COMPARATIVE BIOLOGY: FORM, TIME and SPACE (1: Systematicsand Biogeography;Cladistics and Vicarianceby Gareth Nelson and Norman Platnick

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

COMPARATIVE BIOLOGY: FORM, TIME and SPACE (1: Systematicsand Biogeography;Cladistics and Vicarianceby Gareth Nelson and Norman Platnick COMPARATIVE BIOLOGY: FORM, TIME AND SPACE (1: Systematicsand Biogeography;Cladistics and Vicarianceby Gareth Nelson and Norman Platnick. Columbia University Press, New York, 1981. xi + 567 p. $ 35.00.) Progressing from the maxim that earth and life have evolved together, and taking their organizing principle from the title of a book by CROizaT (1964) Space, Time, Form: The BiologicalSynthesis, Gareth Nelson and Norman Platnick introduce the prob- lematic of their book-an inquiry into the theoretical structure of comparative biology and the nature of our knowledge of organismic diversity. Their treatise opens with an introductory chapter of some 50 + pages, providing the reader with what is essentially an extended precis of the book's contents. Comparative biology is resolved into the elements of Croizat's "alternative threefold parallelism" - Form, Time and Space-and selected subdisciplines-systematics, embryology, paleontology and biogeography---are introduced. This first chapter explores in a nov- el and entertaining way the problems posed by pattern analysis in the three realms, and outlines the methodological tools adopted for their resolution. Like much of the rest of the book, it is clearly written, with problems interestingly formulated and concepts simply, if sometimes controversially, outlined. For example, in a discussion of "kinds" of organisms (species and groups-it is with the latter that the book is centrally concerned) the "species problem" is neatly dispatched and, for the authors' purposes, the sufficient concept of species as "simply the smallest detected samples of self-perpetuating organisms that have unique sets of characterrs" is provided (page 12). The remaining 480 pages are subdivided into seven chapters mirroring the structure of the introduction: FORM-systematichistory (chapt. 2), systematic pattern (chapt. 3), systematic results (chapt. 4), TIME-ontogeny,phylogeny, paleontology and the bio- genetic law (chapt.5), sPa.cE-biogeographic history (chapt. 6) biogeographic pattern (chapt. 7), biogeographic results (chapt. 8). As is perhaps to be expected, the historical considerations (basically chapters 2 and 6) pose least in the way of controversy-they are however, well-written and informa- tive. In their reassessment of the fields of systematics and biogeography Nelson and Platnick recognise in their own results the older notions of pre-evolutionary scientists - of "natural groups" (taxa) and of "natural areas" (regions). In stressing that "Sys- tematics and biogeography are sciences rich in past accomplishments" the authors' are keen to acknowledge a historical imperative and the historical perspective adopted lends insight into the ideas presented in the book. It is pleasing to find two champions of the contributions of Hennig and Croizat stressing an intellectual precedent in the earlier works of Rosa, Mitchell and A.-P. de Candolle, to mention but a few. Turning to more recent history and in a novel treatment of the phyletic versus phenetic versus gradistic controversy, various approaches to the "stability problem" of classification are outlined. The key to the general solution of the problem is located in Hennig's type of branching diagrams (page 142), and there follows a clear expo- sition of what is essentially the transformation of "traditional" phyletic-cladistics into a method of greater generality-a general method of taxonomy. The heuristic distinction between phyletictrees-depicting "aspects of evolutionary genealogies", and cladogramsdepicting "structural elements of knowledge" intro- duced in the first chapter is elaborated. From the statement "taxa A and B are related by common ancestry" two parts are extracted: "taxa A and B are related" (the clad- istic part), and "by common ancestry" (the phyletic part). The decoupling of the cladistic from the phyletic (or phenetic, or gradistic, or whatever) renders a branching 587 diagram illustrating an unspecified relation between certain specified terms (which may be taxa, areas of endemism, or even ethnographic artifacts). This decoupling provides a necessary separation if the pattern of relationship specified by cladistic analy- sis is to provide an adequate test of predictions derived from any particular theory of process.It is perhaps the recognition, and subsequent application, of the generality of the cladistic method and the distinction made between cladograms and phyletic trees, that distinguishes this book and its authors. But what of the important relation "synapomorphy"? Hennig defined synapomor- phy as "shared derived character", Nelson and Platnick take the abstraction further and explore is as a "subset". "Homology implies generality (that there is a set that includes ...), and synapomorphy implies relative, or restricted, generality (that there is a subset included in ...)" (page 158). Viewed in this way both homology and synapomorphy emerge as concepts which may be considered without reference to evolutionary theory-thus the numerous successful homology statements of the pre- evolutionary systematists. An illuminating discussion of homology in this vein is pre- sented in PATTERSON(1982). It is in that paper incidentally, we learn that Nelson's influential and much cited manuscript (Cladograms and trees, 1976) is now published as part of the book under review. Interesting also in this context, is the fact that although many of the ideas in the book are also to be found (often verbatim) in previous publications of both authors, there is no reference to this whole body of their work. It is no exageration to say that much of the book is about branching diagrams; their application and meaning in comparative biology. Regarding such diagrams as variously successful integrations of information. Nelson's method of "component analysis" emerges as a "general calculus" applicable to the examination of any branching diagram. The method is elaborated in considerable, one might almost say excruciating, detail in relation to systematics in chapters 3 and 4, and biogeographic analysis in chapter 7. Restricted to the practicably manageable analysis of basic 3- taxon (or 3-area) problems-more complex problems are reduceable to a series of 3-term statements-component analysis is essentially a means of revealing the infor- mation content of competing diagrams and classifications. Elaborated by the intro- duction of the concept the "general cladogram" (page 314), the method provides a criterion (the "cladistic parameter") for the selection of the most "efficient"-the most "informative" of competing diagrams. Once again, as there is "no necessary correlation between the cladistic parameter and any one discipline, such as phyletics, phenetics, or gradistics" (page 319), the generality of the method is stressed. What is being developed is a "theory of general cladograms"-a conceptual system with wide applicability. Chapter 5, intended as "a synthesis of the material preceeding it, with respect to the temporal dimension" is, in the authors' words "something of a digressionary in- terlude". Given the scope of a chapter subtitled-ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology and the biogenetic law-it is not surprising that an attempted coverage in 21 pages (without a single branching diagram) is inadequate. Consideration of the temporal dimension of comparative biology is too scant rather than digressionary. Nonetheless the authors do raise some interesting propositions-it is a pity that they are not ela- borated in more detail or with more substance. Of Agassiz' threefold parallelism-ontogeny, phylogeny and paleontology-it is ontogeny that emerges as being of decisive importance. The orderliness of ontogeny - that the empirically observable transformations of ontogeny always seem to proceed from the general to the particular-is stressed, and comparative anatomy and paleontology are relegated to secondary disciplines ordering their data in conformity with the framework provided by ontogeny and its orderliness. .
Recommended publications
  • Integrative and Comparative Biology Integrative and Comparative Biology, Volume 58, Number 4, Pp
    Integrative and Comparative Biology Integrative and Comparative Biology, volume 58, number 4, pp. 605–622 doi:10.1093/icb/icy088 Society for Integrative and Comparative Biology SYMPOSIUM INTRODUCTION The Temporal and Environmental Context of Early Animal Evolution: Considering All the Ingredients of an “Explosion” Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/icb/article-abstract/58/4/605/5056706 by Stanford Medical Center user on 15 October 2018 Erik A. Sperling1 and Richard G. Stockey Department of Geological Sciences, Stanford University, 450 Serra Mall, Building 320, Stanford, CA 94305, USA From the symposium “From Small and Squishy to Big and Armored: Genomic, Ecological and Paleontological Insights into the Early Evolution of Animals” presented at the annual meeting of the Society for Integrative and Comparative Biology, January 3–7, 2018 at San Francisco, California. 1E-mail: [email protected] Synopsis Animals originated and evolved during a unique time in Earth history—the Neoproterozoic Era. This paper aims to discuss (1) when landmark events in early animal evolution occurred, and (2) the environmental context of these evolutionary milestones, and how such factors may have affected ecosystems and body plans. With respect to timing, molecular clock studies—utilizing a diversity of methodologies—agree that animal multicellularity had arisen by 800 million years ago (Ma) (Tonian period), the bilaterian body plan by 650 Ma (Cryogenian), and divergences between sister phyla occurred 560–540 Ma (late Ediacaran). Most purported Tonian and Cryogenian animal body fossils are unlikely to be correctly identified, but independent support for the presence of pre-Ediacaran animals is recorded by organic geochemical biomarkers produced by demosponges.
    [Show full text]
  • Phylogenetic Comparative Methods: a User's Guide for Paleontologists
    Phylogenetic Comparative Methods: A User’s Guide for Paleontologists Laura C. Soul - Department of Paleobiology, National Museum of Natural History, Smithsonian Institution, Washington, DC, USA David F. Wright - Division of Paleontology, American Museum of Natural History, Central Park West at 79th Street, New York, New York 10024, USA and Department of Paleobiology, National Museum of Natural History, Smithsonian Institution, Washington, DC, USA Abstract. Recent advances in statistical approaches called Phylogenetic Comparative Methods (PCMs) have provided paleontologists with a powerful set of analytical tools for investigating evolutionary tempo and mode in fossil lineages. However, attempts to integrate PCMs with fossil data often present workers with practical challenges or unfamiliar literature. In this paper, we present guides to the theory behind, and application of, PCMs with fossil taxa. Based on an empirical dataset of Paleozoic crinoids, we present example analyses to illustrate common applications of PCMs to fossil data, including investigating patterns of correlated trait evolution, and macroevolutionary models of morphological change. We emphasize the importance of accounting for sources of uncertainty, and discuss how to evaluate model fit and adequacy. Finally, we discuss several promising methods for modelling heterogenous evolutionary dynamics with fossil phylogenies. Integrating phylogeny-based approaches with the fossil record provides a rigorous, quantitative perspective to understanding key patterns in the history of life. 1. Introduction A fundamental prediction of biological evolution is that a species will most commonly share many characteristics with lineages from which it has recently diverged, and fewer characteristics with lineages from which it diverged further in the past. This principle, which results from descent with modification, is one of the most basic in biology (Darwin 1859).
    [Show full text]
  • Cognition, Biology and Evolution of Musicality Rstb.Royalsocietypublishing.Org Henkjan Honing1, Carel Ten Cate2, Isabelle Peretz3 and Sandra E
    Downloaded from http://rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org/ on February 2, 2015 Without it no music: cognition, biology and evolution of musicality rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org Henkjan Honing1, Carel ten Cate2, Isabelle Peretz3 and Sandra E. Trehub4 1Amsterdam Brain and Cognition (ABC), Institute for Logic, Language and Computation (ILLC), University of Amsterdam, PO Box 94242, 1090 CE Amsterdam, The Netherlands 2Institute of Biology Leiden (IBL), Leiden Institute for Brain and Cognition (LIBC), Leiden University, Introduction PO Box 9505, 2300 RA Leiden, The Netherlands 3Center for Research on Brain, Language and Music and BRAMS, Department of Psychology, University of Cite this article: Honing H, ten Cate C, Peretz Montreal, 1420 Mount Royal Boulevard, Montreal, Canada H3C 3J7 4 I, Trehub SE. 2015 Without it no music: Department of Psychology, University of Toronto Mississauga, 3359 Mississauga Road, Mississauga, Canada L5L 1C6 cognition, biology and evolution of musicality. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 370: 20140088. Musicality can be defined as a natural, spontaneously developing trait based http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0088 on and constrained by biology and cognition. Music, by contrast, can be defined as a social and cultural construct based on that very musicality. One contribution of 12 to a theme issue One critical challenge is to delineate the constituent elements of musicality. What biological and cognitive mechanisms are essential for perceiving, appre- ‘Biology, cognition and origins of musicality’. ciating and making music? Progress in understanding the evolution of music cognition depends upon adequate characterization of the constituent mechan- Subject Areas: isms of musicality and the extent to which they are present in non-human behaviour, evolution, cognition, neuroscience, species.
    [Show full text]
  • Clearing the Highest Hurdle: Human-Based Case Studies Broaden Students’ Knowledge of Core Evolutionary Concepts
    The Journal of Effective Teaching an online journal devoted to teaching excellence Clearing the highest hurdle: Human-based case studies broaden students’ knowledge of core evolutionary concepts Alexander J. Werth1 Hampden-Sydney College, Hampden-Sydney, VA 23943 Abstract An anonymous survey instrument was used for a ten year study to gauge college student attitudes toward evolution. Results indicate that students are most likely to accept evolu- tion as a historical process for change in physical features of non-human organisms. They are less likely to accept evolution as an ongoing process that shapes all traits (including biochemical, physiological, and behavioral) in humans. Students who fail to accept the factual nature of human evolution do not gain an accurate view of evolution, let alone modern biology. Fortunately, because of students’ natural curiosity about their bodies and related topics (e.g., medicine, vestigial features, human prehistory), a pedagogical focus on human evolution provides a fun and effective way to teach core evolutionary concepts, as quantified by the survey. Results of the study are presented along with useful case studies involving human evolution. Keywords: Survey, pedagogy, biology, evolution, Darwin. All science educators face pedagogical difficulties, but when considering the social rami- fications of scientific ideas, few face as great a challenge as biology teachers. Studies consistently show more than half of Americans reject any concept of biological evolution (Harris Poll, 2005, Miller et al., 2006). Students embody just such a cross-section of soci- ety. Much ink has been spilled explaining how best to teach evolution, particularly to unwilling students (Cavallo and McCall, 2008, Nelson, 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Thinking in Biology
    Comparative Thinking in Biology Adrian Currie This material has been published in the Cambridge University Press series Elements in the Philosophy of Biology, edited by Grant Ramsey and Michael Ruse. This version is free to view and download for personal use only. Not for re-distribution, re-sale or use in derivative works. © Adrian Currie. Acknowledgements I’m grateful to Marta Halina, Sabina Leonelli, Alison McConwell, Aaron Novick, Trevor Pearce, Russell Powell, William Wong and two anonymous referees for extremely useful and kind feedback on draft material. Also thanks to Grant Ramsey and Michael Ruse. Ideas from this element were presented to Exeter’s Cognition and Culture reading group, at Philosophy of Biology at Dolphin Beach 13 and at the Recent Trends in Philosophy of Biology conference in Bilkent; thanks to the audiences there. Many thanks to Kimberly Brumble for the wonderful illustrations. Some of the research for this Element was funded by the Templeton World Charity Foundation. Dedicated to the incomparable Kate. Table of Contents Cats versus Dogs............................................................................................................................... 1 1. Comparative Thinking .......................................................................................................... 14 1.1 Comparative Concepts .................................................................................................... 14 1.2 Two Kinds of Inference ...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Integrative and Comparative Biology Integrative and Comparative Biology, Volume 59, Number 4, Pp
    Integrative and Comparative Biology Integrative and Comparative Biology, volume 59, number 4, pp. 856–863 doi:10.1093/icb/icz132 Society for Integrative and Comparative Biology SYMPOSIUM INTRODUCTION Beyond the Powerhouse: Integrating Mitonuclear Evolution, Physiology, and Theory in Comparative Biology Justin C. Havird,* Ryan J. Weaver,*,† Liliana Milani ,‡ Fabrizio Ghiselli ,‡ Ryan Greenway,§ Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/icb/article/59/4/856/5542403 by Auburn University user on 30 April 2021 Adam J. Ramsey,¶ Ana G. Jimenez ,k Damian K. Dowling ,# Wendy R. Hood ,† Kristi L. Montooth ,** Suzanne Estes,†† Patricia M. Schulte,‡‡ Inna M. Sokolova ,§§,¶¶ and Geoffrey E. Hill 1,† *Department of Integrative Biology, University of Texas, Austin, TX 78712, USA; †Department of Biological Sciences, Auburn University, Auburn, AL 36849, USA; ‡Department of Biological, Geological and Environmental Sciences (BiGeA), University of Bologna, Bologna, 40126, Italy; §Division of Biology, Kansas State University, Manhattan, KS 66506, USA; ¶Department of Biological Sciences, University of Memphis, Memphis, TN 38152, USA; kDepartment of Biology, Colgate University, Hamilton, NY 13346, USA; #School of Biological Sciences, Monash University, Clayton, Victoria 3800, Australia; **School of Biological Sciences, University of Nebraska-Lincoln, Lincoln, NE 68502, USA; ††Department of Biology, Portland State University, Portland, OR 97201, USA; ‡‡Department of Zoology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC V6T 1Z4, Canada; §§Department of Marine Biology, Institute of Biological Sciences, University of Rostock, Rostock, Germany; ¶¶Department of Maritime Systems, Interdisciplinary Faculty, University of Rostock, Rostock, Germany From the symposium “Beyond the powerhouse: integrating mitonuclear evolution, physiology, and theory in comparative biology” presented at the annual meeting of the Society for Integrative and Comparative Biology, January 3–7, 2019 at Tampa, Florida.
    [Show full text]
  • Phylogenetic Systematics As the Basis of Comparative Biology
    SMITHSONIAN CONTRIBUTIONS TO BOTANY NUMBER 73 Phylogenetic Systematics as the Basis of Comparative Biology KA. Funk and Daniel R. Brooks SMITHSONIAN INSTITUTION PRESS Washington, D.C. 1990 ABSTRACT Funk, V.A. and Daniel R. Brooks. Phylogenetic Systematics as the Basis of Comparative Biology. Smithsonian Contributions to Botany, number 73, 45 pages, 102 figures, 12 tables, 199O.-Evolution is the unifying concept of biology. The study of evolution can be approached from a within-lineage (microevolution) or among-lineage (macroevolution) perspective. Phylogenetic systematics (cladistics) is the appropriate basis for all among-liieage studies in comparative biology. Phylogenetic systematics enhances studies in comparative biology in many ways. In the study of developmental constraints, the use of such phylogenies allows for the investigation of the possibility that ontogenetic changes (heterochrony) alone may be sufficient to explain the perceived magnitude of phenotypic change. Speciation via hybridization can be suggested, based on the character patterns of phylogenies. Phylogenetic systematics allows one to examine the potential of historical explanations for biogeographic patterns as well as modes of speciation. The historical components of coevolution, along with ecological and behavioral diversification, can be compared to the explanations of adaptation and natural selection. Because of the explanatory capabilities of phylogenetic systematics, studies in comparative biology that are not based on such phylogenies fail to reach their potential. OFFICIAL PUBLICATION DATE is handstamped in a limited number of initial copies and is recorded in the Institution's annual report, Srnithonhn Year. SERIES COVER DESIGN: Leaf clearing from the katsura tree Cercidiphyllumjaponicum Siebold and Zuccarini. Library of Cmgrcss Cataloging-in-PublicationDiaa Funk, V.A (Vicki A.), 1947- PhylogmttiC ryrtcmaticsas tk basis of canpamtive biology / V.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Developmental Psychology: How Is Human Cognitive Development Unique?
    Evolutionary Psychology www.epjournal.net – 2014. 12(2): 448-473 ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Original Article Comparative Developmental Psychology: How is Human Cognitive Development Unique? Alexandra G. Rosati, Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT, USA. Email: [email protected] (Corresponding author). Victoria Wobber, Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA. Kelly Hughes, Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, University of Rochester, Rochester, NY, USA. Laurie R. Santos, Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT, USA. Abstract: The fields of developmental and comparative psychology both seek to illuminate the roots of adult cognitive systems. Developmental studies target the emergence of adult cognitive systems over ontogenetic time, whereas comparative studies investigate the origins of human cognition in our evolutionary history. Despite the long tradition of research in both of these areas, little work has examined the intersection of the two: the study of cognitive development in a comparative perspective. In the current article, we review recent work using this comparative developmental approach to study non-human primate cognition. We argue that comparative data on the pace and pattern of cognitive development across species can address major theoretical questions in both psychology and biology. In particular, such integrative research will allow stronger biological inferences about the function of developmental change, and will be critical in addressing how humans come to acquire species-unique cognitive abilities. Keywords: comparative development, primate cognition, heterochrony, human adaptation ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Introduction Human behavior is strikingly different from that of other animals. We speak language, routinely cooperate with others to reach complex shared goals, engage in abstract reasoning and scientific inquiry, and learn a rich set of sophisticated cultural behaviors from others.
    [Show full text]
  • How Language Adapts to the Environment: an Evolutionary, Experimental Approach
    How Language Adapts to the Environment: An Evolutionary, Experimental Approach Jonas Nölle 2021 Submitted in fulfilment of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy to School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences University of Edinburgh To my parents and grandparents ii Lay Summary Why do humans speak different languages instead of the same? Is this simply the outcome of arbitrary cultural conventions that we decided upon, or can linguistic diversity be explained by other factors? This thesis explores whether human languages adapt to their environment in a similar way to organisms in biological evolution. To test whether this is the case, I conducted two series of experiments. In the first series pairs of participants came into the lab and had to play a game where they could only use their hands to communicate about cartoon pictures. In two experiments we found that the way in which they system- atically picked up traits from these cartoon pictures, and which traits they chose, depended on the context, for example how many targets they were communicating about, and whether they could see the targets or had to recall them from memory. This suggests that a fundamental property of human languages, the ability to mark systematic categories depends, to some extent, on the environment in which these languages develop, which could lead to diversity. A second series of experiments made use of virtual reality games, where participants had to communicate about the location of orbs. Different languages have different preferences for how they express spatial relations, e.g., the orb is to the left of you vs the orb is uphill from you.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Biology: Beyond Sequence Analysis Itay Tirosh1, Yonatan Bilu1 and Naama Barkai1,2
    Comparative biology: beyond sequence analysis Itay Tirosh1, Yonatan Bilu1 and Naama Barkai1,2 Comparative analysis is a fundamental tool in biology. Whereas most comparative studies focus on conserved Conservation among species greatly assists the detection properties as means for characterizing functional ele- and characterization of functional elements, whereas ments, inter-species differences are also of interest. inter-species differences are probably the best indicators These differences are arguably the best indicators of of biological adaptation. Traditionally, comparative evolutionary history and provide much information about approaches were applied to the analysis of genomic species-specific adaptations. Identifying such differences sequences. With the growing availability of functional is thus central to our search for what makes us human and genomic data, comparative paradigms are now being how biological diversity is generated. extended also to the study of other functional attributes, most notably the gene expression. Here we review recent Technological advances over the past decade have led to works applying comparative analysis to large-scale gene the accumulation of genome-scale data describing not expression datasets and discuss the central principles and only gene sequence but also functional properties in- challenges of such approaches. cluding gene expression, protein–protein interactions, Addresses and the binding of transcription factors to DNA. Such 1 Department of Molecular Genetics, Weizmann Institute of Science,
    [Show full text]
  • Felsenstein's 'Phylogenies A
    Manuscript type: Historical comment Title: Revisiting a Key Innovation in Evolutionary Biology: Felsenstein’s ‘Phylogenies and the Comparative Method’ Authors: Raymond B. Huey1,*, Theodore Garland, Jr.2, and Michael Turelli3 1 Department of Biology, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington 98195; 2 Department of Evolution, Ecology, and Organismal Biology, University of California, Riverside, California 92521; 3 Department of Evolution and Ecology, University of California, Davis, California 95616 Running Head: Revisiting Felsenstein (1985) Appendices: A, B, C * Corresponding author: [email protected] ABSTRACT: The comparative method has long been a fundamental exploratory tool in evolutionary biology, but this venerable approach was revolutionized in 1985, when Felsenstein published “Phylogenies and the Comparative Method” in The American Naturalist. This paper forced comparative biologists to start thinking phylogenetically when conducting statistical analyses of correlated trait evolution, rather than simply applying conventional statistical methods that ignore evolutionary relationships. It did so by introducing a novel analytical method (phylogenetically “independent contrasts”) that required a phylogenetic topology with branch lengths and that assumed a Brownian motion model of trait evolution. Independent contrasts enabled comparative biologists to avoid the statistical dilemma of non-independence of species values, arising from shared ancestry, but came at the cost of needing a detailed phylogeny and of accepting a specific model of character change. Nevertheless, this paper not only revitalized comparative biology, but even encouraged studies aimed at estimating phylogenies. Felsenstein’s characteristically lucid and concise statement of the problem (illustrated with powerful graphics), coupled with an oncoming flood of new molecular data and techniques for estimating phylogenies, led Felsenstein ‘85 to become the second most cited paper in the history of this journal.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Nothing Make Sense Except in the Light of Evolution'?
    To appear in Acta Biotheoretica 1 In what sense does ‘nothing make sense except in the light of 1 evolution’? Paul E. Griffiths Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, NSW 2006, Australia & ESRC Centre for Genomics in Society, University of Exeter, Exeter, EX4 4PJ, UK [email protected] Abstract Dobzhansky argued that biology only makes sense if life on earth has a shared history. But his dictum is often reinterpreted to mean that biology only makes sense in the light of adaptation. Some philosophers of science have argued in this spirit that all work in ‘proximal’ biosciences such as anatomy, physiology and molecular biology must be framed, at least implicitly, by the selection histories of the organisms under study. Others have denied this and have proposed non-evolutionary ways in which biologists can frame these investigations. This paper argues that an evolutionary perspective is indeed necessary, but that it must be a forward-looking perspective informed by a general understanding of the evolutionary process, not a backward-looking perspective informed by the specific evolutionary history of the species being studied. Interestingly, it turns out that there are aspects of proximal biology that even a creationist cannot study except in the light of a theory of their effect on future evolution. 1. Dobzhansky’s dictum Classic scientific articles are often more cited than read. ‘Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution’ by the Ukranian-American geneticist Theodosius Dobzhansky (1973) is no exception. It argues that the observed diversity of life and its distribution on the earth’s surface make no sense when viewed as the result of the special creation of each species by God.
    [Show full text]