(2015). Qualia Explained Away - a Commentary on Daniel C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

(2015). Qualia Explained Away - a Commentary on Daniel C Qualia explained away A Commentary on Daniel C. Dennett David H. Baßler In his paper “Why and how does consciousness seem the way it seems?” Daniel Commentator Dennett argues that philosophers and scientists should a"andon #ed Bloc$%s dis& tinction "etween access consciousness and phenomenal consciousness. 'irst he David H. Baßler lays out why the assumption o( phenomenal consciousness as a second medium is davidh"assler1!mail.com not a reasona"le idea. In a second step he shows why "ein!s li$e us must "e con& vinced that there are )ualia that is, why we have the stron! temptation to "elieve 2ohannes 3uten"erg&4niversit5t in their e*istence. +his commentary is e*clusively concerned with this second part ,ain6 3ermany o( the target paper. In particular I o((er a more detailed picture !uided "y (ive )uestions that are not addressed "y Dennett. ,y proposal however still resides +arget Author within the (ramework o( Dennett%s philosophy in !eneral. In particular I use the notion o( intentional systems o( di((erent orders to (ill in some details. I tell the Daniel C. Dennett counterfactual story o( some (irst-order intentional systems evolvin! to "ecome daniel.dennett1tu(ts.edu "elievers in )ualia as "uildin! "loc$s o( their world. +u(ts 4niversity ,ed(ord ,A, 4.7.A. Keywords Dispositions - Intentional systems - .redictive processin! - /ualia - 0om"ic hunch 8ditors +homas ,et6in!er met6in!er 1uni&main6.de 2ohannes 3uten"erg&4niversit5t ,ain6 3ermany 2enni(er ,. Windt 9enni(er.windt1monash.edu ,onash 4niversity ,el"ourne Australia 1 Introduction The first of Rapoport’s Rules1 for composing a views' especially his argument against the e/ist$ critical commentary states that one should ence of 4ualia (constituting the first part of the present the target view in the most charitable target paper)' the diagnosis that there is the way possible (Dennett 2013a ! Although # gen$ zombic hunch'2 along with his strategy for e/$ erally agree with many of Daniel Dennett’s plaining why it e/ists' the connection between 1 Dennett named these rules after social psychologist and game theor$ 4ualia and predicted dispositions' was hard to ist Anatol Rapaport! They are not to be confused with another %Ra$ grasp! Dennett presents the idea that when we poport’s Rule&' named after (duardo )! Rapaport (cf! *tevens 1989 ! Here is the full list of Dennett’s Rapaport’s Rules- tal1 about 4ualia, what we really refer to are 1. %.ou should attempt to re$e/press your target’s position so our dispositions in earlier works (e!g.' Dennett clearly' vividly' and fairly that your target says' 0Than1s' # wish #’d 1991 ! But the connection to predictive pro$ thought of putting it that way!’& 2. %.ou should list any points of agreement (especially if they are not matters of general or widespread agreement !& 2 " philosophical 6ombie has nothing to do with any other sort of 3. %.ou should mention anything you have learned from your target!& 6ombie! #t behaves in every way li1e a normal person! The only dif$ 2! %3nly then are you permitted to say so much as a word of rebut$ ference is' that it lac1s phenomenal e/periences (though ex hypothesi tal or criticism!& it believes that is has phenomenal e/periences ! The 6ombic hunch is (Dennett 2013a' p! 33) the intuition that a philosophical 6ombie would be different from us! Baßler D. H. :;<=>?. /ualia e*plained away & A Commentary on Daniel C. Dennett. In +. ,et6in!er @ 2. ,. Windt :8ds?. Open MIND: =<:C?. 'ran$(urt am ,ainA ,I#D 3roup. doiA 10.=>><;BCDEFC>E>D<>G; 1 | == www.open&mind.net cessing is new (see also Dennett 2013b ! There # want to draw attention to )ume’s Of still seem to be some stepping stones missing, Miracles ()ume 1++B' C ' where he states which # hope to fill in with my reconstruction! that the li1elihood of a testimony about mir$ My goal is to provide a complete story that acles being wrong is always greater than the stic1s as close to Dennett’s argument as pos$ li1elihood of the miracle itself! This serves as sible! This paper is not supposed to be a %re$ a nice analogy for the case at hand- we might buttal& or “criticism”' but an “attempt to re$e/$ thin1 of our own mind as a good %witness&' press [Dennett9’s position& (see footnote 1 ! but we already 1now too much about its The structure of this commentary is as shortcomings! *o we should be suspicious follows- in the first section # shall give a short when it cries out for a revolution in science or outline of Dennett’s e/planation of why we metaphysics' because this cry rests on the be$ have the 6ombic hunch! *ince this involves the lief that something is missing' when no data predictive processing framewor1' # shall give a but this very belief itself ma1es the demand very short introduction to this first! :ollowing necessary! #nstead we should e/amine what this' # present a short list of five 4uestions else could have led our minds to form this that have not' in my opinion' yet been suffi$ conviction! ciently addressed! #n the second section # present an interpretation' or perhaps an e/$ 2 Dennett’s proposal tension' of Dennett’s answers to these 4ues$ tions' by relying on the concept of an inten$ #n %<hy and how does consciousness seem the tional system and using a strategy involving way it seems=& Dennett gives an argument for telling the counterfactual story of the evolu$ why philosophers and scientists should aban$ tion of some agents who end up believing in don Ded 5loc1’s distinction between access 4ualia (although ex hypothesi there are none ! consciousness and phenomenal consciousness' #n the third section # shall analy6e which fea$ 6ombies' and 4ualia altogether! The argument tures 4ualia should have' according to the be$ is twofold- first Dennett lays down his argu$ liefs of these agents' and show that there is at ment for why the assumption of phenomenal least a significant overlap with features many consciousness as a second medium whose states consider 4ualia to have! are conscious e/periences or 4ualia is %scien$ # want to give a short ;ustification for tifically insupportable and deeply misleading& the unorthodo/ way of accounting for beliefs (Dennett this collection' section 2 ! #t is insup$ about x instead of for x’s e/istence itself! This portable because there is simply no need to is a general strategy found in other areas of posit such entities to e/plain any of our beha$ Dennett’s wor1! :or e/ample' he has as1ed' vior' so for reasons of parsimony they should %<hy should we thin1 there is intentionality not be a part of scientific theories (see also although there is none=& (Dennett 1+>1 ' Dennett 1++1' p! 132 ! The assumption is %<hy should we believe there is a god al$ deeply misleading because it ma1es us loo1 for though there is none=& (Dennett 200? ' and the wrong things' namely' the ob;ects our ;udg$ %<hy should we thin1 there is a problem with ments are about' rather than the causes of determinism and free will although there is these ;udgments' which are nothing li1e these none=& (Dennett 1+,2' 2002 ! Dennett’s philo$ ob;ects! sophy can in parts be seen as a therapeutic #n a second step Dennett shows why approach to %philosopher’s syndrome&@%mis$ creatures li1e us must be convinced that there ta1ing failures of imagination for insights into are 4ualia, that is' why we have such a strong necessity& (e!g!' Dennett 1++1' p! 201A Dennett temptation to believe in their e/istence' even 1++,a' p! 3?? @by ma1ing it easier to see why though there are no good reasons for this (Den$ we are convinced of the e/istence of some$ nett this collection' section 2 and 3; other places thing' even when there are good reasons to where Dennett ac1nowledges this conviction' believe that it doesn’t e/ist! the 6ombic hunch' are Dennett 1999A Dennett Baßler D. H. :;<=>?. /ualia e*plained away & A Commentary on Daniel C. Dennett. In +. ,et6in!er @ 2. ,. Windt :8ds?. Open MIND: =<:C?. 'ran$(urt am ,ainA ,I#D 3roup. doiA 10.=>><;BCDEFC>E>D<>G; 2 | == www.open&mind.net 2005' Ch! 1; Dennett 2013a' p! 283 ! The follow$ that this leads to an action that changes the ing sections are e/clusively concerned with this input in such a way that the prediction is vin$ part of the target paper! dicated (active inference' see e!g!' :riston et After completing the second step' Dennett al! 2011 ! )owever' although this aspect of GG e/plains why we ascribe 4ualia their character$ @that it provides one formally$unified ap$ istic properties—simplicity and ineffability proach to perception and action@is a strength (Dennett this collection' section 2 F B ! Al$ of the framewor1' it is not important here' though # also say something about this point given the conte/t of this commentary! These (see section 2 ' *ection ? is an intuition pump changes are supposed to follow 5ayes’ The$ (cf! e!g!' Dennett 2013a that will help the orem' which is why one might spea1 of reader to apply Dennett’s alternative view to 5ayesian prediction (cf! e!g!' )ohwy 2013 ! the e/perience of colors! The higher the layer in the hierarchy the Before # present a short outline of Den$ more abstract the contents and the longer the nett’s second step' # want to briefly describe the time-scales or the predictive hori6on! 3ne e/$ predictive processing framework! This is neces$ ample of a very abstract content is %only one sary since both Dennett’s argument as well as ob;ect can e/ist in the same place at the same my reconstruction make use of this framework! # time& (Hohwy et al! 2008' p! 691, 4uoted after shall not go into details of hierarchical predict$ Elark 2013' p! 5 ! ive processing (GG accounts here' since at least 3ne point to 1eep in mind is that' accord$ three papers in this collection (Elark' Hohwy' ing to Hohwy (2014 ' this framework implies a and *eth ' as well as the associated commentar$ clear-cut distinction between the mind and the ies (Madary' Harkness' and <iese ' are con$ world! That is' there is an evidentiary boundary cerned with this topic and also offer ample ref$ between %where the prediction error minimi6a$ erences for introductory as well as further read$ tion occurs& and %hidden causes 8of the sensory ing.
Recommended publications
  • Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 12 Issue 4 Article 1 10-1-1995 Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia? David Merrihew Lewis Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Lewis, David Merrihew (1995) "Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 12 : Iss. 4 , Article 1. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol12/iss4/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. SHOULD A MATERIALIST BELIEVE IN QUALIA? David Lewis Should a materialist believe in qualia? Yes and no. 'Qualia' is a name for the occupants of a certain functional role that is spelled out in our tacitly known folk psychology. If materialism is true, there are no perfect occu­ pants of the role, and hence no perfect deservers of the name. But in all probability there are imperfect occupants of the role, imperfect deservers of the name. Good enough deservers of the name? May they just be called 'qualia'? I say yes. But I take this to be a case of semantic indecision. There is no settled answer to the question 'how good is good enough?'.
    [Show full text]
  • Dennett's Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness
    Dennett’s Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness1 Justin Sytsma Abstract: It is not uncommon to find assumptions being made about folk psychology in the discussions of phenomenal consciousness in philosophy of mind. In this article I consider one example, focusing on what Dan Dennett says about the “folk theory of consciousness.” I show that he holds that the folk believe that qualities like colors that we are acquainted with in ordinary perception are phenomenal qualities. Nonetheless, the shape of the folk theory is an empirical matter and in the absence of empirical investigation there is ample room for doubt. Fortunately, experimental evidence on the topic is now being produced by experimental philosophers and psychologists. This article contributes to this growing literature, presenting the results of six new studies on the folk view of colors and pains. I argue that the results indicate against Dennett’s theory of the folk theory of consciousness. The existence of phenomenal consciousness is often taken for granted in the philosophical and scientific literature on the topic. Sometimes, this attitude is supported by claims that phenomenal consciousness is in some way evident in our ordinary experience itself.2 The prevalence of this attitude can also be seen in the way that some skeptics about phenomenal consciousness discuss the supposed phenomenon. For example, the qualia eliminativist Dan Dennett seems to accept that belief in qualia is part of our “folk theory of consciousness” (2005, 31). In contrast, I have argued that phenomenal consciousness is not evident in ordinary experience alone—that it is not phenomenologically obvious—and that this can be drawn out by 1 To appear in the Journal of Consciousness Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Privileged Access and Qualia
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by European Scientific Journal (European Scientific Institute) European Scientific Journal December 2015 edition vol.11, No.35 ISSN: 1857 – 7881 (Print) e - ISSN 1857- 7431 PRIVILEGED ACCESS AND QUALIA Thomas W. Smythe Retired Associate Professor, North Carolina Central University Abstract In this paper I shall examine some recent literature that purports to show that sensations or qualia are not real psychological phenomena, and that we do not have privileged access to our psychological states. In particular, I shall criticize some work by Daniel C. Dennett, who has argued against the existence of qualia and privileged access to the mental. I will maintain that Dennett has not made a convincing case for eliminating qualia, and has not shown that we do not have privileged access to psychological phenomena from a first-person point of view. Keywords: Qualia, Privileged Access, Self-Warranting Knowledge Introduction I will defend the view that certain criticisms of what has been called self-justifying or self-warranting knowledge of our psychological states have not succeeded. I will do this by arguing that attempts by Dennett and others to undermine self-justifying knowledge are unsuccessful. I begin by examining a paper by Dennett where he attempts to eliminate qualia. In a notable paper called ”Quining Qualia,” Dennett explains that he uses the verb ‘to quine’ in honor of W. V. O. Quine. It means to deny resolutely the existence or importance of something seemingly real and significant, for example, the soul. Quining qualia means saying there is no such thing as qualia.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia NICHOLAS HARKNESS Harvard University, USA
    Qualia NICHOLAS HARKNESS Harvard University, USA Qualia (singular, quale) are cultural emergents that manifest phenomenally as sensuous features or qualities. The anthropological challenge presented by qualia is to theorize elements of experience that are semiotically generated but apperceived as non-signs. Qualia are not reducible to a psychology of individual perceptions of sensory data, to a cultural ontology of “materiality,” or to philosophical intuitions about the subjective properties of consciousness. The analytical solution to the challenge of qualia is to con- sider tone in relation to the familiar linguistic anthropological categories of token and type. This solution has been made methodologically practical by conceptualizing qualia, in Peircean terms, as “facts of firstness” or firstness “under its form of secondness.” Inthephilosophyofmind,theterm“qualia”hasbeenusedtodescribetheineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible experiences of “the way things seem,” which have been taken to constitute the atomic subjective properties of consciousness. This concept was challenged in an influential paper by Daniel Dennett, who argued that qualia “is a philosophers’ term which fosters nothing but confusion, and refers in the end to no properties or features at all” (Dennett 1988, 387). Dennett concluded, correctly, that these diverse elements of feeling, made sensuously present atvariouslevelsofattention,wereactuallyidiosyncraticresponsestoapperceptions of “public, relational” qualities. Qualia were, in effect,
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology's
    Augsburg Honors Review Volume 12 Article 4 2019 Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Allison Mangan Augsburg University Follow this and additional works at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended Citation Mangan, Allison (2019) "Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire," Augsburg Honors Review: Vol. 12 , Article 4. Available at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review/vol12/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Idun. It has been accepted for inclusion in Augsburg Honors Review by an authorized editor of Idun. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Allison Mangan Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Alio Maga, Augbug Univesty ualia are layered and complex, the basic philosophic understanding a labyrinth of a concept, of qualia today. We will see how Q rife with debate as to their consciousness is necessary for qualia, existence, state, and what they mean and why this makes defning qualia for our understanding of knowledge, a challenge. Next, we will go over the relationship with the world, and explanatory gap of qualia. From there, ourselves. Toughtful exploration into we will see how qualia relate to the mind- the complexities of what qualia are body problem, and the early exploration and how they relate to the mind-body of this problem through Descartes, problem will be wrestled with though Locke, and Berkeley. Additionally, we research applied within this paper. will go over the main schools of thought Qualia can be found in philosophical that surround the mind-body problem: debates surrounding epistemology materialism, idealism, and dualism.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a REFUTATION of QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael
    1 To appear in M. O’Rourke and C. Washington (eds.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry (MIT Press) A REFUTATION OF QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University Recent defenders of reductive physicalism such as Brian Loar (1990, 1997) and John Perry (2001) have adopted an intriguing new strategy:i (1) accept as so much common sense (nearly) everything that property-dualists want to say about sensory qualia, including the central claims that sensory qualia determine ‘what it’s like’ to have a given sense experience, and that persons are directly aware of these qualia in the having of such experiences; (2) contend that while these common sense facts about qualia may show that our ways of thinking and speaking about qualia are conceptually different from our ways of thinking and speaking about physical properties of the brain, these facts do not show that sensory qualia themselves (as opposed to our ways of thinking and speaking about them) are distinct from physical properties of the brain; (3) use this contention to turn aside the few existing arguments against reductive physicalism by such property dualists as Kripke (1972), Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996); and finally (4) insist that sensory qualia are in fact just identical with physical properties of the brain, so that consequently, the facts about the sensory qualities of conscious experience are nothing over and above physical facts about the brain. I will call the view that incorporates this strategy ‘qualia-physicalism’, or ‘Q-physicalism’ for short. In this paper I will argue that Q-physicalism is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind/Body Overview
    Mind/Body Overview 1. Physics and Folk Psychology a. Physics: hard-nosed, particles, observables, repeatable b. Folk Psychology: Beliefs, hopes, desires, sensations, subjective, consciousness 2. Issues a. Ontological 1. What are mental states and processes? 2. What are physical states and processes? 3. How are the mental and physical related? 4. Example: Replace NS with silicon starting at retina. Still conscious? b. Semantical 1. Where do propositional attitudes get their meanings? Ex: Belief; Belief that p. 2. Where do qualia get their meanings? Ex: pain, red, warmth 3. Where do other terms get their meanings? Ex: horse, electron c. Epistemological 1. How do we know anything? 2. How do we know if something has a mind? (Problem of other minds) 3. How do I know my own mental states? (Problem of self-consciousness) d. Methodological 1. What are appropriate methods for studying psychology? 2. What determines their propriety? 3. Ontologies a. Substance Dualism 1. Descartes: Mind is a distinct substance from matter 2. Matter: extended in space; has length, width, breadth, and position. 1 3. Mind: essence is thinking; has no extension or position in space. 4. Reasons: how could matter ever use language or reason mathematically? 5. Problem: How can mind interact with matter, and not violate conservation laws? 6. Problem: Electrons have no extension or determinate postion in space. Yet physical. 7. Eccles and Popper: mind affects probabilities of exocytosis at all synapses b. Popular Dualism 1. Mind is a “ghost in a machine”; machine=body; mind=spiritual substance 2. Mind is inside body (probably brain) 3. Mind interacts with brain by some form of energy exchange 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Environments of Intelligence
    Environments of Intelligence “An absorbing volume that integrates an extraordinarily wide area of work, with interesting observations and new twists right to the end.” Ruth Millikan, University of Connecticut, USA What is the role of the environment, and of the information it provides, in cognition? More specifically, may there be a role for certain artefacts to play in this context? These are questions that motivate “4E” theories of cognition (as being embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). In his take on that family of views, Hajo Greif first defends and refines a concept of information as primarily natural, environmen- tally embedded in character, which had been eclipsed by information-processing views of cognition. He continues with an inquiry into the cognitive bearing of some artefacts that are sometimes referred to as “intelligent environments”. With- out necessarily having much to do with Artificial Intelligence, such artefacts may ultimately modify our informational environments. With respect to human cognition, the most notable effect of digital computers is not that they might be able, or become able, to think but that they alter the way we perceive, think and act. Hajo Greif teaches at the Munich Center for Technology in Society (MCTS), Technical University of Munich, Germany, and the Department of Philosophy, University of Klagenfurt, Austria. His research interests cover the philosophy – and some of the history and the social studies – of science and technology, as well as the philosophy of mind. History and Philosophy of Technoscience Series Editor: Alfred Nordmann For a full list of titles in this series, please visit www.routledge.com 1 Error and Uncertainty in Scientific Practice Marcel Boumans, Giora Hon and Arthur C.
    [Show full text]
  • 15 How to Believe in Qualia
    15 How to Believe in Qualia Amy Kind Why should we believe that qualia exist? It would not be su~prisingif, when confronted with this question, the qualia realist were puzzled. "Look around you," she might say, "and then pause for just a moment and retlest on your experiences. Isn't there a redness to your experience of that soda can on your desk? And isn't there a sweetness to your experience as you take a sip from it? Surely your experiences have qualitative aspect+surely there is something your experiences are like!' And thus, to many a qualia realist, the answer to the question posed above is simple. Why believe in qualia? Because our every experience meals their existence. Unfortunately, the matter cannot be resolved this easily. (If it could, then there would be no need to produce a collection of papers making the case for quaUa.) The existence of qualia has long been under attack. Opponents of qualia typically fall into two camps. In the &st camp, we have philosophers who admit that, at least on the face of it, the phenom- enological data support the existence of qualia. By their lights, however, thm are strong theoretical reasons that count against qualia (typically that they cannot be accommodated within a physicalist framework). These opponents thui have the task of explaining why we should disregard the phenomenology of ow experience. They must convince us why we should not believe in qualia. In the second camp, however, are philosophers who deny the phenorn- enological data. Qualia realists have it wrong, they say.
    [Show full text]
  • Dennett's Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Philsci-Archive Dennett’s Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness1 Justin Sytsma Abstract: It is not uncommon to find assumptions being made about folk psychology in the discussions of phenomenal consciousness in philosophy of mind. In this article I consider one example, focusing on what Dan Dennett says about the “folk theory of consciousness.” I show that he holds that the folk believe that qualities like colors that we are acquainted with in ordinary perception are phenomenal qualities. Nonetheless, the shape of the folk theory is an empirical matter and in the absence of empirical investigation there is ample room for doubt. Fortunately, experimental evidence on the topic is now being produced by experimental philosophers and psychologists. This article contributes to this growing literature, presenting the results of six new studies on the folk view of colors and pains. I argue that the results indicate against Dennett’s theory of the folk theory of consciousness. The existence of phenomenal consciousness is often taken for granted in the philosophical and scientific literature on the topic. Sometimes, this attitude is supported by claims that phenomenal consciousness is in some way evident in our ordinary experience itself.2 The prevalence of this attitude can also be seen in the way that some skeptics about phenomenal consciousness discuss the supposed phenomenon. For example, the qualia eliminativist Dan Dennett seems to accept that belief in qualia is part of our “folk theory of consciousness” (2005, 31). In contrast, I have argued that phenomenal consciousness is not evident in ordinary experience alone—that it is not phenomenologically obvious—and that this can be drawn out by 1 To appear in the Journal of Consciousness Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Eidos Fecha De Recepción: Marzo 3 De 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha De Aceptación: Julio 28 De 2011 Issne 2011-7477
    eidos Fecha de recepción: marzo 3 de 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha de aceptación: julio 28 de 2011 ISSNe 2011-7477 IS THE PANPSYCHIST BETTER OFF AS AN IDEALIST? SOME LEIBNIZIAN REMARKS ON CONSCIOUSNESS AND COMPOSITION Michael Blamauer University of Vienna, Department of Philosophy [email protected] RESUMEN Algunos filósofos de la mente han defendido la idea de considerar la mente como otra característica fundamental de la realidad, además de las propiedades físicas. De ahí que la mayoría de ellos sean propiamente dualistas. Sin embargo, algunos de ellos son pansiquistas. En este artículo sostendré que ser propiamente un dualista implica, en esencia, ser pansiqui- sta. Incluso, si el pansiquismo aborda ciertas dificultades relacionadas con el problema de la conciencia de manera muy elegante, éstas permanecen inmodificables. Siendo partidario del carácter fundamental de la mente, de- fenderé la idea de que sólo mediante una revisión radical de la metafísica el pansiquista podrá evitar tales problemas y, en consecuencia, que debe adoptar el idealismo leibniciano. PALABRAS CLAVE Panpsiquismo, Leibniz, filosofía de la mente, dualismo, composición. ABSTRACT Some philosophers of mind have argued for considering consciousness as a further fundamental feature of reality in addition to its physical prop- erties. Hence most of them are property dualists. But some of them are panpsychists. In the present paper it will be argued that being a real prop- erty dualist essentially entails being a panpsychist. Even if panpsychism deals rather elegantly with certain problems of the puzzle of consciousness, there’s no way around the composition problem. Adhering to the funda- mentality claim of the mind, it will be shown that only a radical revision of metaphysics will allow the panpsychist to avoid these troubles, and hence that a panpsychist must adopt Leibnizian idealism.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz 1
    This article was downloaded by: [Stanford University Libraries] On: 24 September 2012, At: 17:23 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK British Journal for the History of Philosophy Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rbjh20 Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz Shane Duarte a a Stanford University, Version of record first published: 22 Sep 2009. To cite this article: Shane Duarte (2009): Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz , British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17:4, 705-733 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09608780903135089 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub- licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17(4) 2009: 705–733 ARTICLE IDEAS AND CONFUSION IN LEIBNIZ1 Shane Duarte I.
    [Show full text]