Nested Complexes and Their Polyhedral Realizations Andrei Zelevinsky

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nested Complexes and Their Polyhedral Realizations Andrei Zelevinsky Pure and Applied Mathematics Quarterly Volume 2, Number 3 (Special Issue: In honor of Robert MacPherson, Part 1 of 3 ) 655|671, 2006 Nested Complexes and their Polyhedral Realizations Andrei Zelevinsky To Bob MacPherson on the occasion of his 60th birthday 1. Introduction This note which can be viewed as a complement to [9], presents a self-contained overview of basic properties of nested complexes and their two dual polyhedral realizations: as complete simplicial fans, and as simple polytopes. Most of the results are not new; our aim is to bring into focus a striking similarity between nested complexes and associated fans and polytopes on one side, and cluster complexes and generalized associahedra introduced and studied in [7, 2] on the other side. First a very brief history (more details and references can be found in [10, 9]). Nested complexes appeared in the work by De Concini - Procesi [3] in the context of subspace arrangements. More general complexes associated with arbitrary ¯nite graphs were introduced and studied in [1] and more recently in [10]; these papers also present a construction of associated simple convex polytopes (dubbed graph associahedra in [1], and De Concini - Procesi associahedra in [10]). An even more general setup developed by Feichtner - Yuzvinsky in [6] associates a nested complex and a simplicial fan to an arbitrary ¯nite atomic lattice. In the present note we follow [5] and [9] in adopting an intermediate level of generality, and studying the nested complexes associated to building sets (see De¯nition 2.1 below). Feichtner and Sturmfels in [5] show that the simplicial fan associated to a building set is the normal fan of a simple convex polytope, while Postnikov in [9] gives an elegant construction of this polytope as a Minkowski sum of simplices. Received July 29, 2005. 2000 Mathematics Subject Classi¯cation.Primary 52B. Research supported by NSF grant DMS-0500534. 656 Andrei Zelevinsky In this note we develop an alternative approach, constructing the polytope di- rectly from the fan; this construction is completely analogous to that in [2]. The main role in this approach is played by the link decomposition property (Propo- sition 3.2 below) asserting that the link of any element in a nested complex can be naturally identi¯ed with a nested complex of smaller rank. This result pro- vides a uni¯ed method for establishing properties of nested complexes and their polyhedral realizations by induction on the rank of a building set. The note is structured as follows. Section 2 introduces (basically following [9]) building sets and associated nested complexes. Section 3 presents the link decomposition property (Proposition 3.2). In this generality it seems to be new; for the graph associahedra it appeared in [10]. Section 4 contains some struc- tural properties of nested complexes, all of them derived in a uni¯ed way from Proposition 3.2. In Section 5 we show that any nested complex can be realized as a smooth complete simplicial fan (Theorem 5.1 and Corollary 5.2); we refer to this fan as the nested fan. This construction has appeared in [6, 4, 5]. However, it is not so easy to extract from these papers a proof that the nested fan is well-de¯ned; this is why we prefer to give a simple self-contained proof. In Section 6, we prove (Theorem 6.1) that the nested fan is the normal fan of a simple polytope ¦, which we call the nested polytope. The argument is completely parallel to that in [2]; in particular, it leads to a speci¯c realization of ¦ which can be shown to be the same as the realization given in [9]. The concluding Section 7 discusses the special class of graphical building sets, those giving rise to graph associahedra [1, 10]. We give a simple characterization of graphical building sets (Proposition 7.3). For them an analogy with cluster complexes becomes sharper: in particular, the corresponding nested complex is a clique complex (Corollary 7.4). 2. Nested complexes We start by recalling basic de¯nitions from [9, Section 7]. De¯nition 2.1 ([9], De¯nition 7.1). Let S be a nonempty ¯nite set. A building set (or simply a building) on S is a collection B of nonempty subsets of S satisfying the conditions: (B1) If I;J 2 B and I \ J 6= ;, then I [ J 2 B. (B2) B contains all singletons fig, for i 2 S. The nested complex associated to a building B is de¯ned as follows. Let Bmax ½ B be the set of maximal (by inclusion) elements of B. We refer to the elements of Bmax as the B-components. In view of (B1) and (B2), the B-components Nested Complexes 657 are pairwise disjoint, and their union is S. We de¯ne the rank of B by setting rk(B) = jSj ¡ jBmaxj. De¯nition 2.2 (cf. [9], De¯nition 7.3). A subset N ½ B ¡ Bmax is called nested if it satis¯es the following condition: for any k ¸ 2 and any I1;:::;Ik 2 N such that none of the Ii contains another one, the union I1 [ ¢ ¢ ¢ [ Ik is not in B. The simplicial complex on B¡Bmax formed by the nested sets is called the nested complex and denoted N (B). In particular, the 1-simplices of N (B) are pairs fI;Jg ½ B such that: (2.1) either I ½ J, or J ½ I, or I [ J2 = B (in view of (B2), in the last case I and J are disjoint). Note that our de¯nition of nested sets is di®erent from the one in [9, De¯nition 7.3]: Postnikov's nested sets are obtained from ours by adjoining the set Bmax. Of course this does not a®ect the poset structure of the nested complex; an advantage of the present version is that our nested sets form a simplicial complex. 3. Link decomposition Let B be a building on S, and N (B) the associated nested complex. For every C 2 B ¡ Bmax, let 0 0 (3.1) N (B)C = fN ½ B ¡ Bmax ¡ fCg : N [ fCg 2 N (B)g denote the link of C in N (B); this is a simplicial complex on the set fI 2 B¡Bmax ¡ fCg : fC; Ig 2 N (B)g. Our main tool in studying the structure of N (B) is the recursive description of N (B)C given in Proposition 3.2 below. To state it, we need some preparation. De¯nition 3.1. Let C be a nonempty subset of S. ² The restriction of B to C is the building on C de¯ned by (3.2) BjC = fI ½ C : I 2 Bg: ² The contraction of C from B is the building on S ¡ C de¯ned by (3.3) CnB = fI ½ S ¡ C : I 2 B or C [ I 2 Bg: The fact that both BjC and CnB are indeed buildings, is immediate from De¯nition 2.1. Let S1;:::;Sk be disjoint ¯nite sets, and let Bi be a building on Si for i = 1; : : : ; k. The product B1 £ ¢ ¢ ¢ £ Bk is de¯ned as the building on S1 t ¢ ¢ ¢ t Sk formed by the elements of all the Bi. Clearly, the nested complex N (B1 £¢ ¢ ¢£Bk) is naturally isomorphic to the product N (B1) £ ¢ ¢ ¢ £ N (Bk). In particular, every building B on S decomposes as a product BjS1 £¢ ¢ ¢£BjSk , where S1;:::;Sk are the B-components; therefore, N (B) can be identi¯ed with N (BjS1 ) £ ¢ ¢ ¢ £ N (BjSk ). 658 Andrei Zelevinsky Proposition 3.2 (Link Decomposition). For every C 2 B¡Bmax, the link N (B)C is isomorphic to N (BjC £ CnB). 0 Proof. Fix C 2 B ¡ Bmax and abbreviate B = BjC £ CnB. Let B0 = fI 2 B ¡ Bmax ¡ fCg : fC; Ig 2 N (B)g be the ground set of N (B)C . In view of (2.1), B0 is the disjoint union of the following three sets: B1 = fI 2 B ¡ fCg : I ½ Cg;(3.4) B2 = fI 2 B ¡ Bmax ¡ fCg : C ½ Ig;(3.5) (3.6) B3 = fI 2 B ¡ Bmax : C \ I = ;;C [ I2 = Bg: 0 Now to every I 2 B0 = B1 [B2 [B3 we associate a subset I ½ S by setting ( I if I 2 B1 [B3; (3.7) I0 = I ¡ C if I 2 B2. Remembering the de¯nitions, we see that B1 is the ground set of the nested complex N (BjC ), and B3 is a subset of the ground set of N (CnB) formed by those I0 ½ S ¡C for which C [I0 2= B. Furthermore, the correspondence I 7! I0 = I ¡C identi¯es B2 with the remaining part of the ground set of N (CnB), formed by those I0 ½ S ¡ C for which C [ I0 2 B. Thus, the correspondence I 7! I0 is a 0 bijection between the ground sets of N (B)C and N (B ). To prove Proposition 3.2, it remains to show the following: The correspondence I 7! I0 induces an(3.8) 0 isomorphism of complexes N (B)C and N (B ). Thus, we need to show the following: for any distinct I1;:::;Ik 2 B0, the 0 0 0 set fC; I1;:::;Ikg is nested for B if and only if fI1;:::;Ikg is nested for B . 0 0 0 First suppose fI1;:::;Ikg is not nested for B . Without loss of generality, we 0 0 can assume that k ¸ 2, none of the Ii contains another one, and I1 [ ¢ ¢ ¢ [ 0 0 Ik 2 B . Choosing the smallest possible k with this property and using property 0 (B1) in De¯nition 2.1, we can further assume that the Ii are pairwise disjoint.
Recommended publications
  • COMPLEXES of TREES and NESTED SET COMPLEXES 11 K+2 and Congruent to 2 Mod K, and at Least One Internal Edge
    COMPLEXES OF TREES AND NESTED SET COMPLEXES EVA MARIA FEICHTNER Abstract. We exhibit an identity of abstract simplicial complexes between the well- studied complex of trees Tn and the reduced minimal nested set complex of the partition lattice. We conclude that the order complex of the partition lattice can be obtained from the complex of trees by a sequence of stellar subdivisions. We provide an explicit cohomology basis for the complex of trees that emerges naturally from this context. Motivated by these results, we review the generalization of complexes of trees to complexes of k-trees by Hanlon, and we propose yet another, in the context of nested set complexes more natural, generalization. 1. Introduction In this article we explore the connection between complexes of trees and nested set complexes of specific lattices. Nested set complexes appear as the combinatorial core in De Concini-Procesi wonderful compactifications of arrangement complements [DP1]. They record the incidence struc- ture of natural stratifications and are crucial for descriptions of topological invariants in combinatorial terms. Disregarding their geometric origin, nested set complexes can be defined for any finite meet-semilattice [FK]. Interesting connections between seemingly distant fields have been established when relating the purely oder-theoretic concept of nested sets to various contexts in geometry. See [FY] for a construction linking nested set complexes to toric geometry, and [FS] for an appearance of nested set complexes in tropical geometry. This paper presents yet another setting where nested set complexes appear in a mean- ingful way and, this time, contribute to the toolbox of topological combinatorics and combinatorial representation theory.
    [Show full text]
  • 3.2 Supplement
    Introduction to Functional Analysis Chapter 3. Major Banach Space Theorems 3.2. Baire Category Theorem—Proofs of Theorems June 12, 2021 () Introduction to Functional Analysis June 12, 2021 1 / 6 Table of contents 1 Proposition 3.1. The Nested Set Theorem 2 Proposition 3.2. Baire’s Theorem 3 Corollary 3.3. Dual Form of Baire’s Theorem () Introduction to Functional Analysis June 12, 2021 2 / 6 Next, suppose both x, y ∈ Fn for all n ∈ N. Then kx − yk ≤ diam(Fn) for all n ∈ N and since diam(Fn) → 0, then kx − yk = 0, or x = y, establishing uniqueness. Proposition 3.1. The Nested Set Theorem Proposition 3.1. The Nested Set Theorem Proposition 3.1. The Nested Set Theorem. Given a sequence F1 ⊇ F2 ⊇ F3 ⊇ · · · of closed nonempty sets in a Banach space such that diam(Fn) → 0, there is a unique point that is in Fn for all n ∈ N. Proof. Choose some xn ∈ Fn for each n ∈ N. Since diam(Fn) → 0, for all ε > 0 there exists N ∈ N such that if n ≥ N then diam(Fn) < ε. Since the Fn are nested, then for all m, n ≥ N, we have kxn − xmk < ε, and so (xn) is a Cauchy sequence. Since we are in a Banach space, there is x such that (xn) → x. Now for n ∈ N, the sequence (xn, xn+1, xn+2,...) ⊆ Fn is convergent to x and since Fn is closed then Fn = F n. So x ∈ Fn by Theorem 2.2.A(iii). That is x ∈ Fn for all n ∈ N.
    [Show full text]
  • Complexes of Trees and Nested Set Complexes
    Pacific Journal of Mathematics COMPLEXES OF TREES AND NESTED SET COMPLEXES EVA MARIA FEICHTNER Volume 227 No. 2 October 2006 PACIFIC JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol. 227, No. 2, 2006 COMPLEXES OF TREES AND NESTED SET COMPLEXES EVA MARIA FEICHTNER We exhibit an identity of abstract simplicial complexes between the well- studied complex of trees Tn and the reduced minimal nested set complex of the partition lattice. We conclude that the order complex of the partition lattice can be obtained from the complex of trees by a sequence of stellar subdivisions. We provide an explicit cohomology basis for the complex of trees that emerges naturally from this context. Motivated by these results, we review the generalization of complexes of trees to complexes of k-trees by Hanlon, and we propose yet another generalization, more natural in the context of nested set complexes. 1. Introduction In this article we explore the connection between complexes of trees and nested set complexes of specific lattices. Nested set complexes appear as the combinatorial core in De Concini and Pro- cesi’s [1995] wonderful compactifications of arrangement complements. They record the incidence structure of natural stratifications and are crucial for descrip- tions of topological invariants in combinatorial terms. Disregarding their geometric origin, nested set complexes can be defined for any finite meet-semilattice [Feicht- ner and Kozlov 2004]. Interesting connections between seemingly distant fields have been established when relating the purely order-theoretic concept of nested sets to various contexts in geometry. See [Feichtner and Yuzvinsky 2004] for a construction linking nested set complexes to toric geometry, and [Feichtner and Sturmfels 2005] for an appearance of nested set complexes in tropical geometry.
    [Show full text]
  • Submodularity Helps in Nash and Nonsymmetric Bargaining Games∗
    Submodularity Helps in Nash and Nonsymmetric Bargaining Games∗ Deeparnab Chakrabartyy Gagan Goelz Vijay V. Vazirani x Lei Wang{ Changyuan Yuk Abstract Motivated by the recent work of [Vaz12], we take a fresh look at understanding the quality and robustness of solutions to Nash and nonsymmetric bargaining games by subjecting them to several stress tests. Our tests are quite basic, e.g., we ask whether the solutions are computable in polynomial time, and whether they have certain properties such as efficiency, fairness, desirable response when agents change their disagreement points or play with a subset of the agents. Our main conclusion is that imposing submodularity, a natural economies of scale condition, on Nash and nonsymmetric bargaining games endows them with several desirable properties. ∗This work was supported in part by the National Natural Science Foundation of China Grant 60553001, and the National Basic Research Program of China Grant 2007CB807900,2007CB807901. A preliminary version of this appeared in the Proceedings of the 4th Workshop on Internet and Network Economics (2008, Shanghai). yCurrent address: Microsoft Research, Bangalore, India 560001. Email: [email protected]. Work done as a graduate student at Georgia Tech. zCurrent address: Google Inc., NYC, New York. Email: [email protected]. Work done as a graduate student at Georgia Tech. xCollege of Computing, Georgia Tech, Atlanta, GA 30332{0280. Email: [email protected] {Current Address: Microsoft Corporation, Bellevue, WA 98004 Email: [email protected]. Work done as a graduate student at Georgia Tech. kInstitute for Theoretical Computer Science, Tsinghua University 1 1 Introduction Bargaining is perhaps the oldest situations of conflict of interest, and since game theory develops solution concepts for negotiating in such situations, it is perhaps not surprising that bargaining was first modeled as a game in John Nash's seminal 1950 paper [Nas50], using the framework of game theory given a few years earlier by von Neumann and Morgenstern [vNM44].
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Inductive Definitions in Constructive Set Theory
    Generalized Inductive Definitions in Constructive Set Theory Michael Rathjen∗ Department of Mathematics, Ohio State University Columbus, OH 43210, U.S.A. [email protected] February 17, 2010 Abstract The intent of this paper is to study generalized inductive definitions on the basis of Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory, CZF. In theories such as classical Zermelo- Fraenkel Set Theory, it can be shown that every inductive definition over a set gives rise to a least and a greatest fixed point, which are sets. This principle, notated GID, can also be deduced from CZF plus the full impredicative separation axiom or CZF augmented by the power set axiom. Full separation and a fortiori the power set axiom, however, are entirely unacceptable from a constructive point of view. It will be shown that while CZF + GID is stronger than CZF, the principle GID does not embody the strength of any of these axioms. CZF + GID can be interpreted in Feferman's Explicit Mathematics with a least fixed point principle. The proof-theoretic strength of the latter theory is expressible by means of a fragment of second order arithmetic. MSC:03F50, 03F35 Keywords: Constructive set theory, Martin-L¨oftype theory, inductive definitions, proof-theoretic strength 1 Introduction In set theory, a monotone inductive definition over a given set A is derived from a mapping Ψ: P(A) !P(A) that is monotone, i.e., Ψ(X) ⊆ Ψ(Y ) whenever X ⊆ Y ⊆ A. Here P(A) denotes the class of all subsets of A. The set inductively defined by Ψ, Ψ1, is the smallest set Z such that ∗This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Award No.
    [Show full text]
  • Fast Exact Inference for Recursive Cardinality Models
    Fast Exact Inference for Recursive Cardinality Models Daniel Tarlow, Kevin Swersky, Richard S. Zemel, Ryan P. Adams, Brendan J. Frey Dept. of Computer Science Sch. of Eng. & Appl. Sci. Prob. & Stat. Inf. Group University of Toronto Harvard University University of Toronto fdtarlow,kswersky,[email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract celebrated result is the ability of the \graph cuts" algo- rithm to exactly find the maximum a posteriori (MAP) Cardinality potentials are a generally use- assignment in any pairwise graphical model with bi- ful class of high order potential that affect nary variables, where the internal potential structure probabilities based on how many of D bi- is restricted to be submodular. Along similar lines, nary variables are active. Maximum a poste- polynomial-time algorithms can exactly compute the riori (MAP) inference for cardinality poten- partition function in an Ising model if the underlying tial models is well-understood, with efficient graph is planar (Fisher, 1961). computations taking O(D log D) time. Yet Extensions of these results have been a topic of much efficient marginalization and sampling have recent interest, particularly for the case of MAP in- not been addressed as thoroughly in the ma- ference. Gould (2011) shows how to do exact MAP chine learning community. We show that inference in models with certain higher order terms there exists a simple algorithm for comput- via graph cut-like algorithms, and Ramalingham et al. ing marginal probabilities and drawing ex- (2008) give results for multilabel submodular models. act joint samples that runs in O(D log2 D) Tarlow et al.
    [Show full text]
  • A Graph-Theoretic Method for Organizing Overlapping Clusters Into Trees, Multiple Trees, Or Extended Trees
    Joumal of Classification 12:283-313 (1995) A Graph-Theoretic Method for Organizing Overlapping Clusters into Trees, Multiple Trees, or Extended Trees J. Douglas CarroU James E. Corter Rutgers University Teachers CoUege, Columbia University Abstract: A clustering that consists of a nested set of clusters may be represented graphically by a tree. In contrast, a clustedng that includes non-nested ovedapping clusters (sometimes termed a "nonhierarchical' ' cluste¡ cannot be represented by a tree. Graphical representations of such non-nested ovedapping clusterings are usuaUy complex and difficult to interpret. Carroll and Pruzansky (1975, 1980) sug- gested representing non-nested clusterings with multiple ultramet¡ or additive trees. Corter and Tversky (1986) introduced the extended tree (EXTREE) model, which represents a non-nested structure asa tree plus ovedapping clusters that ate represented by marked segments in the tree. We show here that the problem of finding a nested (i.e., tree-structured) set of clusters in ah ovedapping clustering can be reformulated as the problem of finding a clique in a graph. Thus, clique- finding algo¡ can be used to identify sets of clusters in the solution that can be represented by trees. This formulation provides a means of automaticaUy con- structing a multiple tree or extended tree representation of any non-nested cluster- ing. The method, called "clustrees", is applied to several non-nested overlapping clusterings de¡ using the MAPCLUS program (Arabie and Carroll 1980). Keywords: Overlapping clustering; Ultrametric; Additive tree; Extended tree; Multiple trees; Graph; Clique; Proximities. Authors' addresses: Please address correspondence to: James Corter, Box 41, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York, NY 10027, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • When Is a Right Orderable Group Locally Indicable?
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 128, Number 3, Pages 637{641 S 0002-9939(99)05534-3 Article electronically published on October 25, 1999 WHEN IS A RIGHT ORDERABLE GROUP LOCALLY INDICABLE? PATRIZIA LONGOBARDI, MERCEDE MAJ, AND AKBAR RHEMTULLA (Communicated by Ronald M. Solomon) Abstract. If a group G has an ascending series 1 = G0 G1 Gρ =G ≤ ≤···≤ of subgroups such that for each ordinal α, Gα C G,andGα+1=Gα has no non- abelian free subsemigroup, then G is right orderable if and only if it is locally indicable. In particular if G is a radical-by-periodic group, then it is right orderable if and only if it is locally indicable. 1. Introduction x Recall that a group G is said to be locally indicable if every finitely generated non-trivial subgroup of G has an infinite cyclic quotient. Such groups are right orderable, as was shown by R.G. Burns and V.W. Hale in [2]. On the other hand, a right orderable group need not be locally indicable as was shown by G.M. Bergman in [1]. It was shown in [9] that a finite extension of a polycyclic group is right orderable only if it is locally indicable. This result was extended to groups which are finite extensions of solvable groups by I.M. Chiswell and P. Kropholler in [3] and to the class of periodic extensions of radical groups by V. M. Tararin in [10]. The purpose of this paper is to show that if a group G has a normal ascending series 1 = G G G = G of subgroups such that for each ordinal 0 ≤ 1 ≤ ··· ≤ ρ α<ρ; Gα+1=Gα has no non-abelian free subsemigroup, then G is right orderable only if it is locally indicable.
    [Show full text]
  • Real Analysis (4Th Edition)
    Preface The first three editions of H.L.Royden's Real Analysis have contributed to the education of generations of mathematical analysis students. This fourth edition of Real Analysis preserves the goal and general structure of its venerable predecessors-to present the measure theory, integration theory, and functional analysis that a modem analyst needs to know. The book is divided the three parts: Part I treats Lebesgue measure and Lebesgue integration for functions of a single real variable; Part II treats abstract spaces-topological spaces, metric spaces, Banach spaces, and Hilbert spaces; Part III treats integration over general measure spaces, together with the enrichments possessed by the general theory in the presence of topological, algebraic, or dynamical structure. The material in Parts II and III does not formally depend on Part I. However, a careful treatment of Part I provides the student with the opportunity to encounter new concepts in a familiar setting, which provides a foundation and motivation for the more abstract concepts developed in the second and third parts. Moreover, the Banach spaces created in Part I, the LP spaces, are one of the most important classes of Banach spaces. The principal reason for establishing the completeness of the LP spaces and the characterization of their dual spaces is to be able to apply the standard tools of functional analysis in the study of functionals and operators on these spaces. The creation of these tools is the goal of Part II. NEW TO THE EDITION This edition contains 50% more exercises than the previous edition Fundamental results, including Egoroff s Theorem and Urysohn's Lemma are now proven in the text.
    [Show full text]
  • CS 173 Lecture 8: Set Theory (I)
    CS 173 Lecture 8: Set Theory (I) Jos´eMeseguer University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign 1 Preliminary Notions about Sets Intuitively, A set is an unordered collection of objects Given any set, say A, the objects belonging to it are called its elements. The property of an object a being an element of set A is written a P A. Such a property is called set membership, and the simbol P is called the membership predicate. We read a P A as \a belongs to A" or \a in A" or \a is an element of A." Objects Acceptable as Set Elements. Any precisely specified object can be an element of a set. For example, objects such as: { any number is N, Z, Q, or R { a truth value like T or F { any symbol such as an ASCII character, or a standard alphabet letter, or a Greek letter, or a Hebrew letter { any data structure such as, for example, a pair like p2; 3{17q, a triple like pa; b; cq, or an n-tuple like pa1; : : : ; anq { any set 1 is also an object that can be an element of another set. can all be elements of sets. The only general requirements about such objects are: 1. any object should be precisely specified 2. equality between such objects should also be precisely specified. Examples: 1{2 “ 2{4, a ­“ b, p1{2; 2{10q “ p2{4; 1{5q, a ­“ pa; 7q. Only Elements Matter. As we shall see, A set A is completely determined by its elements. 1 For set theory buffs: objects that are not sets are technically called urelements, coming from the German for \primitive elements." It turns out that it is possible to do all of set theory without using any such urelements, so that sets are the only objects used: amazingly enough, everything can be built up as a set, literally out of nothing, i.e., out of the empty set H.
    [Show full text]
  • Trees and Other Hierarchies in Mysql
    Get It Done With MySQL 5&Up, Chapter 20. Copyright © Peter Brawley and Arthur Fuller 2018. All rights reserved. TOC Previous Next Trees and Other Hierarchies in MySQL Graphs and SQL Edge list Edge-list model of a tree CTE edge list treewalk Draw the tree Nested sets model of a tree Edge list model of a network Parts explosions Most non-trivial data is hierarchical. Customers have orders, which have line items, which refer to products, which have prices. Population samples have subjects, who take tests, which give results, which have sub-results and norms. Web sites have pages, which have links, which collect hits across dates and times. These are hierarchies of tables. The number of tables limits the number of JOINs needed to walk the tree. For such queries, conventional SQL is an excellent tool. But when tables map a family tree, or a browsing history, or a bill of materials, table rows relate hierarchically to other rows in the same table. We no longer know how many JOINs we need to walk the tree. We need a different data model. That model is the graph (Fig 1), which is a set of nodes (vertices) and the edges (lines or arcs) that connect them. This chapter is about how to model and query graphs in a MySQL database. Graph theory is a branch of topology, the study of geometric relations that aren't changed by stretching and compression—rubber sheet geometry, some call it. Graph theory is ideal for modelling hierarchies—like family trees, browsing histories, search trees, Bayesian networks and bills of materials— whose shape and size we can't know in advance.
    [Show full text]
  • The Real Numbers: Sets, Sequences, and Functions
    CHAPTER 1 The Real Numbers: Sets, Sequences, and Functions Contents 1.1 The Field, Positivity, and Completeness Axioms . 7 1.2 The Natural and Rational Numbers . 11 1.3 Countable and Uncountable Sets . 13 1.4 Open Sets, Closed Sets, and Borel Sets of Real Numbers . 16 1.5 Sequences of Real Numbers . 20 1.6 Continuous Real-Valued Functions of a Real Variable . 25 We assume the reader has a familiarity with the properties of real numbers, sets of real numbers, sequences of real numbers, and real-valued functions of a real variable, which are usually treated in an undergraduate course in analysis. This familiarity will enable the reader to assimilate the present chapter, which is devoted to rapidly but thoroughly establishing those results which will be needed and referred to later. We assume that the set of real numbers, which is denoted by R, satisfies three types of axioms. We state these axioms and derive from them properties on the natural numbers, rational numbers, and countable sets. With this as background, we establish properties of open and closed sets of real numbers; convergent, monotone, and Cauchy sequences of real numbers; and continuous real-valued functions of a real variable. 1.1 THE FIELD, POSITIVITY, AND COMPLETENESS AXIOMS We assume as given the set R of real numbers such that for each pair of real numbers a and b, there are defined real numbers a + b and ab called the sum and product, respectively, of a and b for which the following Field Axioms, Positivity Axioms, and Completeness Axiom are satisfied.
    [Show full text]