MATERIALISM and EMPIRIO-CRITICISM S.Hrcm;Sqxj

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

MATERIALISM and EMPIRIO-CRITICISM S.Hrcm;Sqxj V. I. LENIN MATERIALISM AND EMPIRIO-CRITICISM S.Hrcm;sqxJ VORKERS OF ALL COUNTRIES, UNITE! V. T. LENI MATERIALISM AND EMPIRIO-CRITICISM FOREIGN LANGUAGES PRESS PEKING 1,972 First Edition t9t2 PUBLISHER'S NOTE The ptesent English edition of V. I. Lenin, Materialis'n and. Empirio-Criticism, is a reprint of the text given in the book under CONTENTS the same title published by the Foreign Languages Publishing House, Moscow. It contains "Ten Questions to a Lecturer," a given Collected Lenin, reprint from the text in Vorks ol V. I. TEN QUESTIONS TO A LECTURER English edition, Vol. 14. The notes at the end of the book are based on those given in the Chinese edition published by the MATERIALISM .A.ND EMPIIItrO-CRITICISM People's Publishing House, Peking, Aptil r97r. Critical Comments on a Reactionary Philosophy ) PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION t PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION In Lieu ol lntroducliott HO\fl CERTAIN "MARXISTS" IN 19OB AND CERTAIN IDEALiSTS IN 1710 REFUTED MATERIAI,ISM Chaptet One Ti]E THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE OF EX,{PIRIO-CRITICISM .A.ND OF DIALECTICAL MATERIALISA,{. I 3r r. Sensations and Complexes of Scnsations 1r z. "The Discovery of the r#orld-Elements" 41 l. The Principal Co-ordination and "Naive Realism" 65 4. Did Nature Exist Prior to Man? 7t 5. Does Man Think with the Help of the Brain? 9o 6. The Solipsism of Mach and Avenarius 99 Cbapter Tzoo THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE OF EMPIRIO.CRITICISM AND OF DIALECTICAL MITTERIALISM' II to4 Priued in tbe People's Republic ol Cbina 111 11 CONTENTS CONIENTS r. The "Thing-in-Itself," or V. Chernov Refutes Frederick Cbapter Fiae Engels to4 THE RECENT REVOI,UT]ON IN NATURAL SCIENCE AND ry8 z. 1'Transcendence," or Bazarov "Revises" Engels I]' P}I[OSOPHICAI, IDEALISM Modern PhYsics ,oI 3, L. Feuerbach and J. Dietzgeo on the Thing-in-Itself 129 r. The Crisis in 4. Does Obfective Ttuth Exist? 13t 2. "Matter Has DisaPPeated" 308 5. Absolute and Relative Ttuth, or the Eclecticism of Engels 3. Is Motion W'ithout Matter Conceivablc? 1r8 as Discovered by A. Bogdanov r47 4. The Two Trcnds io Modern Physics, and English Spitit- 6. The Criterion of Practice in the Theory of Knorvledge rt, ualism 328 The Two Ttends in Modern Physics, and Getman Idealism 139 Cbapter Tlsree J. 6. The Two Trends in Modern Physics, and Frenctr Fideism 349 TIIE THEORY OF KNOTTLEDGE OF DIALECTICAL MATE- Russian "Idealist Physicist" 36o RIALISM AND OF EMPIRIO-CRITICISM. III $1 7. A The Essence and Siglificance o[ i'Physical" Idcalism ,64 r. What Is Matter? What Is Experience? fii 8. z. Plekhanov's Error Concerning the Concept "Experience" r72 Cb(llter Six 3. Causality and Necessity in Nature r7t EMPIRIO-CRITICISM AND HISTORICAL MATERIALISM 179 4. The "Principle of Economy of Thought" and the Problem r, The Excutsiotrs of the Getman Emp'irio-Criticists into the of the "Unity of the rJ/orld" t9, Field of the Social Sciences 380 5. Space and Time 202 z. How Bogdanov Corrects and "Develops" Marx t89 6. Freedom and Neccssity 2rS 3. Suvorov's "F-oundations of Social Philosophy" 400 Philosophy and Philosophical Blockheads 4c,6 Cbapter Four 4. Patties in Ernst Haeckel and Ernst &Iach 420 IFIE PHILOSOPHICAL IDEALISTS AS COMRADES-IN-ARMS ;. AND SUCCESSORS OF EMPIRIO-CR]TICISM CONCLUSION 413 r, The Criticism of Kantiar.rism from the LeIt and frorn the Cbaqtil Four, Section I Right Supplement to FROM WHAT ANGLE DID N. G. CHERNYSHEVSKY 2. How the "Ernpirio-Symbolist" Yushkevich ttre Ridiculed CR.ITICISE KANTIANISM? $6 "Empirio-Criticist" Chernov 24r ,. The Immanentists as Comradcs-in-Atms of Mach and NOTES 440 Avenarius 24t 4. Whithet Is Empirio-Criticism T'ending? 256 5. A. Bogdanov's "Empirio-Monism" 267 6. The "Thcory of Symbols" (ot Hieroglyphs) ancl tbe Criticism of Helmholtz 27t 7. Two Kinds of Criticism of Diihring 283 8. How Could J. Dietzgen Ilave For:nd Fevour with the Reactionary Philosophets ? 28g TEN QUESTIONS TO A LECTURER'I I. Does the lecturer acknowledge that the philosophy of Marxism is dial.ectical ruaterialis m? If he does not, why has he ncver analysed Engels' countless statemeflts If he do Machists call their "revision" of dialectical e philosophy of Marxism"? z. Does cknowledge Engels' fundamcntal 2 TEN euESTroNs ro A LECTURER 6. Does the lecturer acknowledge as correct Engcls' asser- tion that "matter without motion is as inconceivable as motion without matter"? (Anti-Dtibring, 1886, zrrd ed, p. 45, ia part 6 on natural philosophy, cosmogony, physics and chemistry.)3 7. Does the lecturer acknowleclge that the ideas of causal- ity, necessity,law, etc., ate a reflection in the human mind of MA.TERI,{LISM AND EIVffi'IRtrO-CR.ITICISM laws of flature, of the real world? Or was Engels wrong in saying so? (Anti-Dtibring, S. zo-zt, in part III on aprior- Critical Comments on a Reactionary ism, and S. to3-o4, in part XI on freedcim and necessity.)" Philosophyto 8. Does the lectr-lrer know that Mach expressed his agtee- ment with the head of the immanentist school, Schuppe, and evcn dedicated his last and chief philosophical work to him? How does the lecturer explain this adherence of Mach to the obviously idealist philosophy of Schuppe, a defender of clericalistn and in general a downright reactionary in phi- losophy? S. rMhy did the lecturer keep silent about "adventure" with his comrade of yesterday (according to the Studiess), the Menshevik Yushkevich, who has today cleclared Bog- danov6 (following in the wake of RakhmetovT) an ideatist? Is the lecturer aware that Petzoldt in his latest book has classed a number of Mach's disciples arnong the idealists? ro. Does the lecturer confirm the fact that Machism has nothirig in common with Bolshevism? And that Lenin has repeatedly protested against Machism?8 And that the Mensheviks Yushkevich and Valentinove are "pure" empirio- criticists ? Written in May-June r9o8 Published according to the manuscflPt First published in r92\, in Lenin, Miscellany lll PREFACE TO TFIE FIR.ST'EDITION A number of writers, would-be Marxists, have this year undertaken a veiltable campaign against the philosophy of Marxisrn. In the course of less than half a yer four books devoted mainly and almost exclusively to attacks on dialectical materialism have made their appearance. These include first and foremost Studies in l? - it would have been more proper to say "against"lLt ilre Philosopby ol A4arxisru (St. petersburg, r9o8), a symposium by Bazarov, Bogdanov, Lunacharsky, Rerman, Helfond, Yushkevich and Suvorov; yushkevich's Materialisru and Critical Realistn; Berman's Dialectics in tbe Ligbt ol the Modern Tbeory ol Knoza;tedge and Valentinov,s The Pbilosopbical Constructions ot' Marxism. All these people could not have been ignorant of the fact that Marx and Engels scores of times termed their philo- sophical views dialectical materialism. Yet all these people, who, despite the sharp divergence of their political views, are united in their hostility towards dialecticaT materialism, at the same time claim to be Marxists in philosophy! Engels' dialectics is "mysticism," says Berman. Engels' views havb become "antiquated," remarks Baz-arov casually, as though 6 PREFACI] TO TTIE FIRST EDIT]ON PREFACE To THE FIRsT EDITIoN 7 it n'ere a self-eviden t f act. Materialism thus appecrs to be and thoroughness that no one has ever found anything ambig- refuted by our bold warriors, who proudiy allude to the uous in such literary uttefances. "modern theory of knorvledge," "receflt philosophy'l ("r For the rest, there is in the Studies "in" tbe Pbilosopby ot' "recent positivism"), the "philosophy of modern natural Marxistn one phrase which resembles the truth. This is phrase: science," or even the "philosophy of natural science of the Lunacharsky's "Perhaps we li.e., all the collaborators of tire Stwdies evidently] have gone astray, but are seek- twentieth cefltury." Supported by all these supposedly reccnt we ing" (p. 16r). That the first half of this phrase contains an doctrines, our destroyers of dialectical matetialism proceed absolute and the second a relative truth, I shall endeavour fearlessly to downrigtrt fideism*12 (in the case of I-unachar- to denronstrate circumstantially in the present book. At the sky it is most evident, but by flo means in his casc alone!l3). moment I would only remark that if our philosophers had Yet when it comes to an explicit definition of their attitude spoken not in the name of Marxism but in the name o[ a and Engels, all their courage and all their towards Marx few "seeking" Marxists, they would have shown more respect once disappear. In respect for their own convictions at for themselves and for Marxisrn. dialectical materialism, deed a complete renunciation of As for myself, I too am a "seeker" in philosophy. Name- - attcmpts to i.. e., ot Marxism; in word - endless subterfuges, ly, the task I have set myself in these comments is to find to evade the essence of the qucstion, to cover their retreat, out what \tras the stumbling block to these people who under put some materialist or other in place of materialism in the guise of Marxism are offering something incredibly mud- general, and a determined refusal to make a ditect analysis dled, confused and reactioflary. materialist declarations of Marx and of the innumerable Tlte Autbor Engels. This is truly "mutiny on one's knees," as it was lustly characterised by one Marxist' This is typical philosoph- September r9o8 ical revisionism, fot it was only the revisionists who gained a sad notoriety for themselvcs by their departure from the fundamental views of Marxism and by their fear, or inability, to "settle accouflts" openly, explicitly, resolutely and cleady with the views they had abandoned.
Recommended publications
  • Gestalt Psychology and the Anti-Metaphysical Project of the Aufbau
    Science and Experience/ Science of Experience: Gestalt Psychology and the Anti-Metaphysical Project of the Aufbau Uljana Feest Technische Universität Berlin This paper investigates the way in which Rudolf Carnap drew on Gestalt psychological notions when deªning the basic elements of his constitutional system. I argue that while Carnap’s conceptualization of basic experience was compatible with ideas articulated by members of the Berlin/Frankfurt school of Gestalt psychology, his formal analysis of the relationship between two ba- sic experiences (“recollection of similarity”) was not. This is consistent, given that Carnap’s aim was to provide a uniªed reconstruction of scientiªc knowl- edge, as opposed to the mental processes by which we gain knowledge about the world. It is this last point that put him in marked contrast to some of the older epistemological literature, which he cited when pointing to the complex character of basic experience. While this literature had the explicit goal of overcoming metaphysical presuppositions by means of an analysis of conscious- ness, Carnap viewed these attempts as still carrying metaphysical baggage. By choosing the autopsychological basis, he expressed his intellectual depth to their antimetaphysical impetus. By insisting on the metaphysical neutrality of his system, he emphasized that he was carrying out a project in which they had not succeeded. 1. Introduction In his 1928 book, Der Logische Aufbau der Welt, Rudolf Carnap presented what he called a “constructional system” (Carnap 1967). The aim of this system was to demonstrate that all of our scientiªc concepts are logically derivable from more “basic” concepts in a hierarchical fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Vienna Our Aim Is, by Academic Standards, a Radical One : to Use Each of Our Four Topics As a Mirror in Which to Reflect and to Study All the Others
    TOUCHSTONE Gustav Klimt, from Ver Sacrum Wittgenstein' s VIENNA Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin TOUCHSTONE A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster Copyright ® 1973 by Allan Janik and Stephen Toulmin All rights reserved including the right of reproduction in whole or in part in any form A Touchstone Book Published by Simon and Schuster A Division of Gulf & Western Corporation Simon & Schuster Building Rockefeller Center 1230 Avenue of the Americas New York, N.Y. 10020 TOUCHSTONE and colophon are trademarks of Simon & Schuster ISBN o-671-2136()-1 ISBN o-671-21725-9Pbk. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 72-83932 Designed by Eve Metz Manufactured in the United States of America 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 The publishers wish to thank the following for permission to repro­ duce photographs: Bettmann Archives, Art Forum, du magazine, and the National Library of Austria. For permission to reproduce a portion of Arnold SchOnberg's Verklarte Nacht, our thanks to As­ sociated Music Publishers, Inc., New York, N.Y., copyright by Bel­ mont Music, Los Angeles, California. Contents PREFACE 9 1. Introduction: PROBLEMS AND METHODS 13 2. Habsburg Vienna: CITY OF PARADOXES 33 The Ambiguity of Viennese Life The Habsburg Hausmacht: Francis I The Cilli Affair Francis Joseph The Character of the Viennese Bourgeoisie The Home and Family Life-The Role of the Press­ The Position of Women-The Failure of Liberalism The Conditions of Working-Class Life : The Housing Problem Viktor Adler and Austrian Social Democracy Karl Lueger and the Christian Social Party Georg von Schonerer and the German Nationalist Party Theodor Herzl and Zionism The Redl Affair Arthur Schnitzler's Literary Diagnosis of the Viennese Malaise Suicide inVienna 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Thirty-Four NEOPOSITIVISM at WAR with METAPHYSICS
    Thirty-Four NEOPOSITIVISM AT WAR WITH METAPHYSICS Scolars customarily divide Positivism into three phases. The first phase comprises the professional careeer of Positivism’s founder, Auguste Comte. The second phase is the empirio-critical phase in the late nineteenth century as represented by Richard Avenarius (1843–1896) and Ernst Mach (1838–1916). Moritz Schlick (1882–1936) led the third phase, that of the Vienna Circle. Schlick held a chair at the University of Vienna after Mach, Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970), and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). These schools shared a minimalistic conception of science and a negative attitude toward metaphysics. In some sense we may even say that the Positivist and new conception of science has a negative purpose: to eliminate metaphysics from among the sciences. Comte tried to eliminate metaphysics by changing the guiding question in science from inquiry about causes to descriptions that do not refer to causes. This allowed him to banish metaphysical questions from science. Followers of Comte such as Mach and Avenarius held that “how,” not “why,” is the question that should guide science. Science answers the question “how?” by resorting to “pure experience” expressed with the help of “pure description.”1 Pure experience is the foundation of science and contains no elements borrowed from ordinary, or naïve, experience. It contains no elements that are the result of human projection. Pure experience concerns only facts, which we can describe, not explain. Our description must be economical. We must express as simply as possible and must include as many facts as possible. Such a description of facts provides the basis for formulating general laws, although each fact occurs only once and is different from all other facts.
    [Show full text]
  • Points of View in the Modern History of Psychology
    Points of View in the Modern History of Psychology Edited by Claude E. Buxton Department of Psychology Yale University New Haven, Connecticut 1985 ACADEMIC PRESS, INC. (Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Publishers) Orlando San Diego New York London Toronto Montreal Sydney Tokyo Passages from the following are reprinted by permission of the publishers: Newell, Α., Duncker on Thinking, in S. Koch & D. Leary (Eds.), A Century of Psychology as Science. Copyright 1985 by McGraw-Hill. Neisser, U., Cognitive Psychology. © 1967 by Prentice-Hall. COPYRIGHT © 1985 BY ACADEMIC PRESS, INC. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. NO PART OF THIS PUBLICATION MAY BE REPRODUCED OR TRANSMITTED IN ANY FORM OR BY ANY MEANS, ELECTRONIC OR MECHANICAL, INCLUDING PHOTOCOPY, RECORDING, OR ANY INFORMATION STORAGE AND RETRIEVAL SYSTEM, WITHOUT PERMISSION IN WRITING FROM THE PUBLISHER. ACADEMIC PRESS, INC. Orlando, Florida 32887 United Kingdom Edition published by ACADEMIC PRESS INC. (LONDON) LTD. 24-28 Oval Road, London NW1 7DX LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOGING IN PUBLICATION DATA Main entry under title: Points of view in the modern history of psychology. Includes indexes. 1. Psychology— History. I. Buxton, Claude E. BF81.P57 1985 150\9 85-4010 ISBN 0-12-148510-2 (alk. paper) PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 85 86 87 88 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contributors Numbers in parentheses indicate the pages on which the authors' contributions begin. Mitchell G. Ash (295), Department of History, University of Iowa, Iowa City, Iowa 52242 William Bevan (259), John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation, Chicago, Illinois 60603 Arthur L. Blumenthal (19, 51), Department of Psychology, University of Massachusetts at Boston, Boston, Massachusetts 02125 Claude E.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Avenarius’ “Kritik Der Reinen Erfahrung” (Critique of Pure Experience): an English Summary
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 20 September 2018 doi:10.20944/preprints201809.0403.v1 RICHARD AVENARIUS’ “KRITIK DER REINEN ERFAHRUNG” (CRITIQUE OF PURE EXPERIENCE): AN ENGLISH SUMMARY Arturo Tozzi Center for Nonlinear Science, Department of Physics, University of North Texas, Denton, Texas 76203, USA Computational Intelligence Laboratory, University of Manitoba, Winnipeg, Canada ASL Napoli 2 Nord, Distretto 45, Caivano, Naples, Italy E-mail address: [email protected] We provide the first English translation of Richard Avenarius’ masterpiece, the “Kritik der Reinen Erfahrung” (1888-1890), to give the possibility to the (almost) unaware English speakers to appreciate such a neglected and innovative philosopher and his still topical epistemology. KEYWORDS: philosophy; epistemology; empirio-criticism; neuroscience; brain INTRODUCTION The French-Swiss Professor in inductive philosophy Richard Avenarius (1843-1896), father of empirio-criticism together with Ernst Mach, is one of the most underrated and misunderstood philosophers ever. It mostly depends upon his terminology, which displays an insurmountable difficulty (Russo Krauss, 2015). However, influenced by the most innovative proposals of his times of transition between the Idealistic/Rationalist legacies and the new Materialistic/Scientific interpretation of reality – i.e, by cultural evolutionism, linguistics, biomechanics, entropy/energy and, above all, by the newborn experimental psychology -, Richard Avenarius produced a complete system of philosophy
    [Show full text]
  • Physics and the Philosophy of Science at the Turn of the Twentieth Century
    Physics and the Philosophy of Science at the Turn of the Twentieth Century (Forthcoming in the Enciclopedia Italiana di Storia della Scienza under the title, “Fisica e Filosofia della Scienza all’Alba del XX Secolo”) I believe that philosophy can be helped to its feet again only if it devotes itself seriously and fervently to investigations of cognitive processes and the methods of science. There it has a real and legitimate task . Philosophy has obviously come to a standstill because it . still has taken no new life from the vigorous development of the natural sciences. — Hermann von Helmholtz to Adolf Fick, ca. 1875 (as quoted in Koenigsberger 1902–1903, 243) Introduction: Disciplinary Symbiosis Theoretical physics and the philosophy of science are among the most important fields of research in the twentieth century, this as gauged both by their prominence within their respective disciplines and by their broader social and intellectual impact. Yet in 1850 neither field, as we know it today, would have been recognized in the academy or elsewhere as constituting an autonomous mode of inquiry with associated institutional structures. With hindsight, each might be glimpsed in germ. Some would read Hermann von Helmholtz’s 1847 lecture, Über die Erhaltung der Kraft (Helmholtz 1848) as marking the advent of the search for generalizable explanatory structures whose deployment is a distinguishing mark of theoretical physics. Some would read Auguste Comte’s Cours de philosophie positive (1830–1842) or William Whewell’s The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1840) as inaugurating the systematic study of those general questions about scientific method, the nature and limits of scientific knowledge, and the structure and interpretation of scientific theories whose focal significance later defined the field in the form made famous by the members of the Vienna Circle.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychologism: a Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge/Martin Kusch
    PSYCHOLOGISM For most of this century, Western philosophy has been resolutely antinaturalist, and until recently the sharp distinction between the empirical sciences and philosophy seemed almost self-evident: the questions of why they should be separate, and of how they came to be separate, were never asked. These questions are at the heart of Martin Kusch’s groundbreaking study. Antinaturalism rose to dominance in the debate on psychologism among German academic philosophers at the turn of the century. Psychologism, according to received opinion, was decisively refuted by Frege and Husserl. Kusch therefore examines their arguments and, crucially, relates them to the context that shaped that debate and gave those arguments their persuasive force. Drawing on perspectives pioneered by the sociology of scientific knowledge, he reconstructs the dynamics of the psychologism debate; he uncovers its causes and weighs the factors that determined its outcome. What emerges is the fascinating picture of a struggle, between ‘pure’ philosophy and the newly emerging experimental psychology, for academic status, social influence and institutional power. The triumph of antinaturalism, far from being the only logical conclusion, was dependent on historical contingency. Introducing forms of analysis new to the history of philosophy, Psychologism will make fascinating reading for lecturers and students of philosophy, psychology, sociology and cognitive science; it will also stimulate renewed debate on the prospects of antinaturalism at the close of this century. Martin Kusch is Lecturer at the Science Studies Unit of the University of Edinburgh. He is the author of Language as Calculus vs. Language as Universal Medium (1989), and Foucault’s Strata and Fields (1991).
    [Show full text]
  • Avenarius1 Philosophy of Pure Experience (I.)
    II.—AVENARIUS1 PHILOSOPHY OF PURE EXPERIENCE (I.). BY NOBMAN SMITH. Downloaded from AVENABIUB propounds his philosophy from a standpoint whose originality borders on paradox. While all previous philosophers have regarded experience as awaiting interpre- tation through metaphysical conceptions, Avenarius holds pure experience to be self-intelligible, and the existing meta- http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/ physical theories to be the only facts that call for philosoph- ical explanation. Sometimes he describes his philosophy as the philosophy of pure experience, and sometimes as ' em- piriocriticism'. The former title refers to its content, the latter to its method. He claims that, as regards method, it combines and transcends the philosophies of Hume and Kant. The resulting system is as original in its positive teaching as it is novel in orientation. For though in certain aspects it is closely akin to the metaphysical idealism of Spinoza and Hegel, and recently in this country has been at New York University on May 10, 2015 employed as a buttress to the Bradleian philosophy, its most competent critic has described it as the latest, and, in the present state of knowledge, the only tenable form of materialism.1 A system so strongly affiliated is, even apart from its intrinsic merits, sufficiently remarkable to claim attention. In this article I shall state and criticise the main principles of Avenarius' philosophy. But in so doing I shall consider them only from the pomt of view of the problem of knowledge, and as leading up to the statement of his theory of the introjectionist argument. That theory, which has been adopted by several English writers, I reserve for detailed criticism in a second article.3 1 Wundt: " Ueber naiven and kritischen Realismus " in Philoaopkitche Btudi*n,voL xiii, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology and Philosophy
    Zurich Open Repository and Archive University of Zurich Main Library Strickhofstrasse 39 CH-8057 Zurich www.zora.uzh.ch Year: 1897 I.—Richard Avenarius and his general theory of knowledge, empirioicriticsm Carstanjen, Friedrich DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/vi.4.449 Posted at the Zurich Open Repository and Archive, University of Zurich ZORA URL: https://doi.org/10.5167/uzh-154137 Journal Article Published Version Originally published at: Carstanjen, Friedrich (1897). I.—Richard Avenarius and his general theory of knowledge, empirioicrit- icsm. Mind, VI(4):449-475. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/vi.4.449 MIND A QUARTERLY REVIEW OF PSYCHOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. -3se- I.—RICHARD AVENARIUS AND HIS GENERAL THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE, EMPIRIOCRITICISM. BY DB. FBIEDBICH CABSTANJEN, Zurich University. {Translated by H. BOSANQUET.)1 WHEN Kichard Avenarius, Professor of Philosophy at the University, died at Zurich on 18th August, 1896, only a very small circle of philosophers and pupils knew what a powerful mind had been snatched from amongst them; for he was a man whose unique thought was unappreciated by his contemporaries solely because it was unique, and diverged too much from what was previously familiar. Concerning the life of this philosopher I will merely state briefly that he was born at Paris, 19th November, 1843, that he first devoted himself (by his father's wish) to the book trade, but afterwards studied—for the most part philosophy —at Zurich, Berlin, and Leipzig ; in 1876 he attached him- self to the University of Leipzig, and in 1877 was called as Professor of Philosophy to Zurich.
    [Show full text]
  • Brzozowski and the Italians
    Brzozowski and the Italians Joanna Orska Brzozowski’s preface to his Idee (Ideas) is a case unique in its kind, altogether contrary to the rationalist canon of modern science. He certainly was not the first thinker who recognized that a philosophical ‘opus’ is first of all a process as well as an active method of development and construction—the creation of the phi- losopher’s own consciousness. However, it is here as well that the philosopher begins his life-long summa by way of personal confidences that take the form of an intellectual diary. Not only does Brzozowski not give an account of the chapters that make up his philosophical book, he likewise provides no alternative systematic overview of its contents. The author opens his text in a most peculiar way, compromising so to say the objectivity of his own research presented here as a journey through life: “an odyssey across the seas of the human spirit and life which in our time is the only possible epic” (odyseja po morzach ducha i życia ludzkiego, która jest jedynym możliwym eposem naszego czasu).1 For example: Krytyka moja była buntem nie posiadającym lub poszukującym dla siebie organów myśli, i w ich braku walczyła takimi, na których ciążyła jeszcze przynależność do bezhistorycz- nego, abstrakcyjnego stanowiska myślowego, tego właśnie stanowiska, z którym podjąłem walkę.2 My critique was a revolt neither possessing nor seeking to find organs of thinking, and in their absence it was a struggle against those afflicted by adherence to an ahistorical, ab- stract form of thinking, the form precisely that I set out to oppose.
    [Show full text]
  • Make a Distinction Between 'Positivism' and 'Post Positivism. 10
    BY Dr. ALEYA MOUSAMI SULTANA DEPT. OF POLITICAL SCIENCE, CPBU. SECOND SEMESTER COURSE 203 INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS- THEORIES AND PROBLEMS UNIT - III Make a distinction between ‘positivism’ and ‘post positivism. 10 Among all theoretical traditions which International Relations have seen emerging, the one that has invariably been regarded as canonical is associated with the term “positivism”. The term ‘positivism’ appears to have been first used in the 1820s, in French, most influentially by Auguste Comte as a label for his ‘positive philosophy’ though many of the ideas to which it referred have a longer history. Comte’s philosophy was intended to exemplify and promote the scientific mode of thought which he believed was becoming dominant, superseding the theological and metaphysical forms that had prevailed in earlier periods of European history. Comte’s ideas had great influence on social science in the nineteenth and into the twentieth century, directly as well as indirectly through the work of others, such as Mill and Durkheim. It must be understood that it is not simple to define “positivism”, not even if we go back to the decades of turmoil which are extended from mid-XVII Century to the beginnings of this century. Leaving aside its historical circumstances which, as always, are very important, “positivism” became a cornucopia for positions so diverging that it is not much to say that it corresponds to our “controversy on the universals”, the “gray cat” of contemporary philosophy. We may consider as vaguely positivists all theories
    [Show full text]
  • The New Sociology of Scotland 1St Edition Ebook, Epub
    THE NEW SOCIOLOGY OF SCOTLAND 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK David McCrone | 9781473987814 | | | | | The New Sociology of Scotland 1st edition PDF Book Comte believed a positivist stage would mark the final era, after conjectural theological and metaphysical phases, in the progression of human understanding. Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guild-master and journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary re-constitution of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes. For Isaiah Berlin , even though Marx did not consider himself to be a sociologist, he may be regarded as the "true father" of modern sociology, "in so far as anyone can claim the title. Herbert Spencer — was one of the most popular and influential 19th-century sociologists. The primary concern of feminist theory is the patriarchy and the systematic oppression of women apparent in many societies, both at the level of small-scale interaction and in terms of the broader social structure. Durkheim's view of sociology as the study of externally defined social facts was redirected towards literature by Robert Escarpit. Max Weber argued that sociology may be loosely described as a science as it is able to identify causal relationships of human " social action "—especially among " ideal types ", or hypothetical simplifications of complex social phenomena. Sociological reasoning predates the foundation of the discipline itself. A Dictionary of Sociology 3rd ed. Identity and Control. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Retrieved 12 September Sociology of literature, film, and art is a subset of the sociology of culture.
    [Show full text]