Dead Woman Walking: Jocasta in the Thebaid

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dead Woman Walking: Jocasta in the Thebaid CHAPTER 17 Dead Woman Walking: Jocasta in the Thebaid Jessica S. Dietrich Jocasta, wife of Laius, wife and mother of Oedipus, mother of Eteocles and Polynices as well as Antigone and Ismene, and finally, sister of Creon, perhaps best embodies the confusion associated with the house of Oedipus. In his pre- sentation of the two major episodes involving Jocasta in the Thebaid—her attempts to persuade her sons against fighting each other and her suicide— Statius engages with literary models, including epic and tragedy as well as historical accounts, and carefully combines his sources, developing a complex series of allusions.1 It is not surprising that Statius evokes many models in his portrayal of Jocasta in the Thebaid, but through such allusions, Statius invites comparisons that highlight important differences, distinguishing his Jocasta as a uniquely Flavian creation. Statius consistently plays with the contradictory traditions surrounding Jocasta’s death in particular, thus creating a figure who can be read as among the living but also one of the dead. In this way, Jocasta’s role may be similar to that of her first husband Laius, who is twice brought back from the dead to influence the world of the living. Ecce Jocasta: Jocasta in Thebaid 7 In Thebaid 7, Jocasta bursts onto the scene: ecce truces oculos sordentibus obsita canis / exangues Iocasta genas et bracchia planctu (“Look! Jocasta, her savage eyes and bloodless cheeks covered by her filthy gray hair and her arms cov- ered with beating,” Theb. 7.474–5). Jocasta’s intrusion into the text in Thebaid 7 may have been a surprise to Statius’ readers who would have good reason to assume that Jocasta had died after Oedipus blinded himself, as she does in Sophocles’ and Seneca’s Oedipus. Indeed, in Thebaid 1, Oedipus remarks that he has left his eyes on his mother (miseraque oculos in matre reliqui, 1.72), which is a clear reference to Sophocles’ Oedipus, thus implying that Jocasta is already dead.2 Smolenaars rightly tries to make sense of this apparent contradiction of a reference to Jocasta’s death in book 1 and her appearance, apparently alive, 1 Smolenaars (2008) 220–3 investigates the wider tradition of Jocasta’s role in Theban legend. 2 Smolenaars (2008) 219. © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi ��.��63/9789004�84708_0�8 308 Dietrich in book 7. But while Smolenaars suggests that it is not necessary to read the reference in book 1 as being to Jocasta’s corpse,3 I would argue that the ambigu- ity of Jocasta’s status as living or dead is maintained and exploited by Statius in his introduction of her into his story,4 as well as in her other appearances in the epic. Statius’ emphasis on Jocasta’s physical appearance, in particular her filthy hair and bruised arms, may evoke depictions of female lamentation, an asso- ciation Statius returns to in Jocasta’s embassy to Polynices,5 but there is also a suggestion of another kind of imagery—that of a fury. In his commentary on Thebaid 7, Smolenaars argues that the description of Jocasta’s appearance is primarily derived from Vergil’s Allecto in Aeneid 7, who appears to Turnus as the aged Calybe.6 This connection to Allecto is strengthened by the simile fol- lowing Jocasta’s appearance in which Statius explicitly compares Jocasta to a fury: Eumenidum uelut antiquissima (“like the oldest of the Eumenides,” Theb. 7.477). It is difficult, however, to view Jocasta as acting as a fury in this passage as she strives to stop rather than stir up the war between her sons.7 Statius per- haps contrasts Jocasta’s fury-like appearance at the beginning of the passage with the action of the real Fury who instigates the war that Jocasta has failed to avert at the conclusion of her intervention: arma iterum furiaeque placent; fera tempus Erinys / arripit (“arms and battle lust are pleasing again; the savage Fury jumps at the opportunity,” 7.562–3). Therefore, Jocasta is characterized by fury imagery, but her role within the episode is seemingly quite different from that of the actual Furies.8 These two aspects of Statius’ description of Jocasta, her physical appearance and the use of fury imagery, may allow the poet to exploit otherworldly figures similar to the furies, yet not quite the same—figures such as dreams, visions and ghosts. Thus, although Jocasta is introduced on a peace-keeping mission, the simile comparing her to a fury has sinister implications that are evoked by a further 3 Smolenaars (2008) 235. 4 That figures in the Thebaid act like the living dead is argued by Hardie (1993) 44–6, who views Eteocles and Polynices as furies who act after death, and Vessey (1973) 280, who refers to Oedipus’ living death. 5 Cf. below, p. 312 n. 25 for lamentation in the characterization of Jocasta in Thebaid 7 as well as in her embassy to Eteocles in book 11. 6 Smolenaars (1994) 220–2; Ganiban (2007) 112. 7 For readings of Jocasta’s role in the violent action of the poem, see Ganiban (2007) 112; Keith (2000) 97; and especially Augoustakis (2010b) 62–4 on the tension between the representa- tion of a fury and an emphasis on her maternal role. 8 Hershkowitz (1998) 280 suggests that Jocasta’s passivity and resignation make her an unwit- ting agent of the Furies, but it may also be evidence of her status as not quite alive..
Recommended publications
  • Female Familial Relationships in Valerius' Argonautica and Statius
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2021 Female Familial Relationships in Valerius’ Argonautica and Statius’ Thebaid Sophia Warnement Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Warnement, Sophia, "Female Familial Relationships in Valerius’ Argonautica and Statius’ Thebaid" (2021). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 1619. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/1619 This Honors Thesis -- Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Female Familial Relationships in Valerius’ Argonautica and Statius’ Thebaid A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Department of Classical Studies from The College of William and Mary by Sophia Irene Warnement Accepted for ______Honors___________________________ (Honors, Highest Honors) __Vassiliki Panoussi___________________ Vassiliki Panoussi, Director __Molly Swetnam-Burland____________ Molly Swetnam-Burland __Jennifer Gülly___ ____________________ Jennifer Gülly Williamsburg, VA May 07, 2021 Table of Contents ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ..........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Optimistic Rationalist in Euripides: Theseus, Jocasta, Teiresias
    UC Berkeley Classical Papers Title The Optimistic Rationalist in Euripides: Theseus, Jocasta, Teiresias Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/0mn5q9c5 Author Mastronarde, Donald J. Publication Date 1986 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Postprint from Greek Tragedy and its Legacy: Essays presented to D. J. Conacher, ed. by Martin Cropp, Elaine Fantham, S. E. Scully (Calgary 1986) 201-211 [201]THE OPTIMISTIC RATIONALIST IN EURIPIDES: THESEUS, JOCASTA, TEIRESIAS DONALD J. MASTRONARDE University of California, Berkeley Near the end of Act 3 of Corneille’s Oedipe of 1659, Thésée delivers a ringing denunciation of fatalism:1 Quoi? la nécessité des vertus et des vices D’un astre impérieux doit suivre les caprices, Et Delphes, malgré nous, conduit nos actions Au plus bizarre effet de ses prédictions? L’âme est donc toute esclave: une loi souveraine Vers le bien ou le mal incessamment l’entraîne, Et nous ne recevons ni crainte ni désir De cette liberté qui n’a rien à choisir, Attachés sans relâche à cet ordre sublime, Vertueux sans mérite, et vicieux sans crime. Qu’on massacre les rois, qu’on brise les autels, C’est la faute des Dieux, et non pas des mortels. De toute la vertu sur la terre épandue, Tout le prix à ces dieux, toute la gloire est due; Ils agissent en nous quand nous pensons agir; Alors qu’on délibère on ne fait qu’obéir; Et notre volonté n’aime, hait, cherche, évite, Que suivant que d’en haut leur bras la précipite. D’un tel aveuglement daignez me dispenser.
    [Show full text]
  • Tisiphone As an Internal Poet in Statius' Thebaid in This Paper, I Will
    Tisiphone as an Internal Poet in Statius’ Thebaid In this paper, I will analyze Statius’ portrayal of Tisiphone, one of the three Furies, in the Thebaid, with particular emphasis given to her role as an internal poet in Books 1 and 11. Even at the beginning of the poem, Statius struggles to assert his authorial control over the narrative of his epic. After invoking Pierian fire and Clio for a heroic or worthy beginning to the Thebaid, Statius abruptly begins with Oedipus, wrathful in his hatred of his two traitorious sons. Oedipus, who exists in a liminal and corrupted state, operates outside of the heroism of the proem, assumes control of the narrative, and calls upon a divine enactor of his vengeance. After hearing the prayer of Oedipus, Tisiphone summons herself to Earth and brings about the deaths of many Theban and Argive heroes. Her influence in the epic is unparalleled by any other character in the Thebaid, as she manipulates Polynices and Eteocles to bring about their fatal fratricidal duel. Statius’ representation of Tisiphone has been widely debated in the field of Statian scholarship, with scholars such as Philip Hardie (1993) and Alison Keith (2016) analyzing the intertextual connections between Statius’ Tisiphone and the Tisiphone of Vergil’s Aeneid and Ovid’s Metamorphoses. Dennis Feeney, in his seminal work The Gods in Epic: The Poets and Critics of the Classical Tradition, likewise finds many connections between Statius’ Tisiphone and Ovid’s Tisiphone. While I generally agree with the sentiments of Feeney, Hardie, and Keith, I believe that their works have not entirely addressed Tisiphone’s role in Statius’ Thebaid.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Phoenician Women — Genre, Structure, Thematic Unity
    UDC 821.124 Philologia Classica. 2021. Vol. 16. Fasc. 1 Seneca’s Phoenician Women — Genre, Structure, Thematic Unity Tomasz Sapota University of Silesia in Katowice, Faculty of Humanities, pl. Sejmu Śląskiego 1, 40-032 Katowice, Poland; [email protected] Iwona Słomak University of Silesia in Katowice, Faculty of Humanities, pl. Sejmu Śląskiego 1, 40-032 Katowice, Poland; [email protected] For citation: Sapota T., Słomak I. Seneca’s Phoenician Women — Genre, Structure, Thematic Unity. Philologia Classica 2021, 16 (1), 77–89. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu20.2021.107 This article revises current perspectives on the generic status, composition, and subject mat- ter of Phoenician Women by Seneca. It adopts a new approach, focusing on selected elements of text organisation. In particular, emphasis is given to the construction of characters and the analogies and contrasts between them which were already of interest to ancient poetics and rhetoric. Moreover, the article refers to observations, accurate but isolated and largely ignored, made by scholars who recognised Seneca’s originality and suggested that his plays might have been inspired by the declamatory tradition and should be read in the context of evolving post- classical literature. By adopting this perspective, it becomes possible to bring together a large number of partial conclusions that are related to Phoenician Women as well as other plays by Seneca. What is more important, the work brings to light the purposeful composition of the drama and its thematic unity, allowing us to return to the MS versions that until now have been replaced by conjectures, which often distort the meaning of the text.
    [Show full text]
  • Jocasta and the Sin of Thebes Bernadette Waterman Ward
    Jocasta and the Sin of Thebes Bernadette Waterman Ward ABSTRACT: The tragic victim of Oedipus the King is not Oedipus, who after his sufferings shall be raised to divinity; it is his mother Jocasta. She attempted the death by her torture of her own son. When she discovers that he has survived and is her husband, she seeks even to continue her mother-son incest so as to conceal her misdeeds. Cowardly silence among the citizens of doomed Thebes seals their collusion in evil. An examina- tion of the culture of the fatal city can bring the play more vitally into the world that our students actually inhabit, and serve as a warning against the moral collapse that encourages the killing of children. EDIPUS THE KING, the most famous drama of Sophocles, invites many approaches in the classroom. One can delve into such Oquestions as the proper limits of human knowledge, the relation of fate and freewill, responsibility for inadvertent crime, the proper understanding of piety and the power of the gods, and the relation of kingship and self-sacrifice. One can address hubris – pride, overreaching – and hamartia – the mistake or tragic flaw. One can trace dramatic irony in the images of vision and deliberate blindness, or perhaps, with Freud leering in the background, contemplate sexual taboos. Many scholars investigate the guilt of Oedipus, but rarely does the focus shift from the polluted scapegoat to the deep corruption in the scapegoating city of Thebes. The Thebans cast out Oedipus as impure, but in fact they cause their own destruction. By considering the fate of the city, rather than that of Oedipus, our students can make this play vital in the world that we actually inhabit.
    [Show full text]
  • Antigone's Line
    Bulletin de la Société Américaine de Philosophie de Langue Française Volume 14, Number 2, Fall 2005 Antigone’s Line Mary Beth Mader “Leader: What is your lineage, stranger? Tell us—who was your father? Oedipus: God help me! Dear girl, what must I suffer now? Antigone: Say it. You’re driven right to the edge.”1 Sophocles’ Antigone has solicited many superlatives. Hölderlin considered the play to be the most difficult, the most enigmatic and the most essentially Greek of plays. This paper treats a matter of enigma in the play, one that is crucial to understanding the central stakes of the drama. Its main purpose is to propose a novel account of this enigma and briefly to contrast this account with two other readings of the play. One passage in particular has prompted the view that the play is extremely enigmatic; it is a passage that has been read with astonishment by many commentators and taken to demand explanation. This is Antigone’s defense speech at lines 905-914. Here, she famously provides what appear to her to be reasons for her burying her brother Polynices against the explicit command of her king and uncle, Creon. Her claim is that she would not have deliberately violated Creon’s command, would not have ANTIGONE’S LINE intentionally broken his law or edict, had this edict barred her from burying a child or a husband of hers. She states that if her husband or child had died “there might have been another.” But since both her mother and father are dead, she reasons, “no brother could ever spring to light again.”2 Reasoning of this sort has a precedent in a tale found in Herodotus’ Histories, and Aristotle cites it in Rhetoric as an example of giving an explanation for something that one’s auditors may at first find incredible.3 To Aristotle, then, Antigone’s defense speech appears to have been “rhetorically satisfactory,” as Bernard Knox says.4 However, such a reception is rare among commentators.5 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham E-Theses
    Durham E-Theses The legend of Oedipus in fth century tragedy at Athens Bailey, S. K. How to cite: Bailey, S. K. (1955) The legend of Oedipus in fth century tragedy at Athens, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/9722/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk r 1 THE LEGEND OF OEDIPUS IN FIFTH CENTURY TRAGEDY AT ATHENS A THESIS SUJ3W:TTED BY S.K. BAILEY FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF LETTERS The aims of the thesis are (a) to mark what has been altered or added to the legend of Oedipus by the three great dramatists of the fifth century, and (b) to show that these alterations and additions were made with a· specific end in view. To further these aims it has been necessary to broaden somewhat the scope of the thesis so as to include in it a gathering together of the pre-Aeechylean versions of the story; in the case of Aeschylus a reconstruction of the two lost plays of the trilogy, and in the case of each poet a personal interpretation of the plays connected with the Oedipus legend.
    [Show full text]
  • The Shield As Pedagogical Tool in Aeschylus' Seven Against Thebes
    АНТИЧНОЕ ВОСПИТАНИЕ ВОИНА ЧЕРЕЗ ПРИЗМУ АРХЕОЛОГИИ, ФИЛОЛОГИИ И ИСТОРИИ ПЕДАГОГИКИ THE SHIELD AS PEDAGOGICAL TOOL IN AESCHYLUS’ SEVEN AGAINST THEBES* Victoria K. PICHUGINA The article analyzes the descriptions of warriors in Aeschylus’s tragedy Seven against Thebes that are given in the “shield scene” and determines the pedagogical dimension of this tragedy. Aeschylus pays special attention to the decoration of the shields of the com- manders who attacked Thebes, relying on two different ways of dec- orating the shields that Homer describes in The Iliad. According to George Henry Chase’s terminology, in Homer, Achilles’ shield can be called “a decorative” shield, and Agamemnon’s shield is referred to as “a terrible” shield. Aeschylus turns the description of the shield decoration of the commanders attacking Thebes into a core element of the plot in Seven against Thebes, maximizing the connection be- tween the image on the shield and the shield-bearer. He created an elaborate system of “terrible” and “decorative” shields (Aesch. Sept. 375-676), as well as of the shields that cannot be categorized as “ter- rible” and “decorative” (Aesch. Sept. 19; 43; 91; 100; 160). The analysis of this system made it possible to put forward and prove three hypothetical assumptions: 1) In Aeschylus, Eteocles demands from the Thebans to win or die, focusing on the fact that the city cre- ated a special educational space for them and raised them as shield- bearers. His patriotic speeches and, later, his judgments expressed in the “shield scene” demonstrate a desire to justify and then test the educational concept “ἢ τὰν ἢ ἐπὶ τᾶς” (“either with it, or upon it”) (Plut.
    [Show full text]
  • Thebaid 2: Oedipus Descendants of Cadmus
    Thebaid 2: Oedipus Descendants of Cadmus Cadmus = Harmonia Aristaeus = Autonoe Ino Semele Agave = Echion Pentheus Actaeon Polydorus (?) Autonoe = Aristaeus Actaeon Polydorus (?) • Aristaeus • Son of Apollo and Cyrene • Actaeon • While hunting he saw Artemis bathing • Artemis set his own hounds on him • Polydorus • Either brother or son of Autonoe • King of Cadmeia after Pentheus • Jean-Baptiste-Camile Corot ca. 1850 Giuseppe Cesari, ca. 1600 House of Cadmus Hyrieus Cadmus = Harmonia Dirce = Lycus Nycteus Autonoe = Aristaeus Zeus = Antiope Nycteis = Polydorus Zethus Amphion Labdacus Laius Tragedy of Antiope • Polydorus: • king of Thebes after Pentheus • m. Nycteis, sister of Antiope • Polydorus died before Labdacus was of age. • Labdacus • Child king after Polydorus • Regency of Nycteus, Lycus Thebes • Laius • Child king as well… second regency of Lycus • Zethus and Amphion • Sons of Antiope by Zeus • Jealousy of Dirce • Antiope imprisoned • Zethus and Amphion raised by shepherds Zethus and Amphion • Returned to Thebes: • Killed Lycus • Tied Dirce to a wild bull • Fortified the city • Renamed it Thebes • Zethus and his family died of illness Death of Dirce • The Farnese Bull • 2nd cent. BC • Asinius Pollio, owner • 1546: • Baths of Caracalla • Cardinal Farnese • Pope Paul III Farnese Bull Amphion • Taught the lyre by Hermes • First to establish an altar to Hermes • Married Niobe, daughter of Tantalus • They had six sons and six daughters • Boasted she was better than Leto • Apollo and Artemis slew every child • Amphion died of a broken heart Niobe Jacques Louis David, 1775 Cadmus = Harmonia Aristeus =Autonoe Ino Semele Agave = Echion Nycteis = Polydorus Pentheus Labdacus Menoecius Laius = Iocaste Creon Oedipus Laius • Laius and Iocaste • Childless, asked Delphi for advice: • “Lord of Thebes famous for horses, do not sow a furrow of children against the will of the gods; for if you beget a son, that child will kill you, [20] and all your house shall wade through blood.” (Euripides Phoenissae) • Accidentally, they had a son anyway.
    [Show full text]
  • Elegy with Epic Consequences: Elegiac Themes in Statius' Thebaid
    Elegy with Epic Consequences: Elegiac Themes in Statius’ Thebaid A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Cincinnati in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy In the Department of Classics of the College of Arts and Sciences by Carina Moss B.A. Bucknell University April 2020 Committee Chairs: Lauren D. Ginsberg, Ph.D., Kathryn J. Gutzwiller, Ph.D. Abstract This dissertation examines the role of elegy in the Thebaid by Statius, from allusion at the level of words or phrases to broad thematic resonance. It argues that Statius attributes elegiac language and themes to characters throughout the epic, especially women. Statius thus activates certain women in the epic as disruptors, emphasizing the ideological conflict between the genres of Latin love elegy and epic poetry. While previous scholarship has emphasized the importance of Statius’ epic predecessors, or the prominence of tragic allusion in the plot, my dissertation centers the role of elegy in this epic. First, I argue that Statius relies on allusion to the genre of elegy to signal the true divine agent of the civil war at Thebes: Vulcan. Vulcan’s erotic jealousy over Venus’ affair with Mars leads him to create the Necklace of Harmonia. Imbued with elegiac resonance, the necklace comes to Argia with corrupted elegiac imagery. Statius characterizes Argia within the dynamic of the elegiac relicta puella and uses this framework to explain Argia’s gift of the necklace to Eriphyle and her advocacy for Argos’ involvement in the war. By observing the full weight of the elegiac imagery in these scenes, I show that Argia mistakenly causes the death of Polynices and the devastation at Thebes as the result of Vulcan’s elegiac curse.
    [Show full text]
  • The Story of Oedipus: Prequel to Antigone
    The Story of Oedipus: Prequel to Antigone • LAIUS is left an orphaned minor by his father Labdacus • AMPHION AND ZETHUS rule Thebes (Build the Cadmeia) and exile Laius • Laius goes to live in Elis (PISA) with King Pelops (son of Tantalus son of Zeus) • Laius becomes very good friends with young Chrysippus, youngest child of King Pelops • Laius and Chrysippus run away together (or Laius rapes Chrysippus). Pelops curses Laius. • Laius returns to Thebes and becomes King • Laius marries his cousin Jocasta, but they are childless • Laius goes to Delphi and intends to ask Apollo's advice; Apollo announces that Laius will have a child who will kill him • Laius and Jocasta have a baby son (Oedipus) whom they plan to kill. The royal shepherd is ordered to dispose of the child on Mt. Cithaeron. Instead he gives Oedipus to the royal Corinthian shepherd. • The Royal Corinthian Shepherd takes the child back to the childless king and queen of Corinth (Polybus and Merope), who adopt him. • At about the age of 18, at a dinner party, one of Oedipus' friends makes a rude remark about his not being a real Corinthian but only adopted. Oedipus is shocked and shamed, and goes off to Delphi to ask Apollo about the truth. • Apollo tells Oedipus he is doomed to kill his father and sleep with his mother. • Oedipus unknowingly kills his father Laius (within hours, at The Three Ways) • Oedipus kills the SPHINX on the way from the Three Ways to Thebes • Oedipus is received at Thebes as a national hero, and invited to marry the recently widowed queen Jocasta.
    [Show full text]
  • Polis As Player in Aeschylus' Seven Against Thebes This Paper Will
    Polis as Player in Aeschylus’ Seven Against Thebes This paper will focus on the city in Aeschylus’ Seven Against Thebes and argue that the city itself plays a prominent role not just in locating the action, but also in participating in it as a fundamental part of the curse on the house of Laius. Previous scholarship has focused on the absence of Polynices as a speaking character in Aeschylus’ Seven Against Thebes: some have argued that his absence indicates Aeschylus’ sole focus on Eteocles (Kitto 1966, 47), even denying any rightful claim to dike on Polynices’ part (cf. Gagarin 1976, 122 n. 11). The implication of this stance is that Eteocles’ death is predicated solely on Oedipus’ curse on his sons (785-787) and is not caused by any wrongful action on his part. Contrary to this view, I will argue that Eteocles’ death is caused by his mistreatment of the city, and I will suggest that this type of mistreatment is the driving force behind the curse on the family. Aeschylus’ emphasis on intergenerational misfortune is well-known as the basis on which his trilogies are built, and scholarly attention has revolved around human action and interaction as the manifestations of intergenerational conflict. I will argue that, in addition to the human players, the city of Thebes must also be understood as an active participant in and focal point of this intergenerational narrative. This paper will explore the various personifications of the city, first as mother and caretaker in Eteocles’ opening speech (10-15), and later more general ones that speak of the city as one entity (793, 803, 900) comprising its physical structures (795, 901).
    [Show full text]