEGISLATION ................................ 398 IV . PATENTS ............................................ 399 A. Matters in Which the Patent Office has OriginalJurisdiction ............................... 399 1. Conflicts ...................................... 399 2. Compulsory Licences ............................ 400 3. Subject Matter Capable of Being Patented .......... 401 (a) Printed M atter .............................. 402 (b) Gam es ..................................... 402 (c) Mental Processes and Computer Programs ...... 402 (d) Living M atter ............................... 405 (e) Medical Treatment of Animals and Humans ...... 407 (f) Medical Inventions .......................... 408 (g) The Progeny of Sandoz v. Gilcross ............. 410 (h) Aggregations and Exhausted Combinations ...... 412 (i) Synergism .............................. 412 (ii) M ixtures ............................... 412 (iii) The Aggregative or Unnecessary Addition ... 413 4. D ivision ....................................... 4 15 5. R eissue ....................................... 4 16 6. D isclaimer .................................... 417 B. Substantive Matters in the Courts .................... 418 1. Intervening Rights .............................. 418 2. Personal Liability of Persons in Control of CorporateInfringers .........................
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Law and Legal Reasoning Law Is
    CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION TO LAW AND LEGAL REASONING LAW IS "MAN MADE" IT CHANGES OVER TIME TO ACCOMMODATE SOCIETY'S NEEDS LAW IS MADE BY LEGISLATURE LAW IS INTERPRETED BY COURTS TO DETERMINE 1)WHETHER IT IS "CONSTITUTIONAL" 2)WHO IS RIGHT OR WRONG THERE IS A PROCESS WHICH MUST BE FOLLOWED (CALLED "PROCEDURAL LAW") I. Thomas Jefferson: "The study of the law qualifies a man to be useful to himself, to his neighbors, and to the public." II. Ask Several Students to give their definition of "Law." A. Even after years and thousands of dollars, "LAW" still is not easy to define B. What does law Consist of ? Law consists of enforceable rule governing relationships among individuals and between individuals and their society. 1. Students Need to Understand. a. The law is a set of general ideas b. When these general ideas are applied, a judge cannot fit a case to suit a rule; he must fit (or find) a rule to suit the unique case at hand. c. The judge must also supply legitimate reasons for his decisions. C. So, How was the Law Created. The law considered in this text are "man made" law. This law can (and will) change over time in response to the changes and needs of society. D. Example. Grandma, who is 87 years old, walks into a pawn shop. She wants to sell her ring that has been in the family for 200 years. Grandma asks the dealer, "how much will you give me for this ring." The dealer, in good faith, tells Grandma he doesn't know what kind of metal is in the ring, but he will give her $150.
    [Show full text]
  • Federalizing Contract Law
    LCB_24_1_Article_5_Plass_Correction (Do Not Delete) 3/6/2020 10:06 AM FEDERALIZING CONTRACT LAW by Stephen A. Plass* Contract law is generally understood as state common law, supplemented by the Second Restatement of Contracts and Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code. It is regarded as an expression of personal liberty, anchored in the bar- gain and consideration model of the 19th century or classical period. However, for some time now, non-bargained or adhesion contracts have been the norm, and increasingly, the adjudication of legal rights and contractual remedies is controlled by privately determined arbitration rules. The widespread adoption of arbitral adjudication by businesses has been enthusiastically endorsed by the Supreme Court as consonant with the Federal Arbitration Act (“FAA”). How- ever, Court precedents have concluded that only bilateral or individualized arbitration promotes the goals of the FAA, while class arbitration is destruc- tive. Businesses and the Court have theorized that bilateral arbitration is an efficient process that reduces the transaction costs of all parties thereby permit- ting firms to reduce prices, create jobs, and innovate or improve products. But empirical research tells a different story. This Article discusses the constitu- tional contours of crafting common law for the FAA and its impact on state and federal laws. It shows that federal common law rules crafted for the FAA can operate to deny consumers and workers the neoclassical contractual guar- antee of a minimum adequate remedy and rob the federal and state govern- ments of billions of dollars in tax revenue. From FAA precedents the Article distills new rules of contract formation, interpretation, and enforcement and shows how these new rules undermine neoclassical limits on private control of legal remedies.
    [Show full text]
  • AJS Review Barry Scott Wimpfheimer. Narrating The
    AJS Review http://journals.cambridge.org/AJS Additional services for AJS Review: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Barry Scott Wimpfheimer. Narrating the Law: A Poetics of Talmudic Legal Stories. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2011. 248 pp. Steven D. Fraade AJS Review / Volume 37 / Issue 01 / April 2013, pp 135 ­ 139 DOI: 10.1017/S0364009413000093, Published online: 17 May 2013 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0364009413000093 How to cite this article: Steven D. Fraade (2013). AJS Review, 37, pp 135­139 doi:10.1017/ S0364009413000093 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/AJS, IP address: 128.36.43.134 on 22 May 2013 AJS Review 37:1 (April 2013), 135–176 © 2013 Association for Jewish Studies BOOK REVIEWS FEATURED REVIEWS Barry Scott Wimpfheimer. Narrating the Law: A Poetics of Talmudic Legal Stories. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2011. 248 pp. doi:10.1017/S0364009413000093 Barry Wimpfheimer makes an insightfully original and valuable contri- bution to the growing number of studies of the relation between law and narrative (halakhah and aggadah in rabbinic terminology) in ancient Judaism, as in Judaism and the humanities more broadly. His focus is on “talmudic legal stories,” that is, on narratives whose subjects are legal actors, which are set within a mainly legal setting in the Babylonian Talmud, and which, therefore, both draw meaning from and contribute meaning to that broader literary context. These stories have often baffled (or annoyed) previous commentators on the Talmud precisely because they complicate any neat division between rabbinic law and narrative and the con- ventional roles assigned to each.
    [Show full text]
  • The Putative Spouse and Marriage by Estoppel Doctrines: an "End Run Around Marriage" Or Just a Marriage?
    Child and Family Law Journal Volume 8 Issue 1 Article 3 3-27-2020 The Putative Spouse and Marriage by Estoppel Doctrines: An "End Run Around Marriage" or Just a Marriage? Dana E. Prescott, Esq., Ph.D Follow this and additional works at: https://lawpublications.barry.edu/cflj Part of the Elder Law Commons, Family Law Commons, Juvenile Law Commons, and the Other Law Commons Recommended Citation Prescott, Esq., Ph.D, Dana E. (2020) "The Putative Spouse and Marriage by Estoppel Doctrines: An "End Run Around Marriage" or Just a Marriage?," Child and Family Law Journal: Vol. 8 : Iss. 1 , Article 3. Available at: https://lawpublications.barry.edu/cflj/vol8/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Barry Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Child and Family Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Barry Law. The Putative Spouse and Marriage by Estoppel Doctrines: An “End Run Around Marriage” or Just a Marriage? Dana E. Prescott, Esq., Ph.D* I. INTRODUCTION For generations in the United States, each state determined the definition of a legally recognized marriage.1 Indeed, the United States Supreme Court long ago held that marriage “has always been subject to the control of the [state] legislature.”2 For the most part, these early notions of “federalism”3 permitted states to constrain the definition of a lawful marriage. States did so without much public controversy; at least when consistent with socially and legally *Dana E. Prescott is licensed to practice in Maine and Massachusetts and a partner with Prescott, Jamieson, & Murphy Law Group LLC, Saco, Maine.
    [Show full text]
  • Jewish Law and Litigation in the Secular Courts of the Late Medieval Mediterranean Rena N
    Jewish Law and Litigation in the Secular Courts of the Late Medieval Mediterranean Rena N. Lauer* Abstract Although medieval rabbinic law generally forbade Jews from suing their co-religionists in state courts, this practice was widely accepted among some Mediterranean Jewish com- munities. This study focuses on one such community, the Jews of Venetian Crete’s capital city of Candia, during the century following the Black Death (ca. 1350-1450). Court records indicate that Candiote Jews quite often sued each other in Venice’s coloni- al courts. Unlike many other medieval Jewish communities, the rabbinical leadership of Candia took this intra-Jewish litigation as a given. Moreover, these leaders themselves ac- cessed Venetian justice to sue fellow Jews. Among the factors that motivated Jewish use of the Venetian court was a special accommodation given to Cretan Jews: when litigation in the colonial court dealt with Jews’ marriages or divorces, judges were obligated to ad- judicate according to Jewish law. Many Candiote Jews utilized this personal law privilege, and the Venetian court actively implemented it. The Catholic judges of the colonial court in Crete learned about Jewish law mostly from the litigants themselves, and not from a panel of rabbinic experts, giving these Jewish litigants significant agency in shaping not only the outcome of their marriage and divorce cases but also the government’s under- standing of Jewish law. * * * Normative rabbinic consensus in medieval Europe squarely forbade Jews from suing each other in secular or so-called “gentile” courts. Instead of airing intracommunal grievances before state judiciaries, Jews were directed to settle their disputes in their local Jewish court (beit din).1 The responsa2 of the unrivaled Barcelonan legal authority Rabbi Solomon ibn Adret (the Rashba, d.
    [Show full text]
  • Statutory Law
    Basic Briefing on statutory law A statute, strictly speaking, is an Act of Parliament. There are two kinds: public and private, but we are only concerned with public acts such as the Medicines Act, the Misuse of Drugs Act, etc. Acts are usually called primary legislation since they are the primary authority for legislation in the UK and have been through the full parliamentary debate procedure. Statutory law (or statute law) is also used to describe legislation which is subsidiary to an Act, normally in the form of Regulations or Orders. These are collectively known as statutory Instruments (or S.I.s) or subordinate or secondary legislation. Recent legislation can be located on www.hmso.gov.uk/legis.htm Here you will find details of all Acts and SIs enacted since the late 1990s, together with draft acts (i.e. bills) and SIs. Most Acts are now accompanied by Explanatory Notes which contain useful briefings from civil servants on what the bill is intended to achieve and how it relates to earlier legislation – however these notes are not part of the law iteslf. When reading a statutory instrument, start at the end with the explanatory notes! How law is made Proposals to introduce new legislation come forward in the form of a bill. Most are government bills but sometimes they are put forward by individual members of parliament (private members’ bills). Before a bill is proposed, the government will normally signal its intentions in a “white paper”. Sometimes this is preceded by a discussion document, called a “green paper”. The programme of most primary legislation is outlined in the Queen’s speech when Parliament enters a new session in the Autumn.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is This Thing Called Jewish Law? in October, Professor Noah Feldman of Harvard Law School Visited TBA
    Education jly icEdid xywd YourYour Jewish Jewish (Internet) Connection Connection! Brought to you by the Lifelong Learning Committee Written by Linda S Trapasso What Is This Thing Called Jewish Law? In October, Professor Noah Feldman of Harvard Law School visited TBA. He and the rabbi discussed several US Supreme Court decisions that touched on religion and gay marriage. I found this discussion fascinating and thought I’d look at Jewish law. So, do Jews have a body of law, or do they live with a mindset and way of life? The latter is how Aish.com frames their series of articles on Practical Jewish Law. At MyJewishLearning. com, there are articles on the Orthodox, Conservative, and Reform approaches to halakhah. In December 2013, Mosaic magazine published an article by Joshua Berman, and the responses to it, about Jewish law or halakhah. Though two years old, the issues and concerns are still relevant today. What constitutes religious law? How do we interpret it? Where and when did it start? It seems to have started as common law, using various systems of interpretation (such as midrash) that allowed the law to develop over time, responding to the needs of the day. As Berman states, “How then did Judaism come to embrace the legal codes of Moses Maimonides (1138- 1204) and Joseph Karo (1488-1575)? When and why did Jewish jurisprudence turn toward statutory law?” For a complete history, go to Oxford Scholarship Online and review An Introduction to History and Sources of Jewish Law. The table of contents is a timeline of the development of Jewish law.
    [Show full text]
  • Relationship Between Statutory Law and Common Law
    Relationship Between Statutory Law And Common Law Intercollegiate and massed Abdul repels some passion so rough! Floury and limbless Rolland divaricate her mercurialism sulphurate alright or serpentinizes andante, is Hiram biogenous? Concussive Gustaf chelates some phlogopite after clashing Rocky bound daily. No You're Not In one Common-Law sign After 7 Years Together. The box Law was Self-Defense or North Carolina North. Which States Recognize Common after Marriage Nolo. Private lobby to harvest public recognized and responsible national association. Animals usually visible on the interstate aspects of our relationships to animals. These differences between common goods or regulation? How much statutory law created Statutory period is created by the Congress. 2013 FEDERAL COMMON council OF STATUTORY INTERPRETATION 755. What access the difference between statute and civil law. What split the difference between eternal law during civil law. Many different from control judicial resolution. Equal weight under native Law. Common law is pocket that is derived from judicial decisions instead split from statutes American courts originally fashioned common law rules based on English. History many Common death and Statute Law in Canada. Learn about through law marriages and find fibre what states recognize them. Which rules control if their conflicts between two maybe more sources of law. Family law and common act. It cannot be common law is fond of law and common law of the way? Cannot do determined based on existing statutes or written rules of law. This endeavor is used in contradistinction to through common law. The relationship was subject to this privilege only relatively fewer and unspoken.
    [Show full text]
  • Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation Richard Kay University of Connecticut School of Law
    University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Faculty Articles and Papers School of Law 2009 Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation Richard Kay University of Connecticut School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Kay, Richard, "Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation" (2009). Faculty Articles and Papers. 5. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers/5 +(,121/,1( Citation: 103 Nw. U. L. Rev. 703 2009 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Mon Aug 15 16:57:29 2016 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0029-3571 Copyright 2009 by Northwestern University School of Law Printedin U.S.A. Northwestern University Law Review Vol. 103, No. 2 ORIGINAL INTENTION AND PUBLIC MEANING IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION Richard S. Kay* INTRO D U CTION ............................................................................................................. 703 I. THE FLIGHT FROM INTENTION .............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation Kevin M
    Vanderbilt University Law School Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 2004 The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation Kevin M. Stack Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kevin M. Stack, The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation, 75 Colorado Law Review. 1 (2004) Available at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications/223 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UNIVERSITY OF COLORADO LAW REVIEW Volume 75, Number 1 2004 THE DIVERGENCE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION KEVIN M. STACK* INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................... 2 I. THE CONVERGENCE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION IN CONTEMPORARY THEORY ........................... 10 A. Scalia's Textualist Originalism........................................ 10 B. Eskridge's Dynamism ......................................................... 15 II. THE DEMOCRATIC FOUNDATIONS OF ORIGINALISM IN CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION ..................... 22 A. MajoritarianOriginalism ................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Amicus Curiae Submission of Canadian Generic
    IN THE MATTER OF AN ARBITRATION UNDER CHAPTER ELEVEN OF THE NORTH AMERICAN FREE TRADE AGREEMENT AND THE UNCITRAL ARBITRATION RULES (1976) BETWEEN: ELI LILLY AND COMPANY Claimant/Investor AND: GOVERNMENT OF CANADA Respondent/Party (Case No. UNCT/14/2) AMICUS CURIAE SUBMISSIONS BY THE CANADIAN GENERIC PHARMACEUTICAL ASSOCIATION Jonathan Stainsby Daniel Hynes Aitken Klee LLP 181 Bay Street, Suite 3350 Toronto, Ontario Canada, M5J 2T3 Tel: (647) 317-6868 Fax: (613) 695-5854 E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected] Amicus Curiae Submissions CGPA Eli Lilly and Company, Claimant/Investor and Canada, Respondent/Party (Case No. UNCT/14/2) AMICUS CURIAE SUBMISSIONS of the CANADIAN GENERIC PHARMACEUTICAL ASSOCIATION 1. The Canadian Generic Pharmaceutical Association (‘CGPA’) appreciates the opportunity to provide these submissions in connection with the arbitration between Eli Lilly and Company (‘Lilly’) and Canada. The CGPA’s motivation and basis for seeking to file an amicus brief on this arbitration, as well as the significant public interest in the outcome of this arbitration, are set out in the CGPA’s application for leave to file these submissions and will not be re-iterated here. Preliminary Issue 2. Investor-state arbitrations under NAFTA are not intended as ‘blanket protection’ for investors against the mere disappointment arising from rejected complaints before national courts or from dealing with national authorities.1 The Tribunal should be mindful that Lilly’s arguments, as they relate to Canadian patent law, have been fully canvassed and adjudicated by Canadian Courts, the very courts charged with interpreting and applying domestic Canadian patent law.
    [Show full text]