Some Results in the Extension with a Coherent Suslin Tree

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Some Results in the Extension with a Coherent Suslin Tree Some results in the extension with a coherent Suslin tree Teruyuki Yorioka (Shizuoka University) Winter School in Abstract Analysis section Set Theory & Topology 28th January { 4th February, 2012 Motivation Theorem (Kunen, Rowbottom, Solovay, etc). implies K : Every ccc forcing MA@1 2 has property K. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Does K imply ? 2 MA@1 Theorem (Todorˇcevi´c). PID +p > @1 implies no S-spaces. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PID, does no S-spaces imply p > @1? Definition (Todorˇcevi´c). PFA(S) is an axiom that there exists a coherent Suslin tree S such that the forcing axiom holds for every proper forcing which preserves S to be Suslin. Theorem (Farah). t = @1 holds in the extension with a Suslin tree. Proof. Suppose that T is a Suslin tree, and take π : T ! [!]@0 such that ∗ s ≤T t ! π(s) ⊇ π(t) and s ?T t ! π(s) \ π(t) finite: Then for a generic branch G through T , the set fπ(s): s 2 Gg is a ⊆∗-decreasing sequence which doesn't have its lower bound in [!]@0. Motivation Theorem (Kunen, Rowbottom, Solovay, etc). implies K : Every ccc forcing MA@1 2 has property K. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Does K imply ? 2 MA@1 Theorem (Todorˇcevi´c). PID +p > @1 implies no S-spaces. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PID, does no S-spaces imply p > @1? Definition (Todorˇcevi´c). PFA(S) is an axiom that there exists a coherent Suslin tree S such that the forcing axiom holds for every proper forcing which preserves S to be Suslin. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PFA(S), does S force K2? Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PFA(S), does S force no S-spaces? Question. What statements can be forced by S under PFA(S)? Motivation Theorem (Kunen, Rowbottom, Solovay, etc). implies K : Every ccc forcing MA@1 2 has property K. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Does K imply ? 2 MA@1 Theorem (Todorˇcevi´c). PID +p > @1 implies no S-spaces. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PID, does no S-spaces imply p > @1? Definition (Todorˇcevi´c). PFA(S) is an axiom that there exists a coherent Suslin tree S such that the forcing axiom holds for every proper forcing which preserves S to be Suslin. Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PFA(S), does S force K2? Question (Todorˇcevi´c). Under PFA(S), does S force no S-spaces? Question. What statements can be forced by S under PFA(S)? PFA(S) was introduced to combines many of the consequences of the two contra- dictory set theoretic axioms, the weak diamond principle, and PFA. Theorem (Consequences from the weak }). A Suslin tree forces the following. (Farah) t = @1. (Farah) It doesn't hold that all @1-dense subsets of the reals are isomorphic. (Larson{Todorˇcevi´c) Every ladder system has an ununiformized coloring. (Larson{Todorˇcevi´c) There are no Q-sets. (Moore{Hruˇs´ak{Dˇzamonja) }(R; R; =)6 holds. Theorem (Consequences from PFA). Under PFA(S), S forces the following. @ (Todorˇcevi´c) 2 0 = @2 = h = add(N ). (Farah) The open graph dichotomy. (Todorˇcevi´c) The P -ideal dichotomy. (Todorˇcevi´c) There are no compact S-spaces. Today, we see the following. Theorem. Under PFA(S), S forces the following. x1. Every forcing with rectangle refining property has precaliber @1. x2. There are no !2-Aronszajn trees. x3. All Aronszajn trees are club-isomorphic. x4. The weak club guessing and f fail. x1. Every forcing with rec. ref. has precaliber @1 in the ext. with S under PFA(S). Definition. FSCO0 is the collection of forcing notions P such that • conditions of P are finite sets of countable ordinals, • P is uncountable, and • ≤P is equal to the superset relation ⊇, that is, for any σ and τ in P, σ ≤P τ iff σ ⊇ τ. E.g., a specialization of an Aronszajn tree, freezing an (!1;!1)-gap, adding an uncountable homogeneous set of a partition. Definition (Y.). A forcing notion P in FSCO0 has the rectangle refining property (REC) if P is uncountable and for any I and J 2 [P]@1, if I [ J forms a ∆-system, then 0 @ 0 @ 0 0 there are I 2 [I] 1 and J 2 [J] 1 s.t. for every p 2 I and q 2 J , p 6?P q. Note that REC implies CCC. FSCO2 ⊆ FSCO0 is defined (omitted here). Lemma. For any ladder system and its colorig, there is a forcing with REC in FSCO2 which adds a function uniformizing the coloring. Theorem (Larson{Todorˇcevi´c). In the extension with a coherent Suslin tree, every ladder system has a coloring which cannot be uniformized. So, forces that ( in ) fails. S MA@1 REC FSCO2 Lemma. Under ( ), forces that every forcing with in has pre- MA@1 S S REC FSCO2 caliber @1. Therefore, Theorem. Under ( ), forces that every forcing with in has MA@1 S S REC FSCO2 precaliber @ and ( in ) fails. 1 MA@1 REC FSCO2 Compare with the following. Theorem (Todorˇcevi´c{Veliˇckovi´c). Every ccc forcing has precaliber @ iff 1 MA@1 holds. x2. There are no !2-Aronszajn trees in the extension with S under PFA(S). This proof is quite standard. Claim. For a σ-closed forcing P and an S-name T_ for an !2-tree, P adds no new S-names for cofinal chains through T_ whenever c > @1 holds. Claim. For an S-name T_ for a tree of size @1 and of height !1 which doesn't have uncountable (i.e. cofinal) chains through T_, there exists a ccc forcing notion which preserves S to be Suslin and forces T_ to be special (i.e. to be a union of countably many antichains through T_). The following is the motivation of this work. Theorem (Todorˇcvi´c). PFA implies the failure of κ,ω1 for any unctbl κ. Theorem (Magidor). It is consistent that PFA and κ,ω2 hold for any unctbl κ. Theorem (Magidor). It is consistent that PDFA and κ,ω1 hold for any unctbl κ. Theorem (Raghavan). PID implies the failure of κ,ω, for any unctbl κ, and @ PID +b > 1 implies the failure of κ,ω1 for any κ with cf(κ) > !1. @ Question. Does PID +p > 1 imply the failure of !1;!1? We note that !1;!1 holds iff there exists a special !2-Aronszajn tree. Claim. For an S-name T_ for a tree of size @1 and of height !1 which doesn't have uncountable (i.e. cofinal) chains through T_, there exists a ccc forcing notion which preserves S to be Suslin and forces T_ to be special (i.e. to be a union of countably many antichains through T_). Sketch. Assume that <_ T is an S-name such that S \ T_ = h!1; <_ T i " and for any 2 6? _ s S and α, β in !1, if s S \ α T_ β " and α < β, then s S \ α <T_ β ". Take a club C on !1 s.t. for every δ 2 C, every node of Sδ decides <_ T \ (δ × δ). [ ( ) <@ σ P consists of finite partial functions p : S ! [!1] 0 such that σ2[!]<@0 • for every s 2 dom(p) and n 2 dom(p(s)), p(s)(n) ⊆ sup(C \ lv(s)) and s S \ p(s)(n) is an antichain in T_ "; • for every s and t in dom(p), if s <S t, then for every n 2 dom(p(s))\dom(p(t)), t S \ p(s)(n) [ p(t)(n) is an antichain in T_ "; p ≤P q : () p ⊇ q: Note that P adds an S-name which witnesses that T_ to be special in the extension with S. It is proved that if P×S has an uncountable antichain, then some node of S forces that T_ has an uncountable chain. x3. All Aronszajn trees are club-isomorphic in the extension with S under PFA(S). _ _ _ _ ⊆ <!1 ⊆ Let T and US-names for Aronszajn trees s.t. S \ T; U ! & <T_ =<U_ = ": P consists of the functions p such that • dom(p) is a finite 2-chain of countable elementary submodels of H(@2) with S, T_ and U_ , D E • 2 p p 2 for each M dom(p), p(M) = tM ; fM , where tM S and p p p p p αM ! αM fM : ! ! ; non-empty finite partial injection for some αM < ht(tM ), • for each M; M0 2 dom(p) with M0 2 M, p 62 , p 2 , p 62 and p 2 tM M tM0 M αM M αM0 M; • for each M 2 dom(p), p ≤ p ≤ p _ \ αM _ \ αM { tM decides the S-names T ! and U ! , p p ⊆ _ p ⊆ _ { tM S \ dom(fM ) T & ran(fM ) U "; and [ { p \ p [ p is an order-preserving map whose domain is tM S fM0 fM M02dom(p)\M with tp < tp M0 S M a subtree of T_ in which every maximal n chain is of height o 0 2 dom( ) \ ; p p + 1 ", M p M tM0 <S tM DD E E DD E E p p 2 q q 2 P and for each p = tM ; fM ; M dom(p) and q = tM ; fM ; M dom(q) in , ( ) ≤ () ⊇ 8 2 p q p ⊇ q p P q : dom(p) dom(q)& M dom(q) tM = tM & fM fM : P _ _ _ For a -generic GP, define S-names IGP and fGP such that, letting GS be a canonical S-generic name over the extension by GP, n o _ p 2 2 p 2 _ S \ IGP := αM ; p GP & M dom(p)& tM GS " and [ _ p S \ fGP := fM ": p2GP M2dom(p) p 2 _ with tM GS Note that _ is an -name for an uncountable subset of and IGP S n o !1n o _ _ 2 _ 2 _ ! 2 _ 2 _ fGP is an S-name for an isomorphism x T ; ht(x) IGP y U; ht(y) IGP .
Recommended publications
  • Guessing Axioms, Invariance and Suslin Trees
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of East Anglia digital repository Guessing Axioms, Invariance and Suslin Trees A thesis submitted to the School of Mathematics of the University of East Anglia in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Alexander Primavesi November 2011 c This copy of the thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with the author and that use of any information derived there from must be in accordance with current UK Copyright Law. In addition, any quotation or extract must include full attribution. Abstract In this thesis we investigate the properties of a group of axioms known as `Guessing Axioms,' which can be used to extend the standard axiomatisation of set theory, ZFC. In particular, we focus on the axioms called `diamond' and `club,' and ask to what extent properties of the former hold of the latter. A question of I. Juhasz, of whether club implies the existence of a Suslin tree, remains unanswered at the time of writing and motivates a large part of our in- vestigation into diamond and club. We give a positive partial answer to Juhasz's question by defining the principle Superclub and proving that it implies the exis- tence of a Suslin tree, and that it is weaker than diamond and stronger than club (though these implications are not necessarily strict). Conversely, we specify some conditions that a forcing would have to meet if it were to be used to provide a negative answer, or partial answer, to Juhasz's question, and prove several results related to this.
    [Show full text]
  • AUTOMORPHISMS of A^-TREES
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 173, November 1972 AUTOMORPHISMSOF a^-TREES BY THOMASJ. JECH(') ABSTRACT. The number of automorphisms of a normal c<Ji-tree T, denoted by o-(T), is either finite or 2 °<cr(T)¿ 2 . Moreover, if cr(T) is infinite then cr(T)^0 _ cr(T). Moreover, if T has no Suslin subtree then cr(T) is finite or v(T) - 2 " or cr(T) -2 '.It is consistent that there is a Suslin tree with arbitrary pre- cribed °~(T) between 2 u and 2 *, subject to the restriction above; e.g. 2 0 K, 2 1 = ^324 an(^ a(T) = N]7. We prove related results for Kurepa trees and isomorphism types of trees. We use Cohen's method of forcing and Jensen's tech- niques in L. 0. Introduction. A normal co.-tree, being a partially ordered set with K. elements, admits at most 2 automorphisms. Also, the number of isomorphism types of co .-trees is not larger that 2 . In §1, we shall show that the number of automorphisms a normal co .-tree admits is either finite, or at least 2 ; as a matter of fact, it is 2 or 2 , with the exception of Suslin trees. In §2, we investigate Suslin trees. Inspired by Jensen's result [6l, which says that it is consistent to have rigid Suslin trees, and Suslin trees which admit N ., or N~ automorphisms, we prove a general consistency result saying that the number of automorphisms of a Suslin tree can be anything between 2 and 2 it is allowed to be.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Continuous Gradability of the Cut-Point Orders of $\Mathbb R $-Trees
    On the continuous gradability of the cut-point orders of R-trees Sam Adam-Day* *Mathematical Institute, University of Oxford, Andrew Wiles Building, Radcliffe Observatory Quarter, Woodstock Road, Oxford, OX2 6GG, United Kingdom; [email protected] Abstract An R-tree is a certain kind of metric space tree in which every point can be branching. Favre and Jonsson posed the following problem in 2004: can the class of orders underlying R-trees be characterised by the fact that every branch is order-isomorphic to a real interval? In the first part, I answer this question in the negative: there is a ‘branchwise-real tree order’ which is not ‘continuously gradable’. In the second part, I show that a branchwise-real tree order is con- tinuously gradable if and only if every well-stratified subtree is R-gradable. This link with set theory is put to work in the third part answering refinements of the main question, yielding several independence results. For example, when κ ¾ c, there is a branchwise-real tree order which is not continuously gradable, and which satisfies a property corresponding to κ-separability. Conversely, under Martin’s Axiom at κ such a tree does not exist. 1 Introduction An R-tree is to the real numbers what a graph-theoretic tree is to the integers. Formally, let 〈X , d〉 be a metric space. An arc between x, y ∈ X is the image of a topological embedding r : [a, b] → X of a real interval such that r(a) = x and r(b) = y (allowing for the possibility that a = b).
    [Show full text]
  • Parametrized ♢ Principles
    Parametrized ♦ principles Justin Tatch Moore, Michael Hruˇs´ak, Mirna Dˇzamonja ∗† September 2, 2003 Abstract We will present a collection of guessing principles which have a similar relationship to ♦ as cardinal invariants of the continuum have to CH. The purpose is to provide a means for systematically analyzing ♦ and its consequences. It also provides for a unified approach for understanding the status of a number of consequences of CH and ♦ in models such as those of Laver, Miller, and Sacks. 1 Introduction Very early on in the course of modern set theory, Jensen isolated the following combinatorial principle known as ♦: ♦ There is a sequence Aα (α < ω1) such that for all α < ω1, Aα ⊆ α and if X is a subset of ω1 then set {α < ω1 : X ∩ α = Aα} is stationary. ∗The first and third authors received support from EPSRC grant GR/M71121 for the research of this paper. The research of the second author was supported in part by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) – Grant 613.007.039, and in part by the Grant Agency of the Czech Republic – Grant GACRˇ 201/00/1466. †2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03E17, 03E65. Key words: Dia- mond, weak diamond, cardinal invariant, guessing principle. 1 Jensen used this principle to construct a Suslin tree [17] and later many other constructions were carried out using ♦ as an assumption — see [9]. The purpose of this paper is to provide a broad framework for analyzing the consequences of Jensen’s ♦ principle. Our intent is to present an array of ♦-principles which have the same relation to ♦ as the cardinal invariants of the continuum (see e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY 1. the Suslin Problem 1.1. the Suslin Hypothesis. Recall
    SET THEORY MOSHE KAMENSKY Abstract. Notes on set theory, mainly forcing. The first four sections closely follow the lecture notes Williams [8] and the book Kunen [4]. The last section covers topics from various sources, as indicated there. Hopefully, all errors are mine. 1. The Suslin problem 1.1. The Suslin hypothesis. Recall that R is the unique dense, complete and separable order without endpoints (up to isomorphism). It follows from the sepa- rability that any collection of pairwise disjoint open intervals is countable. Definition 1.1.1. A linear order satisfies the countable chain condition (ccc) if any collection of pairwise disjoint open intervals is countable. Hypothesis 1.1.2 (The Suslin hypothesis). (R; <) is the unique complete dense linear order without endpoints that satisfies the countable chain condition. We will not prove the Suslin hypothesis (this is a theorem). Instead, we will reformulate it in various ways. First, we have the following apparent generalisation of the Suslin hypothesis. Theorem 1.1.3. The following are equivalent: (1) The Suslin hypothesis (2) Any ccc linear order is separable Proof. Let (X; <) be a ccc linear order that is not separable. Assume first that it is dense. Then we may assume it has no end points (by dropping them). The completion again has the ccc, so by the Suslin hypothesis is isomorphic to R. Hence we may assume that X ⊆ R, but then X is separable. It remains to produce a dense counterexample from a general one. Define x ∼ y if both (x; y) and (y; x) are separable. This is clearly a convex equivalence relation, so the quotient Y is again a linear order satisfying the ccc.
    [Show full text]
  • $ L (\Mathbb {R}) $ with Determinacy Satisfies the Suslin Hypothesis
    L(R) WITH DETERMINACY SATISFIES THE SUSLIN HYPOTHESIS WILLIAM CHAN AND STEPHEN JACKSON Abstract. The Suslin hypothesis states that there are no nonseparable complete dense linear orderings without endpoints which have the countable chain condition. ZF + AD+ + V = L(P(R)) proves the Suslin hypothesis. In particular, if L(R) |= AD, then L(R) satisfies the Suslin hypothesis, which answers a question of Foreman. 1. Introduction Cantor had shown that R with its usual ordering is the unique complete dense separable linear ordering without endpoints up to isomorphism. A linear ordering has the countable chain condition if there are no uncountable sets of disjoint open intervals. Every separable linear ordering has the countable chain condition. Suslin asked if R is the unique (up to isomorphism) complete dense linear ordering without endpoints that satisfies the countable chain condition. This question has come to be known as the Suslin problem. The study of the Suslin problem under the axiom of choice, AC, has led to a number of developments in set theory such as in constructibility and iterated forcing. A Suslin line is an complete dense linear ordering without endpoints which has the countable chain condition but is not separable. The existence of a Suslin line gives a negative answer to the Suslin problem. The Suslin hypothesis, SH, is the statement that there are no Suslin lines. The Suslin problem can not be resolved under ZFC. However, [3] showed that no linear ordering which ∆1 comes from a 1 prelinear ordering on R can be a counterexample to the Suslin problem. This suggests that no linear ordering which comes from a definable prelinear ordering on R should be a Suslin line.
    [Show full text]
  • Suslin's Problem
    Chapter 20 Suslin’s Problem In this chapter we investigate Suslin’s Problem, which is the question whether every linearly orderedset which is dense, unbounded,complete, and satisfies the countable chain condition is also separable. First it will be shown that the answer to Suslin’s Problem is “no” if and only if there exists a Suslin line, and then it will be proved that the existence of a Suslin line is independent of ZFC. A Topological Characterisation of the Real Line Let (P,<) be a linearly ordered set, in particular, for any two distinct elements a,b P we have either a<b or b<a. We say that ∈ • P is dense if for all a,b P with a<b there is a c P such that a<c<b; ∈ ∈ • P is unbounded if for all a P there are b ,b P such that b <a<b ; ∈ 0 1 ∈ 0 1 • P is complete if every non-empty, bounded subset of P has a supremum and an infimum; • P is separable if there exists a countable set C P such that for all a,b P with a<b there is a c C such that a<c<b; ⊆ ∈ ∈ • P satisfies ccc if every family of pairwise disjoint, non-empty open intervals (a,b)= c P : a<c<b is countable. { ∈ } It is well-known that the real line R together with the natural ordering “<” is—up to isomorphism—the unique linearly ordered set that is dense, unbounded, complete, and separable. Now, Suslin’s Problem is the question whether separable can be replaced with satisfying ccc, that is, whether every linearly ordered set which is dense, unbounded, complete, and satisfies ccc is isomorphic to the real line.
    [Show full text]
  • The Suslin Problem
    Bachelorarbeit Suslin’s Problem Verfasser Joaquín Padilla Montani angestrebter akademischer Grad Bachelor of Science (BSc) Wien, 2018 Studienkennzahl lt. Studienblatt: A 033 621 Fachrichtung: Mathematik Betreuerin: Vera Fischer, Privatdoz., PhD CONTENTS Contents Introduction 1 Motivation . 1 Outline . 2 Prerequisites . 3 1 A Characterization of (R, <R) 3 2 Suslin’s Hypothesis 7 3 Trees 10 4 Jensen’s Diamond 14 5 Gödel’s Constructible Universe 17 6 Martin’s Axiom 23 References 27 INTRODUCTION Introduction Motivation1 The first volume of the Polish journal Fundamenta Mathematicae, published in 1920, ended with a list of open problems. Problem 3 [17], posthumously attributed to the Russian mathematician Mikhail Yakovlevich Suslin (1894-1919), read as follows: Un ensemble ordonné (linéairement) sans sauts ni lacunes et tel que tout en- semble de ses intervalles (contenant plus qu’un élément) n’empiétant pas les uns sur les autres est au plus dénumerable, est-il nécessairement un continue linéaire (ordinaire)? Which roughly translates to: “Is a (linearly) ordered set, with no jumps and no gaps, and such that every collection of its intervals (containing more than one element) not overlapping each other is at most countable, necessarily an (ordinary) linear continuum?”. In modern terms, the absence of jumps refers to the ordering being dense, and the lack of gaps amounts to asking for the ordering to be complete. If we compare this to the usual characterization of (R, <R) where the real numbers are that unique unbounded linearly ordered set which is dense in itself, complete and separable, Suslin’s Problem asks whether the hypothesis of separability can be replaced by the topological countable chain condition (c.c.c.): that every collection of nonempty pairwise disjoint open intervals is at most countable.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory - John R
    MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS – Vol. III - Set Theory - John R. Steel SET THEORY John R. Steel Department of Mathematics, University of California, Berkeley, CA. USA Keywords: Aronszajn tree, Axiom of Choice, Axiom of Infinity, Borel determinacy, cardinal number, closed unbounded set, Cohen’s forcing method, Cohen real, consistency strength, constructible set, Continuum Hypothesis, Covering lemma, countable set, cumulative hierarchy of sets, descriptive set theory, diamond sequence, elementary embedding, fine structure theory, Fodor’s lemma, forcing conditions, generic absoluteness, generic extension, generic filter, inner model, iterated ultrapower, large cardinal hypothesis, Lebesgue measure, Levy hierarchy, Levy collapse, Martin’s Axiom, Martin’s Maximum, measurable cardinal, ordinal number, Powerset Axiom, projective determinacy, random real, relative consistency, Reflection Principle, regular cardinal, set theory, singular cardinal, stationary set, super-compact cardinal, Suslin’s Hypothesis, Suslin tree, transfinite induction, transitive model, transitive set, ultrafilter, wellfounded relation, wellorder, Woodin cardinal, Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory. Contents 1. Introduction 2. Some elementary tools 2.1. Ordinals 2.2. The Wellordering Theorem 2.3. The Cumulative Hierarchy; Proper Classes 2.4. Cardinals 2.5. Cofinality, Inaccessibility, and König’s Theorem 2.6. Club and Stationary Sets 2.7. Trees 2.8. Transitive Models and the Levy Hierarchy 2.9. Large Cardinals and the Consistency-Strength Hierarchy 3. Constructible sets 3.1. Gödel’s Work on L 3.2. Suslin Trees, ◊ and  3.3. Canonical Inner Models Larger Than L 4. ForcingUNESCO – EOLSS 4.1. The Basics of Forcing 4.2. ¬ CH via Adding Cohen Reals 4.3. Easton’s theoremSAMPLE CHAPTERS 4.4. The Singular Cardinals Problem 4.5. A model where the Axiom of Choice fails 4.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Remarks on Suslin's Problem
    Historical Remarks on Suslin’s Problem Akihiro Kanamori1 The work of Stanley Tennenbaum in set theory was centered on the investigation of Suslin’s Hypothesis (SH), to which he made crucial contributions. In 1963 Tennenbaum established the relative consistency of ¬SH, and in 1965, together with Robert Solovay, the relative consistency of SH. In the formative period after Cohen’s 1963 founding of forcing when set theory was transmuting into a modern, sophisticated field of mathematics, this work on SH exhibited the power of forcing for elucidating a classical problem of mathematics and stimulated the development of new methods and areas of investigation. §1 discusses the historical underpinnings of SH. §2 then describes Tennenbaum’s consis- tency result for ¬SH and related subsequent work. §3 then turns to Tennenbaum’s work with Solovay on SH and the succeeding work on iterated forcing and Martin’s Axiom. To cast an amusing sidelight on the life and the times, I relate the following reminiscence of Gerald Sacks from this period, no doubt apocryphal: Tennenbaum let it be known that he had come into a great deal of money, $30,000,000 it was said, and started to borrow money against it. Gerald convinced himself that Tennenbaum seriously believed this, but nonetheless asked Simon Kochen about it. Kochen replied, “Well, with Stan he might be one per-cent right. But then, that’s still $300,000.” §1. Suslin’s Problem In 1920, at the end of the first volume of Fundamenta Mathematicae there appeared a list of problems with one attributed to Mikhail Suslin [1920], a problem that would come to be known as Suslin’s Problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1805.08164V2 [Math.LO]
    A FORCING AXIOM FOR A NON-SPECIAL ARONSZAJN TREE JOHN KRUEGER ∗ Abstract. Suppose that T is an ω1-Aronszajn tree with no stationary an- tichain. We introduce a forcing axiom PFA(T ∗) for proper forcings which preserve these properties of T ∗. We prove that PFA(T ∗) implies many of the strong consequences of PFA, such as the failure of very weak club guessing, that all of the cardinal characteristics of the continuum are greater than ω1, and the P -ideal dichotomy. On the other hand, PFA(T ∗) implies some of the consequences of diamond principles, such as the existence of Knaster forcings which are not stationarily Knaster. In one of the earliest applications of the method of forcing in set theory, Solovay and Tennenbaum [11] proved the consistency of Suslin’s hypothesis, which is the statement that there does not exist an ω1-Suslin tree. Baumgartner, Malitz, and MA Reinhardt [2] improved this by showing that ω1 implies that every ω1-Aronszajn tree is special, a statement which implies Suslin’s hypothesis. Shelah [10, Chapter IX] proved that Suslin’s hypothesis does not imply that all ω1-Aronszajn trees are special by constructing a model in which there are no ω1-Suslin trees but there exists a non-special Aronszajn tree. In Shelah’s model, the non-special Aronszajn tree satisfies that there are stationarily many levels on which the tree is special, and stationary many levels on which there is no stationary antichain (recall that an antichain of a tree is stationary if the set of heights of its nodes forms a stationary set).
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/9812115V1
    2 A∆2 Well-Order of the Reals And Incompactness of L(QMM ) Uri Abraham Department of mathematics and computer science Ben-Gurion University, Be’er Sheva, ISRAEL; Saharon Shelah ∗ Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, ISRAEL. 8-16-91 Abstract ℵ A forcing poset of size 22 1 which adds no new reals is described 2 and shown to provide a ∆2 definable well-order of the reals (in fact, any given relation of the reals may be so encoded in some generic extension). The encoding of this well-order is obtained by playing with products of Aronszajn trees: Some products are special while other are Suslin trees. The paper also deals with the Magidor-Malitz logic: it is consistent that this logic is highly non compact. arXiv:math/9812115v1 [math.LO] 18 Dec 1998 Preface This paper deals with three issues: the question of definable well-orders of the reals, the compactness of the Magidor-Malitz logic and the forcing techniques for specializing Aronszajn trees without addition of new reals. ∗Supported by a grant from the Israeli Academy of Sciences. Pub. 403 1 In the hope of attracting a wider readership, we have tried to make this paper as self contained as possible; in some cases we have reproved known results, or given informal descriptions to remind the reader of what he or she probably knows. We could not do so for the theorem that the iteration of DD-complete proper forcing adds no reals, and the reader may wish to consult chapter V of Shelah [1982], or the new edition [1992].
    [Show full text]