Vagueness, Presupposition and Truth-Value Judgments Jérémy Zehr

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Vagueness, Presupposition and Truth-Value Judgments Jérémy Zehr Vagueness, Presupposition and Truth-Value Judgments Jérémy Zehr To cite this version: Jérémy Zehr. Vagueness, Presupposition and Truth-Value Judgments. Linguistics. École Normale Supérieure de Paris, 2014. English. tel-01107532 HAL Id: tel-01107532 https://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-01107532 Submitted on 22 Jan 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution| 4.0 International License Vagueness, Presupposition and Truth-Value Judgments J´er´emy Zehr Institut Jean Nicod, UMR 8128 Ecole´ Normale Sup´erieure de Paris Committee Members Paul Egr´e´ ∗, Orin Percus∗ Reinhard Muskens∗∗, Florian Schwarz∗∗ M´arta Abrus´an,Benjamin Spector A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor in Linguistics 18 December 2014 ∗Supervisors ∗∗Reviewers Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 IntroducingVagueness .......................... 4 1.2 IntroducingPresupposition. 8 1.3 The Project of Unifying Vagueness and Presupposition . ..... 12 1.3.1 PreviousM.A.Work ....................... 12 1.3.2 PresentWork ........................... 15 2 Trivalence, Vagueness and Presupposition 19 2.1 Supervaluationism ............................ 20 2.1.1 Presupposition: Van Fraassen’s Proposal . 22 2.1.2 Vagueness: Fine’simplementation . 27 2.2 StrongKleene............................... 29 2.2.1 Presupposition: George’s Implementation . .. 31 2.2.2 Vagueness: Tye’simplementation . 36 2.3 PredictionsandComparisons . 38 3 Experimental Literature on Vagueness and on Presupposition 47 3.1 Vagueness ................................. 48 3.2 Presupposition .............................. 51 3.3 Summary ................................. 57 4 ST5: a 5-Valued System 59 4.1 Truth-ValueJudgments. 60 4.2 ST5 .................................... 61 4.2.1 TheOriginal3-ValuedSTSystem . 61 4.2.1.1 TwoNotionsofSatisfaction . 61 4.2.1.2 NoRoomforPresupposition. 63 4.2.2 WhyExcludeAlternativeSystems. 63 4.2.3 TheST5System ......................... 65 i 4.3 HybridSentences ............................. 67 4.3.1 Conjunctions, Disjunctions and Implications in ST5 . ..... 67 4.3.1.1 AnExample ...................... 67 4.3.1.2 Left-RightAsymmetries . 68 4.3.2 DerivingPresuppositionsFromWords . 71 4.3.2.1 Presuppositional Expressions in Traditional Truth- ConditionalSemantics . 72 4.3.2.2 Presuppositional Expressions in ST5 . 74 4.4 Conclusions ................................ 82 5 Three Experiments 83 5.1 FirstExperiment:TestingST5 . 84 5.1.1 Design............................... 85 5.1.1.1 Predictions ....................... 88 5.1.2 Methods.............................. 91 5.1.2.1 Materials ........................ 91 5.1.2.2 ProcedureandParticipants . 91 5.1.3 Results............................... 92 5.1.4 Discussion............................. 92 5.1.4.1 Vagueness........................ 92 5.1.4.2 Presupposition . 94 5.2 Second Experiment: A 3-Response Paradigm . .. 99 5.2.1 Design............................... 99 5.2.1.1 Predictions . 100 5.2.2 Methods.............................. 102 5.2.2.1 Materials ........................ 102 5.2.2.2 ProcedureandParticipants . 102 5.2.3 Results............................... 103 5.2.4 Discussion............................. 105 5.3 Follow-Up Experiment: Investigating Participants’ Motivations for Presupposition .............................. 107 5.3.1 Design............................... 107 5.3.1.1 Predictions . 107 5.3.2 Methods.............................. 108 5.3.2.1 Materials ........................ 108 5.3.2.2 ProcedureandParticipants . 108 ii 5.3.3 Results............................... 109 5.3.4 Discussion............................. 111 5.4 Conclusions ................................ 112 5.4.1 ExperimentalConsiderations. 112 5.4.2 TheoreticalConsiderations . 113 6 4-Valued Systems for Vagueness and Presupposition 115 6.1 ABi-Lattice................................ 116 6.1.1 P asanAbsorbingTruth-Value . 119 6.2 TheRepairStrategy ........................... 121 6.2.1 WeakKleeneandStrongKleene. 121 6.2.2 MergingWeakandStrongKleene . 122 6.2.3 MergingStrongandMiddleKleene . 124 6.3 ConclusionsandComparisonwithST5 . 129 7 Antonyms 132 7.1 BorderlineContradictions . 132 7.2 TwoConceptionsofAntonyms. 134 7.3 PilotExperiment ............................. 136 7.3.1 Design............................... 137 7.3.1.1 Predictions . 138 7.3.2 Methods.............................. 141 7.3.2.1 Possible Biases in the Adjectives’ and their Antonyms’ Features......................... 141 7.3.2.2 Materials ........................ 144 7.3.2.3 Procedure........................ 145 7.3.3 Results............................... 146 7.3.4 Discussion............................. 146 7.4 MainExperiment ............................. 150 7.4.1 Design............................... 150 7.4.1.1 Predictions . 150 7.4.2 Methods.............................. 151 7.4.2.1 Materials ........................ 151 7.4.2.2 Procedure........................ 152 7.4.3 Results............................... 152 7.4.4 Discussion............................. 153 iii 8 Conclusions 157 8.1 TheoreticalConclusions . 157 8.2 TheoreticalPerspectives . 159 8.3 EmpiricalConclusions . 160 8.4 ExperimentalPerspectives . 162 A Experiments on Vagueness and Presupposition 164 A.1 Experiment1 ............................... 164 A.1.1 Instructions ............................ 164 A.1.2 Materials ............................. 165 A.1.3 PracticeItem ........................... 166 A.2 Experiment2 ............................... 166 A.2.1 Instructions ............................ 166 A.2.2 Materials ............................. 167 A.2.3 TrialItems ............................ 167 B Experiment on Antonyms 169 B.1 Instructions ................................ 169 B.2 Materials ................................. 170 Bibliography 171 iv Acknowledgments I want to thank my supervisors, Paul Egr´eand Orin Percus, who spent so much time and effort supporting me prior to and during the last three years. They knew how to bring out the best in me. Their rigorous advice and their kind patience have been priceless. I am very grateful to Reinhard Muskens and Florian Schwarz for accepting to be my thesis reviewers. I am also grateful to the other members of my committee, M´arta Abrus´an and Benjamin Spector. My thanks also go to the members of my mid-thesis committee, Denis Bonnay and Nicholas Asher, for their helpful feedback, and to Philippe Schlenker for valuable advice and discussion. My gratitude goes to Benjamin Spector again and to Emmanuel Chemla too, for their availability and all the enriching discussions that we had together. This work has benefited from discussions with more people than I can name. Among these people are the participants of the ESSLLI 2012 Workshop on Trivalent Logic and Their Applications, the participants of the Paris-Munich Workshop, and the participants of the Oxford-Princeton-IJN Workshop. I am especially thankful to John Burgess for his very helpful reviews. The Ph.D. students and the teachers that I met during my visiting quarter at UCLA contributed greatly to the early development of this thesis. I want to thank all of the members of the Linguistics Department for welcoming me and making my visit truly enjoyable. In particular, I owe a great deal to Heather Burnett for her personal and intellectual guidance, and to Dominique Sportiche for his help during these first months of my thesis. I would never have pursued this dissertation project without the encouragement and training that I received from the amazing teachers that I had at the University of Nantes. In particular, I am indebted to Orin Percus, Hamida Demirdache, and Nicolas Guilliot for introducing me to syntax and semantics. I would also like to thank my fellow graduate students; I am especially grateful to Nataˇsa Kneˇzevi´cfor 1 many stimulating discussions, and to Typhanie Prince for always providing moral support. This thesis would not have been possible without the administrative and financial support of the Institut Jean Nicod – Institut d’Etudes´ Cognitives at the Ecole´ Normale Sup´erieure. During my time at ENS, I also had the good fortune to meet many brilliant researchers from all over the world, including new friends whose presence and moral support have been essential to the completion of this thesis. My warmest thanks go to Bianca Cepollaro, Alexandre Cremers, Natasha Ivlieva, Jeremy Kuhn, Tristan Thommen, Lyn Tieu, and Erin Zaroukian for their precious feedback and advice, and for the invaluable moments of fun that we had together. My final thanks go to two important friends, Jean Balavoine and Jean Demel, and to my family, for supporting me day after day. This thesis has been granted by the Labex program “Frontiers in Cognition”. This work has been supported by ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL; a part of this work was also supported by a ‘Euryi’ grant from the European Sci- ence Foundation (“Presupposition: A Formal Pragmatic Approach” to P. Schlenker). The ESF is not responsible for any claims made here. 2 Chapter 1 Introduction The day I
Recommended publications
  • Logical Truth, Contradictions, Inconsistency, and Logical Equivalence
    Logical Truth, Contradictions, Inconsistency, and Logical Equivalence Logical Truth • The semantical concepts of logical truth, contradiction, inconsistency, and logi- cal equivalence in Predicate Logic are straightforward adaptations of the corre- sponding concepts in Sentence Logic. • A closed sentence X of Predicate Logic is logically true, X, if and only if X is true in all interpretations. • The logical truth of a sentence is proved directly using general reasoning in se- mantics. • Given soundness, one can also prove the logical truth of a sentence X by provid- ing a derivation with no premises. • The result of the derivation is that X is theorem, ` X. An Example • (∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx. – Suppose d satisfies ‘(∀x)Fx’. – Then all x-variants of d satisfy ‘Fx’. – Since the domain D is non-empty, some x-variant of d satisfies ‘Fx’. – So d satisfies ‘(∃x)Fx’ – Therefore d satisfies ‘(∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx’, QED. • ` (∀x)Fx ⊃ (∃x)Fx. 1 (∀x)Fx P 2 Fa 1 ∀ E 3 (∃x)Fx 1 ∃ I Contradictions • A closed sentence X of Predicate Logic is a contradiction if and only if X is false in all interpretations. • A sentence X is false in all interpretations if and only if its negation ∼X is true on all interpretations. • Therefore, one may directly demonstrate that a sentence is a contradiction by proving that its negation is a logical truth. • If the ∼X of a sentence is a logical truth, then given completeness, it is a theorem, and hence ∼X can be derived from no premises. 1 • If a sentence X is such that if it is true in any interpretation, both Y and ∼Y are true in that interpretation, then X cannot be true on any interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic
    Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic § 5.1 Valid inference steps Conjunction elimination Sometimes called simplification. From a conjunction, infer any of the conjuncts. • From P ∧ Q, infer P (or infer Q). Conjunction introduction Sometimes called conjunction. From a pair of sentences, infer their conjunction. • From P and Q, infer P ∧ Q. § 5.2 Proof by cases This is another valid inference step (it will form the rule of disjunction elimination in our formal deductive system and in Fitch), but it is also a powerful proof strategy. In a proof by cases, one begins with a disjunction (as a premise, or as an intermediate conclusion already proved). One then shows that a certain consequence may be deduced from each of the disjuncts taken separately. One concludes that that same sentence is a consequence of the entire disjunction. • From P ∨ Q, and from the fact that S follows from P and S also follows from Q, infer S. The general proof strategy looks like this: if you have a disjunction, then you know that at least one of the disjuncts is true—you just don’t know which one. So you consider the individual “cases” (i.e., disjuncts), one at a time. You assume the first disjunct, and then derive your conclusion from it. You repeat this process for each disjunct. So it doesn’t matter which disjunct is true—you get the same conclusion in any case. Hence you may infer that it follows from the entire disjunction. In practice, this method of proof requires the use of “subproofs”—we will take these up in the next chapter when we look at formal proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • Pluralisms About Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected]
    University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Doctoral Dissertations University of Connecticut Graduate School 8-9-2019 Pluralisms about Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut - Storrs, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations Recommended Citation Kellen, Nathan, "Pluralisms about Truth and Logic" (2019). Doctoral Dissertations. 2263. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/dissertations/2263 Pluralisms about Truth and Logic Nathan Kellen, PhD University of Connecticut, 2019 Abstract: In this dissertation I analyze two theories, truth pluralism and logical pluralism, as well as the theoretical connections between them, including whether they can be combined into a single, coherent framework. I begin by arguing that truth pluralism is a combination of realist and anti-realist intuitions, and that we should recognize these motivations when categorizing and formulating truth pluralist views. I then introduce logical functionalism, which analyzes logical consequence as a functional concept. I show how one can both build theories from the ground up and analyze existing views within the functionalist framework. One upshot of logical functionalism is a unified account of logical monism, pluralism and nihilism. I conclude with two negative arguments. First, I argue that the most prominent form of logical pluralism faces a serious dilemma: it either must give up on one of the core principles of logical consequence, and thus fail to be a theory of logic at all, or it must give up on pluralism itself. I call this \The Normative Problem for Logical Pluralism", and argue that it is unsolvable for the most prominent form of logical pluralism. Second, I examine an argument given by multiple truth pluralists that purports to show that truth pluralists must also be logical pluralists.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics Versus Science
    To appear in Journal for General Philosophy of Science (2004) In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics versus Science F.A. Muller Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Utrecht University, P.O. Box 80.000 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands E-mail: [email protected] August 2003 Summary Over the past years, in books and journals (this journal included), N. Maxwell launched a ferocious attack on B.C. van Fraassen's view of science called Con- structive Empiricism (CE). This attack has been totally ignored. Must we con- clude from this silence that no defence is possible against the attack and that a fortiori Maxwell has buried CE once and for all, or is the attack too obviously flawed as not to merit exposure? We believe that neither is the case and hope that a careful dissection of Maxwell's reasoning will make this clear. This dis- section includes an analysis of Maxwell's `aberrance-argument' (omnipresent in his many writings) for the contentious claim that science implicitly and per- manently accepts a substantial, metaphysical thesis about the universe. This claim generally has been ignored too, for more than a quarter of a century. Our con- clusions will be that, first, Maxwell's attacks on CE can be beaten off; secondly, his `aberrance-arguments' do not establish what Maxwell believes they estab- lish; but, thirdly, we can draw a number of valuable lessons from these attacks about the nature of science and of the libertarian nature of CE. Table of Contents on other side −! Contents 1 Exordium: What is Maxwell's Argument? 1 2 Does Science Implicitly Accept Metaphysics? 3 2.1 Aberrant Theories .
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege
    Synthese (2010) 174:237–261 DOI 10.1007/s11229-008-9420-9 The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege Willem R. de Jong Received: 10 April 2007 / Revised: 24 July 2007 / Accepted: 1 April 2008 / Published online: 8 November 2008 © The Author(s) 2008. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic- synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces con- siderable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, that is, within the Classical Model of Science: scientific knowledge as cognitio ex principiis. But as we will see, the way the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments or propositions functions within this model turns out to differ considerably between them. Keywords Analytic-synthetic · Science · Logic · Kant · Bolzano · Frege 1 Introduction As is well known, the critical Kant is the first to apply the analytic-synthetic distinction to such things as judgments, sentences or propositions. For Kant this distinction is not only important in his repudiation of traditional, so-called dogmatic, metaphysics, but it is also crucial in his inquiry into (the possibility of) metaphysics as a rational science. Namely, this distinction should be “indispensable with regard to the critique of human understanding, and therefore deserves to be classical in it” (Kant 1783, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Deduction (I) Tautologies, Contradictions And
    D (I) T, & L L October , Tautologies, contradictions and contingencies Consider the truth table of the following formula: p (p ∨ p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula depends on the way a truth value is assigned to p: the whole formula is true if p is true and false if p is false. Contrast the truth table of (p ∨ p) in () with the truth table of (p ∨ ¬p) below: p ¬p (p ∨ ¬p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula does not depend on the way a truth value is assigned to p. The formula is always true because of the meaning of the connectives. Finally, consider the truth table table of (p ∧ ¬p): p ¬p (p ∧ ¬p) () This time the formula is always false no matter what truth value p has. Tautology A statement is called a tautology if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contradiction A statement is called a contradiction if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contingency A statement is called a contingency or contingent if the final column in its truth table contains both ’s and ’s. Let’s consider some examples from the book. Can you figure out which of the following sentences are tautologies, which are contradictions and which contingencies? Hint: the answer is the same for all the formulas with a single row. () a. (p ∨ ¬p), (p → p), (p → (q → p)), ¬(p ∧ ¬p) b.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem Of
    Leibniz’s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem of »Impossible Objects« Wolfgang Lenzen (Osnabrück) Abstract The core idea of the ontological proof is to show that the concept of existence is somehow contained in the concept of God, and that therefore God’s existence can be logically derived – without any further assumptions about the external world – from the very idea, or definition, of God. Now, G.W. Leibniz has argued repeatedly that the traditional versions of the ontological proof are not fully conclusive, because they rest on the tacit assumption that the concept of God is possible, i.e. free from contradiction. A complete proof will rather have to consist of two parts. First, a proof of premise (1) God is possible. Second, a demonstration of the “remarkable proposition” (2) If God is possible, then God exists. The present contribution investigates an interesting paper in which Leibniz tries to prove proposition (2). It will be argued that the underlying idea of God as a necessary being has to be interpreted with the help of a distinguished predicate letter ‘E’ (denoting the concept of existence) as follows: (3) g =df ιxE(x). Principle (2) which Leibniz considered as “the best fruit of the entire logic” can then be formalized as follows: (4) ◊E(ιxE(x)) → E(ιxE(x)). At first sight, Leibniz’s proof appears to be formally correct; but a closer examination reveals an ambiguity in his use of the modal notions. According to (4), the possibility of the necessary being has to be understood in the sense of something which possibly exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastive Empiricism
    Elliott Sober Contrastive Empiricism I Despite what Hegel may have said, syntheses have not been very successful in philosophical theorizing. Typically, what happens when you combine a thesis and an antithesis is that you get a mishmash, or maybe just a contradiction. For example, in the philosophy of mathematics, formalism says that mathematical truths are true in virtue of the way we manipulate symbols. Mathematical Platonism, on the other hand, holds that mathematical statements are made true by abstract objects that exist outside of space and time. What would a synthesis of these positions look like? Marks on paper are one thing, Platonic forms an­ other. Compromise may be a good idea in politics, but it looks like a bad one in philosophy. With some trepidation, I propose in this paper to go against this sound advice. Realism and empiricism have always been contradictory tendencies in the philos­ ophy of science. The view I will sketch is a synthesis, which I call Contrastive Empiricism. Realism and empiricism are incompatible, so a synthesis that merely conjoined them would be a contradiction. Rather, I propose to isolate important elements in each and show that they combine harmoniously. I will leave behind what I regard as confusions and excesses. The result, I hope, will be neither con­ tradiction nor mishmash. II Empiricism is fundamentally a thesis about experience. It has two parts. First, there is the idea that experience is necessary. Second, there is the thesis that ex­ perience suffices. Necessary and sufficient for what? Usually this blank is filled in with something like: knowledge of the world outside the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets, Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Quantifiers
    COMP 182 Algorithmic Thinking Sets, Propositional Logic, Luay Nakhleh Computer Science Predicates, and Quantifiers Rice University !1 Reading Material ❖ Chapter 1, Sections 1, 4, 5 ❖ Chapter 2, Sections 1, 2 !2 ❖ Mathematics is about statements that are either true or false. ❖ Such statements are called propositions. ❖ We use logic to describe them, and proof techniques to prove whether they are true or false. !3 Propositions ❖ 5>7 ❖ The square root of 2 is irrational. ❖ A graph is bipartite if and only if it doesn’t have a cycle of odd length. ❖ For n>1, the sum of the numbers 1,2,3,…,n is n2. !4 Propositions? ❖ E=mc2 ❖ The sun rises from the East every day. ❖ All species on Earth evolved from a common ancestor. ❖ God does not exist. ❖ Everyone eventually dies. !5 ❖ And some of you might already be wondering: “If I wanted to study mathematics, I would have majored in Math. I came here to study computer science.” !6 ❖ Computer Science is mathematics, but we almost exclusively focus on aspects of mathematics that relate to computation (that can be implemented in software and/or hardware). !7 ❖Logic is the language of computer science and, mathematics is the computer scientist’s most essential toolbox. !8 Examples of “CS-relevant” Math ❖ Algorithm A correctly solves problem P. ❖ Algorithm A has a worst-case running time of O(n3). ❖ Problem P has no solution. ❖ Using comparison between two elements as the basic operation, we cannot sort a list of n elements in less than O(n log n) time. ❖ Problem A is NP-Complete.
    [Show full text]
  • Yuji NISHIYAMA in This Article We Shall Focus Our Attention Upon
    The Notion of Presupposition* Yuji NISHIYAMA Keio University In this article we shall focus our attention upon the clarificationof the notion of presupposition;First, we shall be concerned with what kind of notion is best understood as the proper notion of presupposition that grammars of natural languageshould deal with. In this connection,we shall defend "logicalpresupposi tion". Second, we shall consider how to specify the range of X and Y in the presuppositionformula "X presupposes Y". Third, we shall discuss several difficultieswith the standard definition of logical presupposition. In connection with this, we shall propose a clear distinction between "the definition of presupposi tion" and "the rule of presupposition". 1. The logical notion of presupposition What is a presupposition? Or, more particularly, what is the alleged result of a presupposition failure? In spite of the attention given to it, this question can hardly be said to have been settled. Various answers have been suggested by the various authors: inappropriate use of a sentence, failure to perform an illocutionary act, anomaly, ungrammaticality, unintelligibility, infelicity, lack of truth value-each has its advocates. Some of the apparent disagreementmay be only a notational and terminological, but other disagreement raises real, empirically significant, theoretical questions regarding the relationship between logic and language. However, it is not the aim of this article to straighten out the various proposals about the concept of presupposition. Rather, we will be concerned with one notion of presupposition,which stems from Frege (1892)and Strawson (1952),that is: (1) presupposition is a condition under which a sentence expressing an assertive proposition can be used to make a statement (or can bear a truth value)1 We shall call this notion of presupposition "the statementhood condition" or "the conditionfor bivalence".
    [Show full text]
  • On Axiomatizations of General Many-Valued Propositional Calculi
    On axiomatizations of general many-valued propositional calculi Arto Salomaa Turku Centre for Computer Science Joukahaisenkatu 3{5 B, 20520 Turku, Finland asalomaa@utu.fi Abstract We present a general setup for many-valued propositional logics, and compare truth-table and axiomatic stipulations within this setup. Results are obtained concerning cases, where a finitary axiomatization is (resp. is not) possible. Related problems and examples are discussed. 1 Introduction Many-valued systems of logic are constructed by introducing one or more truth- values between truth and falsity. Truth-functions associated with the logical connectives then operate with more than two truth-values. For instance, the truth-function D associated with the 3-valued disjunction might be defined for the truth-values T;I;F (true, intermediate, false) by D(x; y) = max(x; y); where T > I > F: If the truth-function N associated with negation is defined by N(T ) = F; N(F ) = T;N(I) = I; the law of the excluded middle is not valid, provided \validity" means that the truth-value t results for all assignments of values for the variables. On the other hand, many-valuedness is not so obvious if the axiomatic method is used. As such, an ordinary axiomatization is not many-valued. Truth-tables are essential for the latter. However, in many cases it is possi- ble to axiomatize many-valued logics and, conversely, find many-valued models for axiom systems. In this paper, we will investigate (for propositional log- ics) interconnections between such \truth-value stipulations" and \axiomatic stipulations". A brief outline of the contents of this paper follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Logic Part One
    Mathematical Logic Part One An Important Question How do we formalize the logic we've been using in our proofs? Where We're Going ● Propositional Logic (Today) ● Basic logical connectives. ● Truth tables. ● Logical equivalences. ● First-Order Logic (Today/Friday) ● Reasoning about properties of multiple objects. Propositional Logic A proposition is a statement that is, by itself, either true or false. Some Sample Propositions ● Puppies are cuter than kittens. ● Kittens are cuter than puppies. ● Usain Bolt can outrun everyone in this room. ● CS103 is useful for cocktail parties. ● This is the last entry on this list. More Propositions ● I came in like a wrecking ball. ● I am a champion. ● You're going to hear me roar. ● We all just entertainers. Things That Aren't Propositions CommandsCommands cannotcannot bebe truetrue oror false.false. Things That Aren't Propositions QuestionsQuestions cannotcannot bebe truetrue oror false.false. Things That Aren't Propositions TheThe firstfirst halfhalf isis aa validvalid proposition.proposition. I am the walrus, goo goo g'joob JibberishJibberish cannotcannot bebe truetrue oror false. false. Propositional Logic ● Propositional logic is a mathematical system for reasoning about propositions and how they relate to one another. ● Every statement in propositional logic consists of propositional variables combined via logical connectives. ● Each variable represents some proposition, such as “You liked it” or “You should have put a ring on it.” ● Connectives encode how propositions are related, such as “If you liked it, then you should have put a ring on it.” Propositional Variables ● Each proposition will be represented by a propositional variable. ● Propositional variables are usually represented as lower-case letters, such as p, q, r, s, etc.
    [Show full text]