ABSTRACT the Argument from Divine Hiddenness: an Assessment Ross Parker, Ph.D. Mentor: Trent Dougherty, Ph.D. the Argument From

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

ABSTRACT the Argument from Divine Hiddenness: an Assessment Ross Parker, Ph.D. Mentor: Trent Dougherty, Ph.D. the Argument From ABSTRACT The Argument from Divine Hiddenness: An Assessment Ross Parker, Ph.D. Mentor: Trent Dougherty, Ph.D. The argument from divine hiddenness against God’s existence has become one of the most important atheistic arguments in the contemporary philosophical literature. In this dissertation I offer an assessment of this argument. Specifically, I provide some needed conceptual clarity to the discussion of the argument from hiddenness and respond to various strands of the contemporary discussion of the argument. In the first chapter I argue that the argument from hiddenness is best understood as a family of arguments, and I give an account of what binds these arguments together. In the second chapter, after surveying extant presentations of arguments from hiddenness, I provide a conceptual map of various ways an argument from hiddenness can be presented. I then in the third chapter I develop a Schellenbergian argument from the existence of inculpable nonbelief which serves as the focus of my critical evaluation. In the fourth chapter I address the relationship between that argument from evil and the argument from hiddenness. Chapters five and six offer critiques of two recent attempts to respond to the argument from evil. Then in the seventh chapter I develop my own response to the Schellenbergian argument from hiddenness, arguing that God would be justified in allowing temporary inculpable favorably disposed nonbelief because of various goods that make possible or are made possible by the existence of nonbelief. Copyright © 2014 by Ross Parker All rights reserved TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements Dedication CHAPTER ONE: The Argument from Divine Hiddenness 1 §1.1: Introduction to the Dissertation §1.2: Some Preliminary Issues §1.3: An Analysis of Arguments from Hiddenness §1.4: Conclusion CHAPTER TWO: A Historical and Conceptual Overview of the Argument from Divine Hiddenness 14 §2.1: A Survey of Arguments from Divine Hiddenness §2.1.1 The Discussion of Divine Hiddenness before the Modern Period §2.1.2 Summaries of Arguments from Divine Hiddenness §2.1.3 Differences and Commonalities in the Arguments from Divine Hiddenness §2.2: The Conceptual Space of Arguments from Hiddenness §2.3: Conclusion CHAPTER THREE: A Defense of the Argument from Inculpable Nonbelief 42 §3.1: In Defense of the Theological Premise §3.2: In Defense of the Existence Premise §3.3: Conclusion CHAPTER FOUR: The Argument from Divine Hiddenness and the Argument from Evil 67 §4.1: The Argument from Evil §4.2: Commonly Acknowledged Connections between the Argument from Evil and the Argument from Divine Hiddenness §4.3. The Argument from Hiddenness is a Version of the Argument from Evil §4.3.1: The Positive Case §4.3.2: Van Inwagen’s case for conceptual independence §4.3.3 Schellenberg’s case for conceptual independence §4.4: Conclusion v CHAPTER FIVE: An Inadequate Response to Arguments from Divine Hiddenness 95 §5.1: Jordan on (L), the Nature of Love, and Intensity of Love §5.2: Jordan’s Divine Perfection Argument against (L) §5.3: Jordan’s Nature of Love Argument against (L) §5.4: Evaluating the divine perfection argument against (L) §5.5: Evaluating the Nature of Love Argument against (L) §5.6: Conclusion CHAPTER SIX: A Critical Evaluation of Rea’s Response to the Problem of Divine Hiddenness 121 §6.1: Rea’s argument from hiddenness §6.2: Rea’s Response to RIT §6.2.1: Defending T1 §6.2.2: Defending T2 §6.2.3: Defending T3 §6.3: Evaluating Rea’s Presentation of the Argument from Divine Hiddenness §6.4: Evaluating T1 §6.4.1: Interpreting Divine Silence §6.4.2: Rea’s Defense of his God-justifying Good §6.4.3 Another Problem for Rea’s God-justifying Good §6.5: Evaluating T3 §6.6: Evaluating T2 §6.7: Conclusion CHAPTER SEVEN: A Cumulative Case Response to the Argument from Inculpable Nonbelief 147 §7.1: What is Required to Reply to the Argument? §7.2: Responding to the AIN §7.2.1: A Consideration of the Existence Premise §7.2.2: Rejecting the Theological Premise of the AIN §7.3: Responding to AIFDN §7.3.1 Evaluating the Existence Premise §7.3.2 A Consideration of the Value of Theistic Belief for the Favorably Disposed §7.3.3 Relating Personally to God without Theistic Belief §7.3.4 The Cumulative Case Response to the Theological Premise §7.3.4.1: Nonbelief and the Good of Moral Freedom §7.3.4.2: Divine Hiddenness and the Good of Intellectual Probation §7.3.4.3: Divine Hiddenness and the Goods of Social Dependency §7.3.4.4: Divine Hiddenness and the Good of Learning for Oneself vi §7.3.4.5: Divine Hiddenness and the Good of Desiring to Know God §7.3.5 Conclusion of My Evaluation of the AIFDN §7.4: Responding to Schellenberg’s Accomodationist Strategy §7.4.1 The Accomodationist Strategy Stated §7.4.2: Critical Evaluation §7.5: Conclusion WORKS CITED 200 vii ANALYTIC TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE: The Argument from Divine Hiddenness §1.1: Introduction to the Dissertation I provide a brief and intuitive statement of the argument from hiddenness. I then give a brief overview of the chapters of the dissertation. §1.2: Some Preliminary Issues This section addresses the following issues: I first state that I will use the term “God” as an honorific title and not as a proper name, referring minimally to a being who is all-powerful, all-knowing, perfectly good, worthy of worship, and creator of the universe. This allows theists and atheists to talk about what God would and would not do. Second, I discuss the phrase “argument from divine hiddenness,” pointing out that it’s not the best title for the argument since it seems to imply that God exists (though I continue to follow the literature and use the terminology of divine hiddenness following the literature). Third, I acknowledge that I will be drawing on the resources of the Christian tradition in my evaluation of the argument from hiddenness. §1.3: An Analysis of Arguments from Hiddenness This section defends my claim that the argument from divine hiddenness is a family of arguments with the following common core: arguments from hiddenness argue (i) that states of affairs describable as instances of divine hiddenness (ii) are incompatible or in evidential tension with a perfectly good God. Concerning (ii), to have an argument from hiddenness for God’s nonexistence, hiddenness must be something that is unexpected, surprising, or incompatible with God’s existence. Concerning (i) I argue that divine hiddenness is best understood as a lack of epistemic support for truths about God necessary for being in a loving relationship with God (with an epistemic lack concerning the existence of God as the most important of these truths). Below is a summary of my argument for this understanding of divine hiddenness: ASSUMPTION: The divine hiddenness connected to arguments from hiddenness is epistemic hiddenness. (1) It is not the case that the following is a sufficient condition for divine hiddenness: there is some proposition about God such that someone lacks epistemic support for that proposition. viii (2) Divine hiddenness is broader than lack of epistemic support for the proposition <God exists>. (3) If (1) and (2), then divine hiddenness is a lack of epistemic support for some sub-set of propositions about God. (4) The best account of divine hiddenness is to understand divine hiddenness as a lack of epistemic support for truths about God important for being in a personal relationship with God. §1.4: Conclusion CHAPTER TWO: A Historical and Conceptual Overview of the Argument from Divine Hiddenness §2.1: A Survey of Arguments from Divine Hiddenness I overview the extant statements of atheistic arguments from the existence of divine hiddenness. I do this in order to give a survey of the literature on the argument, as well as to provide support for the account of what constitutes an argument from hiddenness defended in §1.2. §2.1.1 The Discussion of Divine Hiddenness before the Modern Period Though arguments from hiddenness are not often made in the history of philosophy, there was a fair bit of discussion concerning the issue of divine hiddenness (I consider Anselm’s discussion of hiddenness). I offer two considerations for why arguments from hiddenness were not made throughout the history of philosophy: (1) If one is to give an argument from hiddenness, then one must claim that divine hiddenness is in evidential tension with the existence of God. But many accounts of God on offer in ancient times consider God as unconcerned with human existence, which means there’s no evidential tension between God’s existence and divine hiddenness. (2) Many Theistic thinkers believed that they had strong evidence for God’s existence. So they approached divine hiddenness as something that must be compatible with God’s existence, instead of seeing it as a evidence against God existence. §2.1.2 Summaries of Arguments from Divine Hiddenness I summarize arguments from hiddenness given in the following works: Berkeley 1710; Butler 1736; Nietzsche 1881; Hepburn 1963; Hanson 1971; O’Hear 1984; Schellenberg 1993; Schellenberg 2007; Schellenberg 2004 (analogy argument); Schellenberg 2007 (four arguments from specific kinds of nonbelief); Drange 1993, 1998; Maitzen 2006; Rowe 1996, 2001 ix §2.1.3 Differences and Commonalities in the Arguments from Divine Hiddenness Concerning the arguments outlined in §2.1.2, there are differences in the understanding of God argued against, the type of hiddenness that motivates the argument, and the amount of hiddenness that is taken to be problematic (other differences could be identified). But there are important similarities – all argue from the existence of epistemic lack concerning relationally-necessary truths about God, all assume an omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent God, and all claim that hiddenness is in some way in evidential tension with God’s perfect goodness.
Recommended publications
  • Does Reasonable Nonbelief Exist?
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 18 Issue 1 Article 6 1-1-2001 Does Reasonable Nonbelief Exist? Douglas V. Henry Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Henry, Douglas V. (2001) "Does Reasonable Nonbelief Exist?," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 18 : Iss. 1 , Article 6. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200118114 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol18/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. DOES REASONABLE NONBELIEF EXIST? Douglas V. Henry J. L. Schellenberg's Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason claims that the exis­ tence of reflective persons who long to solve the problem of God's existence but cannot do so constitutes an evil rendering God's existence in1probable. In this essay, I present Schellenberg's argument and argue that the kind of reasonable nonbelief Schellenberg needs for his argument to succeed is unlikely to exist. Since Schellenberg's argument is an inductive-style version of the problem of evil, the empirical improbability of the premise Ichallenge renders the conclusions derived fron1 it empirically improbable as well. 1. Introduction In Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason, J. L. Schellenberg presents a special version of the problem of evil, one that is an interesting, significant, and genuinely new contribution to the scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • Statement of the Problem 1
    Liberty Baptist Theological Seminary THE INCOMPATIBILITY OF OPEN THEISM WITH THE DOCTRINE OF INERRANCY A Report Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Theology by Stuart M. Mattfield 29 December 2014 Copyright © 2015 by Stuart M. Mattfield All Rights Reserved ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS As with all things, the first-fruits of my praise goes to God: Father, Son and Spirit. I pray this work brings Him glory and honor. To my love and wife, Heidi Ann: You have been my calm, my sanity, my helpful critic, and my biggest support. Thank you and I love you. To my kids: Madison, Samantha, and Nick: Thank you for your patience, your humor, and your love. Thank you to Dr. Kevin King and Dr. Dan Mitchell. I greatly appreciate your mentorship and patience through this process. iii ABSTRACT The primary purpose of this thesis is to show that the doctrine of open theism denies the doctrine of inerrancy. Specifically open theism falsely interprets Scriptural references to God’s Divine omniscience and sovereignty, and conversely ignores the weighty Scriptural references to those two attributes which attribute perfection and completeness in a manner which open theism explicitly denies. While the doctrine of inerrancy has been hotly debated since the Enlightenment, and mostly so through the modern and postmodern eras, it may be argued that there has been a traditional understanding of the Bible’s inerrancy that is drawn from Scripture, and has been held since the early church fathers up to today’s conservative theologians. This view was codified in October, 1978 in the form of the Chicago Statement of Biblical Inerrancy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Heritage of Non-Theistic Belief in China
    The Heritage of Non-theistic Belief in China Joseph A. Adler Kenyon College Presented to the international conference, "Toward a Reasonable World: The Heritage of Western Humanism, Skepticism, and Freethought" (San Diego, September 2011) Naturalism and humanism have long histories in China, side-by-side with a long history of theistic belief. In this paper I will first sketch the early naturalistic and humanistic traditions in Chinese thought. I will then focus on the synthesis of these perspectives in Neo-Confucian religious thought. I will argue that these forms of non-theistic belief should be considered aspects of Chinese religion, not a separate realm of philosophy. Confucianism, in other words, is a fully religious humanism, not a "secular humanism." The religion of China has traditionally been characterized as having three major strands, the "three religions" (literally "three teachings" or san jiao) of Confucianism, Daoism, and Buddhism. Buddhism, of course, originated in India in the 5th century BCE and first began to take root in China in the 1st century CE, so in terms of early Chinese thought it is something of a latecomer. Confucianism and Daoism began to take shape between the 5th and 3rd centuries BCE. But these traditions developed in the context of Chinese "popular religion" (also called folk religion or local religion), which may be considered a fourth strand of Chinese religion. And until the early 20th century there was yet a fifth: state religion, or the "state cult," which had close relations very early with both Daoism and Confucianism, but after the 2nd century BCE became associated primarily (but loosely) with Confucianism.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE (Last Revised 10/19/2017)
    CURRICULUM VITAE (Last Revised 10/19/2017) KEITH McKENDREE PARSONS POSITION: Professor of Philosophy University of Houston-Clear Lake Dates of Employment: September 1, 1996 to present. Assistant Professor, 9/96-9/2002 Associate Professor, 9/2002-9/2006 Promoted to Professor, 9/2006 ADDRESS: Box #296 University of Houston-Clear Lake 2700 Bay Area Boulevard Houston, TX 77058 Office Phone: (281) 283-3361 Home Phone: (281) 309-1944 E-mail: [email protected] EDUCATION: Ph.D.--History and Philosophy of Science, The University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA; 1996 Dissertation: Wrongheaded Science? Rationality, Constructivism, and Dinosaurs; Supervisor: James Lennox Ph.D.--Philosophy, Queen's University, Kingston, Ontario, Canada; 1986 Dissertation: Science, Confirmation, and the Theistic Hypothesis; Supervisor: C.G. Prado; M.A.--Philosophy, Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA; 1982 Thesis: Miracles and Christian Apologetics; Supervisor: James Humber Master of Theological Studies--Emory University, Atlanta, Georgia; 1981; awarded cum laude B.A.--Religion and Philosophy, Berry College, Rome, Georgia; 1974; awarded magna cum laude AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION: Philosophy of Science; History of Science and Technology; Philosophy of Religion AREAS OF COMPETENCE: Darwinism; History of Philosophy; Logic; Critical Thinking PUBLICATIONS: Books: Polarized: Confronting the Collapse of Truth, Civility, and Community in Divided Times, Co-authored with Paris N. Donehoo, D. Min. Prometheus Books, (forthcoming, 2018). Bombing The Marshall Islands: A Cold War Tragedy. Co- authored with Robert Zaballa, Ph.D. Cambridge University Press (2017). It Started with Copernicus; extensively revised and expanded (three new chapters) edition of Copernican Questions, Prometheus Books (2014). Selected by Choice Reviews as an Outstanding Academic Title in 2015.
    [Show full text]
  • A Scriptural and Philosophical Evaluation of the Open Model of God As an Ontological Necessity and Its Compatibility with Evangelical Theology
    Ouachita Baptist University Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita Honors Theses Carl Goodson Honors Program 2007 A Scriptural and Philosophical Evaluation of the Open Model of God as an Ontological Necessity and Its Compatibility with Evangelical Theology Richard Garrett Ham Jr. Ouachita Baptist University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.obu.edu/honors_theses Part of the Biblical Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, and the Practical Theology Commons Recommended Citation Ham, Richard Garrett Jr., "A Scriptural and Philosophical Evaluation of the Open Model of God as an Ontological Necessity and Its Compatibility with Evangelical Theology" (2007). Honors Theses. 44. https://scholarlycommons.obu.edu/honors_theses/44 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Carl Goodson Honors Program at Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons @ Ouachita. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CI IAPTER I: INTRODUCTION .............................................................................................................................. ! Til£ EV.- \ 'I'GELICAL U'I'OEHSTAND II\"G OF SCIHPTUJn: ............................................................................................ 1 1'l1e Nature ofScriplllre ... ................................................................................................................... .................. 3 The Purpose ofScripture. ....... .... ......................
    [Show full text]
  • IS OPEN THEISM EVANGELICAL? . . . Bruce A. Ware
    JETS 45/2 (June 2002) 193–212 DEFINING EVANGELICALISM’S BOUNDARIES THEOLOGICALLY: IS OPEN THEISM EVANGELICAL? bruce a. ware* i. introduction Clark Pinnock is exactly right. After noting (correctly) in his Most Moved Mover that Arminians and Augustinians have co-existed throughout much of the church’s history, and that a number of evangelical theologians today (and not just open theists) are working toward refinements in an evangeli- cal doctrine of God, he asks, “Why draw the line at foreknowledge?”1 A few pages later, he returns to this question: “In raising the issue of the divine foreknowledge, we have not transgressed some rule of theological discourse and placed ourselves outside the pale of orthodoxy. Why can an evangelical not propose a different view of this matter? What church council has de- clared it to be impossible? Since when has this become the criterion of being orthodox or unorthodox, evangelical or not evangelical?”2 What does Pinnock mean when he says that open theists have raised the issue of divine foreknowledge? Simply this: Open theism affirms God’s ex- haustive knowledge of the past and present, but it denies exhaustive divine foreknowledge, in that it denies that God knows—or can know—the future free decisions and actions of his moral creatures, even while it affirms that God knows all future possibilities and all divinely determined and logically- necessary future actualities. As William Hasker explains, “Since the future is genuinely open, since it is possible for a free agent to act in any of several different ways, it follows that it is not possible for God to have complete and exhaustive knowledge of the entire future.”3 So, the specific denial of exhaustive divine foreknowledge is embraced in open theism as central and essential to its own identity.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Origins of Religious Universalism Peter R
    Ancient Origins of Religious Universalism Peter R. Bedford, Union College (A précis, of sorts) It is commonly considered By HeBrew BiBle scholars that monotheism in Ancient Israel—and By ‘monotheism’ I mean the Belief that there is only one God and that other ‘gods’ people worship are in fact figments of human imagination, idols that do not exist— emerged around the middle of the first millennium BCE in the context of Israel’s political subjugation and exile at the hands of successive Near Eastern empires, the Neo-Assyrian, Neo-BaBylonian, and the Achaemenid Persian empires. Imperialism is key here since the political sovereignty of the kingdoms of Israel and Judah was undermined By these empires and with it the royal-state ideology that averred that Yahweh, the god of these kingdoms, was their sovereign lord who superintended their affairs and well-being. The political power of these foreign empires compromised the authority of Yahweh since it very much looked like their gods had greater authority than the god of Israel and Judah and that these imperial gods dictated what would happen to Israel and Judah, their kings and their peoples. One reaction of a suBjugated people to the demonstrated power of successive empires and their chief deities—Assur for Assyria, Marduk for Babylonia, Ahura Mazda for Persia—is simply to recognize that your own god is one among many who serves the Great God of the empire in the heavenly court, and so suBjugated peoples here on earth must serve the Great King of the empire who acts as the imperial god’s vicegerent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: a Version of the Argument from Reason
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies The Vault: Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2019-04-30 The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason Hawkes, Gordon Hawkes, G. (2019). The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary, AB. http://hdl.handle.net/1880/110301 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason by Gordon Hawkes A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY CALGARY, ALBERTA APRIL, 2019 © Gordon Hawkes 2019 i Abstract The argument from reason is the name given to a family of arguments against naturalism, materialism, or determinism, and often for theism or dualism. One version of the argument from reason is what Victor Reppert calls “the argument from the psychological relevance of logical laws,” or what I call “the argument from logical principles.” This argument has received little attention in the literature, despite being advanced by Victor Reppert, Karl Popper, and Thomas Nagel.
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Religion
    Science and Religion: A Conflict of Methods Timothy Alexander Smith A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Otago, June 2017. i Abstract There is an epistemological conflict between religion and science. While the claims of science are justified using epistemic methods whose reliability has been corroborated by other people and by other methods, the claims of religion are not justified in the same way. Different methods are used. This thesis offers both a comprehensive description of the distinctive epistemic methods of religion and a philosophical appraisal of the claim that such methods are knowledge-conferring. The methods explored are various and care has been taken to sample a broad range of religious cultures. It is found that the same religious methods, when used to answer the same questions, generate different answers for different practitioners. Additionally, the results of religious methods fail to agree with the results of other epistemic methods when employed independently. This lack of independent agreement is the primary reason for the exclusion of religious methods from science. It is further argued that (a) this lack of agreement is evidence that religious methods are unreliable, and (b) the agreement generated by scientific methods is evidence for their reliability. ii Acknowledgements In 2013, I approached Greg Dawes at the AAPNZ Conference at the University of Auckland. ‘What’s wrong with creationism?’ I asked him. ‘Is it untestable in principle or has it simply failed too many tests?’ I can’t remember Greg’s exact reply, but this thesis was the result.
    [Show full text]
  • Leading a Polytheistic Faith to the Monotheistic
    The Asbury JOllmaI66/2:77-91 © 2011 "\sbury Theological Seminary Leading a PolYtheistic Faith to the Monotheistic God' A S tu4J in I dentijjing Barriers to the Gospel in a Chinese Buddhist Community and W qys to Overcome those Barriers Abstract This article is written for the purpose of exploring a way to lead a polytheistic faith, prevalent in the local Chinese Buddhist community (LCBC) in Brunei, to the reality of a monotheistic God as revealed in the Bible (1 Corinthians 8:6). It serves as a guide for the local Chinese church (CC) to lead the LCBC to see that God as a Creator is sufficient to be their God. This article identifies the need of a missiological package in order to lead the LCBC to Christ. The CC needs to assist the LCBC to become receptive before the core of the gospel message is proclaimed to the community. This article thus presents a missiological package which consists of ministries of witnessing Christ with good conduct, building good relations, taking dialogic action, establishing a well-organized team, contextualizing the gospel critically, directing the community to the Father of all, and applying consensus and pluralism in mission. Keywords: Chinese Buddhism, Chinese culture, worldview, Christian mission, evangelism, critical contextualization, and consensus and pluralism. Agnes N. A. Woo received her doctorate in missiology from "\sbury Theological Seminary in Wihnore, Kentucky. 77 78 I The Asbllry JOllrnal 66/ 2 (2011) The Yellow River is a place where the Chinese can trace their origin, a place where all the Chinese ancestors lived, and a place which tile Chinese should call home ..
    [Show full text]
  • Pentecostalism and Shamanism in Asia and Beyond: an Inter-Disciplinary Analysis
    Pentecostalism and Shamanism in Asia and Beyond An Inter-disciplinary Analysis Alena Govorounova “To every action there is always an equal and opposite reaction.” Isaac Newton, Third Law of Motion, Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica “The unlike is joined together, and from differences results the most beautiful harmony, and all things take place by strife.” Heraclitus of Ephesus, On Nature Erich Neumann suggests in The Origins and History of Con- sciousness that human consciousness is subjected to the constant process of centroversion and differentiation (Neumann 1973, 261). This tendency of human thought—to constantly strive toward polarities and reorganize itself again as a holistic mode—seems to pertain to all layers of human cog- nitive architecture, from archetypal pre-reflective self-awareness to highly analytical interpretative supra-consciousness. It is reflected in the evolution of cultures and civilizations and it seems to be the driving force behind his- * Alena Govorounova is a Research Associate at the Nanzan Institute for Religion and Culture. The quotations from the Bible are from the niv (New International Version, Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1984). 54 alena govorounova | 55 torical changes in the intellectual climate and scientific paradigm shifts (see Kuhn 1962). As Friedrich Nietzsche (1999 [1888]; 1966 [1886]) once ironi- cally observed, we are doomed to think in opposites and controversies, we are trapped in categorical dualisms of “good and evil,” we are conditioned by contrast-based human language, where each unit of meaning is defined against what it is not. We are carried away in the endless play of différance1 in search for identity and meaning and we need the Other to define who we are.
    [Show full text]
  • Craig, William Lane. "Religious Epistemology"
    verified, positivistic philosophers held them to be literally meaningless, as if one had asserted, “’t was brillig, and the slythey toves did gyre and gimble in the wabe.” Under criticism, the Verification Principle underwent a number of changes, including its permutation into the Falsification Principle, which held that a meaningful sentence must be capable in principle Religious epistemology of being empirically falsified. The fate of religious William Lane Craig language was thought to be no brighter under falsificationism than under verificationism, as became evident at a famous Oxford University symposium on “Theology and Falsification” held in 1948. "Enlightenment critiques of the reasonableness of religious belief point to defects not so much in At the symposium Antony Flew borrowed a story religious belief as in the conceptions of told several years earlier by John Wisdom knowledge uncritically adopted as the basis of concerning two explorers who came upon a patch these critiques. Maybe religious knowledge looks of flowers in a jungle clearing. One explorer was dubious because we have the wrong idea about convinced that the flowers were tended by a what it is to know something and how we know gardener. In the ensuing days, however, despite what we know." --C. Stephen Evans and Merold the explorers’ every effort to find him, no gardener Westphal, Christian Perspectives on Religious was ever detected. To save his hypothesis, the Knowledge. one explorer was progressively forced to qualify his original hypothesis to the point that the Introduction hypothesized gardener must be invisible, intangible, and undetectable. To which the other In Religious Epistemology we encounter the finally replied, “Just how does what you call an intersection of traditional epistemology with the invisible, intangible, eternally elusive gardener newly burgeoning field of Philosophy of Religion.
    [Show full text]