Consequences, Norms, and Inaction: a Critical Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Consequences, Norms, and Inaction: a Critical Analysis Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 15, No. 3, May 2020, pp. 421–442 Consequences, norms, and inaction: A critical analysis Jonathan Baron∗ Geoffrey P. Goodwin† Abstract Gawronski, Armstrong, Conway, Friesdorf and Hütter (2017, GACFH) presented a model of choices in utilitarian moral dilemmas, those in which following a moral principle or norm (the deontological response) leads to worse consequences than violating the principle (the utilitarian response). In standard utilitarian dilemmas, the utilitarian option involves action (which causes some harm in order to prevent greater harm), and the deontological response, omission. GACFH propose that responses in such dilemmas arise in three different ways: a psychological process leading to a deontological choice, a different process leading to a utilitarian choice, or a bias toward inaction or action. GACFH attempt to separate these three processes with new dilemmas in which action and omission are switched, and dilemmas in which the utilitarian and deontological processes lead to the same choice. They conclude that utilitarian and deontological responses are indeed separable, and that past research has missed this fact by treating them as naturally opposed. We argue that a bias toward harmful inaction is best understood as an explanation of deontological responding rather than as an alternative process. It thus should be included as an explanation of deontological responding, not an alternative response type. We also argue that GACFH’s results can be largely explained in terms of subjects’ unwillingness to accept the researchers’ assumptions about which consequence is worse and which course of action is consistent with a moral norm. This problem is almost inherent in the attempt to switch act and omission while maintaining equivalent norms. We support this argument with data from experiments with new and old scenarios, in which we asked subjects to judge both norms and consequences. We also find that GACFH’s results are not as consistent as they appear to be in the paper. Keywords: utilitarianism, deontology, omission bias, process dissociation 1 Introduction some individuals, refraining from directly causing this harm thereby becomes more attractive than causing it, even though A great deal of research has now established that many peo- the overall consequences are worse. These cases are called ple’s moral judgments do not follow utilitarian principles. “sacrificial dilemmas.” In one sort of demonstration (among many), subjects are The usual analysis of these dilemmas is that they pit utili- asked to compare two options, one of which leads to a better tarian responding (responding in terms of the greater good) result than the other, e.g., fewer deaths, but many subjects against deontological responding, where deontology refers choose the other option, thus violating the utilitarian prin- to a category of moral theories that emphasize properties of ciple of doing the most good, or the least harm, aggregated action other than their consequences, such as whether an ac- across those affected. In order to get this result, the more tion violates basic rights, or whether an action conflicts with harmful option must be made attractive in some way that is a required duty. Deontological theories can justify not push- irrelevant to the utilitarian calculation.1 Usually this involves ing the man in a variety of ways, but most of them involve a telling subjects that the harm from the utilitarian option must prohibition of active killing, whatever the consequences. be actively and directly caused by the decision maker, e.g., Gawronski, Armstrong, Conway, Friesdorf & Hütter pushing a man off of a bridge, to his death, in order to stop (2017, henceforth GACFH) report an experimental analy- a trolley that will otherwise kill several other people. For sis of sacrificial dilemmas, using a new method, which they call the CNI model because it considers three possible deter- minants of responses: Consequences, Norms, and Inaction. We thanks Andreas Glöcker, the reviewers, and Ilana Ritov for helpful comments. The model is similar to, and builds upon, an earlier model Copyright: © 2020. The authors license this article under the terms of based on the idea of process dissociation (PD; Conway & the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License. Gawronski, 2013). In this paper, we discuss largely the sin- ∗Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, 3720 Walnut St., Philadelphia, PA, 19104. Email: [email protected]. ORCID: 0000- gle paper that introduces the CNI model, but some of our 0003-1001-9947. comments apply to other papers using the CNI model or the †Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania. PD model as applied to moral judgments. We do not at- 1 We use the term “utilitarian” rather than “consequentialist” because the tempt to discuss or even enumerate all these papers (many latter is a broader class of principles, some of which ignore the number of people affected (e.g., Rawls’s [1971] “difference principle”). For most of of which have appeared while the present paper was under the dilemmas at issue here, numbers are highly relevant to the conflict. review.). Instead, we intend this paper as an expression of 421 Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 15, No. 3, May 2020 Consequences, norms, and inaction: A critical analysis 422 general concern about the use of both methods to study moral from a preference for inaction, for the other (in which both judgment. norms and consequences prescribe action). In a typical sacrificial dilemma, consequences favor act- In this paper, we discuss two general concerns with this ing, e.g., pushing the man, a bias toward inaction opposes approach. We begin with the main philosophical assumption action, and moral norms usually also oppose action (e.g., made by GACFH, which is that a bias against action is not “don’t kill people”). GACFH further suppose that deontolog- deontological. We argue that whether an option involves ical and utilitarian responses are not simply poles of a single action or omission, in itself, is a feature of the sort that dimension but, rather, alternative and independent ways of deontology can take into account but utilitarianism cannot. thinking about the dilemmas. In particular, GACFH assume We then discuss the difficulty of constructing items that meet that the basic utilitarian principle is based on consequences the new requirements, and other problems with assessing the and the basic deontological principle is based on norms. In relationship between model parameters and other variables. their view, a preference for inaction (or action) is separate, We then present evidence that the apparent results of the different from either approach. In standard sacrificial dilem- CNI model are affected by subjects’ lack of agreement with mas, they argue that an apparent utilitarian response could the experimenters about which norms and consequences are arise either from a focus on consequences or from a bias relevant for the choice, as well as by inconsistencies in the toward action, and an apparent deontological response could data. arise either from a norm or a bias toward inaction. However, we agree that the CNI model raises an impor- To assess the role of each of the three components of the tant question about the kind of deontological judgments that model, GACFH use a design in which they manipulate the lead to apparent rejections of utilitarian options, specifically pairing of norms and consequences with action or inaction. whether they arise from norms that concern action vs. omis- In this design, the consequences of action are manipulated sion as well as other features. We review other literature that so that action is better than inaction in half of the items, and tries to answer this question along with related questions worse in the other half. Orthogonally, norms either forbid about the nature of apparent deontological responses. (proscribe) or require (prescribe) action. These manipula- tions give rise to three new versions of the standard sacrificial dilemma. In the standard version of a sacrificial dilemma, ac- 2 Omission bias and deontological tion has better consequences than inaction, but it is forbidden reasoning by a norm. In a new, reversed version, action is worse than inaction, but it is required by a norm. In cases of this sort, Utilitarianism, as a principle of choice, says that we should the action in question is one of preventing someone else’s choose the option with the best overall consequences. A action, or reversing an action already chosen, or reversing minimal definition of deontology, consistent with the litera- its effects. In two further versions, norms and consequences ture in both philosophy and psychology, is that it consists of align — such that both dictate either action, or alternatively, moral rules or principles about choices (acts or omissions) inaction. Thus, consequences and norms are congruent for other than those concerned with consequences. Most char- two of the four resulting cases and incongruent (conflicting) acteristically, it concerns properties of acts that make them for the other two. The pattern of subjects’ responses to the proscribed or forbidden. It can also concern properties of four dilemmas indicates how much each principle is driving acts that make them prescribed (required), as in the case of their responses. If action is always chosen, or inaction is al- duties. The rules may be, but need not be, absolute; some of ways chosen, then the responses are driven by a bias toward them may be overridden by other rules or by consequences action or inaction, not by either norms or consequences. (Ross, 1930). Some philosophers add additional specifica- The PD model, on which the CNI model builds, uses tions to what they count as deontology. But, in general, we only one type of congruent case, in which both norms and can think of deontology as consisting of rules that must be consequences prescribe inaction. For example, the act of considered in addition to, or instead of, utilitarian outcomes.
Recommended publications
  • Contributors
    Contributors Edward J. McCaffery is Robert C. Packard Trustee Chair in Law and Po- litical Science at the University of Southern California and visiting pro- fessor of law and economics at the California Institute of Technology. Joel Slemrod is Paul W. McCracken Collegiate Professor of Business Economics and Public Policy, director of the Office of Tax Policy Research in the Stephen M. Ross School of Business, and professor of economics at the University of Michigan. Caroline Adams teaches psychology at the University of Plymouth, En- gland. Jonathan Baron is professor of psychology at the University of Pennsyl- vania. James J. Choi is assistant professor of finance at the Yale School of Man- agement. Terrence Chorvat is associate professor in the George Mason University, School of Law. John Cullis is reader in economics in the Department of Economics and International Development at the University of Bath in England. Henk Elffers is senior researcher at the Netherlands Institute for the Study of Crime and Law Enforcement and professor of psychology and law at Antwerp University in Belgium. Richard A. Epstein is James Parker Hall Distinguished Service Professor of Law at the University of Chicago and Peter and Kirsten Bedford Se- nior Fellow at the Hoover Institution. vii viii Behavioral Public Finance Hanming Fang is associate professor of economics at Yale University and faculty research fellow of the National Bureau of Economic Research. Lee Anne Fennell is associate professor of law at the University of Illi- nois College of Law. Bruno S. Frey is professor of economics at the University of Zurich and research director of CREMA (Center for Research in Economics, Manage- ment and the Arts).
    [Show full text]
  • Intuitions About Penalties and Compensation in the Context of Tort Law
    Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 7:17-33 (1993) © 1993 Kluwer Academic Publishers Intuitions about Penalties and Compensation in the Context of Tort Law JONATHAN BARON Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, 3SI5 Walnut Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6196 I LAN A RITOV* Department of Industrial Enffncering and Management, Ben-Gurion University, P.O. Box 653, Beer Sheeva 84105, Isrnel Abstract Students, retired judges, economists, and others made judgments of appropriate penalties and compen,sation for hypothetical injuries. In some scenarios, compensation was paid by the government and penalties were paid to the government, so the two could differ. Penalties were generally uninfluenced by their deterrent effect on future behavior. Penalties were greater when they were paid directly to the victim than when they were paid to the government. Compensation was affected by whether injuries were caused by people or by nature, or by acts vs, omissions. These effects are not justified according to consequentialist views of penalties and compensation. We suggest that people are overgeneralizing reasonable rules and that such overgeneralization may be in- volved in perverse effects of tort law. Key words: tort law, penalties, compensations, intuitive judgments When one person (or group) harms another, people often think that the injurer should compensate the victim. Tort law can compel compensation. Such a transaction not only compensates the victim but also punishes the injurer. When the injurer compensates the victim, as when a child is induced to give back something she has taken or when a victim sues an injurer in court, punishment and compensation are linked together. Sometimes these functions are separated.
    [Show full text]
  • Judgment and Decision Making: an Interdisciplinary Reader, Second Edition Edited by Terry Connolly, Hal R
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-62602-6 - Judgment and Decision Making: An Interdisciplinary Reader, Second Edition Edited by Terry Connolly, Hal R. Arkes and Kenneth R. Hammond Frontmatter More information Cambridge Series on Judgment and Decision Making Judgment and Decision Making Researchers in a growing number of fields – public policy, law, business, medicine, psychology, engineering, and others – are working to under- stand and improve human judgment and decision making. This book, which presupposes no formal training, brings together a selection of key articles in the area, with careful organization, introductions, and com- mentaries. Issues include medical diagnosis, weather forecasting, labor negotiations, risk, public policy, business strategy, eyewitness testimony, and more. This is a revised edition of the 1986 collection of papers, Judgment and Decision Making, edited by Hal Arkes and Ken Hammond. The focus of this updated and extended volume is interdisciplinary and applied. The papers selected are scientific in nature, but chosen to appeal to the scholar, student, and layperson alike. Terry Connolly is FINOVA Professor of Management and Policy in the College of Business and Public Administration at the University of Arizona. Hal R. Arkes is Professor of Psychology at Ohio University. Kenneth R. Hammond is Emeritus Professor of Psychology and Director of the Center for Research on Judgment and Policy at the University of Colorado, Boulder. All three editors are past presidents of the Society for Judgment and Decision Making. © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-62602-6 - Judgment and Decision Making: An Interdisciplinary Reader, Second Edition Edited by Terry Connolly, Hal R.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Jonathan Haidt March 30, 2021 NYU-Stern School of Business Business and Society Program, KMC-7-150 (212) 992-6802 44 West 4th Street [email protected] New York, NY 10012 www.JonathanHaidt.com Education Yale University, B.A. in Philosophy, Magna Cum Laude, 1985. University of Pennsylvania, M.A. in Psychology, 1988. University of Pennsylvania, Ph.D. in Psychology, 1992. Dissertation title: "Moral judgment, affect, and culture, or, is it wrong to eat your dog?" Advisors: Jonathan Baron, Alan Fiske Professional Appointments Post-Doctoral Fellow, University of Chicago, Committee on Human Development. NIMH Training Program in Culture, Emotion, and Mental Health. Under Richard Shweder, 7/92-6/94. Post-Doctoral Associate, The John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation, Program on Mental Health and Human Development. Under Judith Rodin, 7/94-8/95. Assistant Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of Virginia, 8/95-8/01. Associate Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of Virginia, 8/01-8/09. Professor, Dept. of Psychology, University of Virginia, 8/09-5/12. Thomas Cooley Professor of Ethical Leadership, NYU-Stern School of Business, 6/12 – present. Visiting Professorships & Fellowships: Laurance S. Rockefeller Visiting Professor for Distinguished Teaching, Princeton University Center for Human Values, 9/06-7/07. Visiting Distinguished Fellow, Sage Center for the study of the Mind, University of California at Santa Barbara, 11/1/08-12/20/08. Henry Kaufman Visiting Prof. of Business Ethics, NYU-Stern School of Business, 7/11-6/12. Honors National Science Foundation. Graduate Fellowship, 1988-1991. American Psychological Association. Dissertation Research Award, 1991. Harry Frank Guggenheim Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • Group Cooperation Under Uncertainty
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Operations, Information and Decisions Papers Wharton Faculty Research 12-2009 Group Cooperation Under Uncertainty Min Gong Joanne Baron University of Pennsylvania Howard Kunreuther University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/oid_papers Part of the Other Economics Commons, and the Other Education Commons Recommended Citation Gong, M., Baron, J., & Kunreuther, H. (2009). Group Cooperation Under Uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39 251-270. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11166-009-9080-2 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/oid_papers/83 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Group Cooperation Under Uncertainty Abstract Previous research has shown an ‘interindividual-intergroup discontinuity effect’: intergroup interactions generally lead to less cooperative outcomes than interindividual interactions. We replicate the discontinuity effect in the deterministic prisoner’s dilemma, but find that groups are more cooperative than individuals in a stochastic version of the game. Three major factors that underlie the usual discontinuity effect are reduced in the stochastic environment: greed, fear, and persuasion power. Two group mechanisms are proposed to explain the reversed discontinuity effect: the motivation to avoid guilt and blame when making decisions that affect others’ welfare, and the social pressure to conform to certain norms when one is in a group setting. Keywords group decision,
    [Show full text]
  • Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Volume 70, Issue 1
    ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAVIOR AND HUMAN DECISION PROCESSES Vol. 70, No. 1, April, pp. 1±16, 1997 ARTICLE NO. OB972690 Protected Values Jonathan Baron University of Pennsylvania and Mark Spranca RAND, SANTA MONICA such as those for the protection of nature or individual Protected values are those that resist trade-offs with freedom from interference. other values, particularly economic values. We propose Such willingness to make trade-offs is especially rea- that such values arise from deontological rules con- sonable when we consider what would mean to be com- cerning action. People are concerned about their par- pletely committed to some value. It would mean that ticipation in transactions rather than just with the consequences that result. This proposal implies that we could not take any risk of sacrificing this value, protected values, defined as those that display trade- through our actions or our failures to act. We would off resistance, will also tend to display quantity insensi- thus be obliged to spend our lives looking for actions tivity, agent relativity, and moral obligation. People will that could reduce small risks of sacrificing this value. also tend to experience anger at the thought of making If we had more than one such value, we would be in a trade-offs, and to engage in denial of the need for trade- serious quandary. offs through wishful thinking. These five properties Although the need to make trade-offs is a fact of life, were correlated with tradeoff resistance (across differ- it is not one that everyone is happy with. Some people ent values, within subjects) in five studies in which say that human livesÐor human rights, or natural re- subjects answered several questions about each of sev- sourcesÐare infinitely more important than other eco- eral values, or in which they indicated their willing- nomic goods.
    [Show full text]
  • Zbwleibniz-Informationszentrum
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Camerer, Colin F.; Weber, Martin Working Paper — Digitized Version Recent developments in modelling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguitiy Manuskripte aus den Instituten für Betriebswirtschaftslehre der Universität Kiel, No. 275 Provided in Cooperation with: Christian-Albrechts-University of Kiel, Institute of Business Administration Suggested Citation: Camerer, Colin F.; Weber, Martin (1991) : Recent developments in modelling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguitiy, Manuskripte aus den Instituten für Betriebswirtschaftslehre der Universität Kiel, No. 275, Universität Kiel, Institut für Betriebswirtschaftslehre, Kiel This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/161405 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen)
    [Show full text]
  • Group Cooperation Under Uncertainty
    Group Cooperation under Uncertainty Min Gong *, Jonathan Baron #, Howard Kunreuther + * Center for Research on Environmental Decisions, Columbia University, 406 Schermerhorn Hall - MC 5501, 1190 Amsterdam Ave, New York, NY 10027. Email address: [email protected] . # Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania. Email address: [email protected] . + Cecilia Yen Koo Professor of Decisions Sciences and Public Policy at the Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania and co-director of the Wharton Risk Management and Decision Processes Center. E-mail address: [email protected] . Acknowledgements: We appreciate helpful comments and suggestions from David Aadland, Colin Camerer, Rachel Croson, Jason Dana, Charles Holt, David Krantz, Robert Meyer, Charles Plott, Deborah Small, and participants at the CRED 2008 Annual Meeting, the CREATE Behavioral Economics and Terrorism Workshop, the SJDM 2008 Annual Conference, Jonathan Baron lab meeting, and weekly seminar at the Marketing Department, the Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. We thank the Wharton Behavior Lab, Leonid Markel, and Sarah Martin for collecting and compiling the data. We also wish to thank Kip Viscusi and an anonymous reviewer for their feedback and suggestions on an earlier version of the paper. This research is supported by National Science Foundation grant CMS-0527598. 1 Group Cooperation under Uncertainty Min Gong, Jonathan Baron, Howard Kunreuther Abstract : Previous research has shown an ‘interindividual-intergroup discontinuity effect’: intergroup interactions generally lead to less cooperative outcomes than interindividual interactions. We replicate the discontinuity effect in the deterministic prisoner’s dilemma, but find that groups are more cooperative than individuals in a stochastic version of the game. Three major factors that underlie the usual discontinuity effect were reduced in the stochastic environment: greed, fear, and persuasion power.
    [Show full text]