Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation SPEECH AND THEOLOGY God is Infinite, but language finite; thus speech would seem to condemn him to finitude. In speaking of God, would the theologian violate divine transcendence by reducing God to immanence, or choose, rather, to remain silent? At stake in this argument is a core problem of the conditions of divine revelation. How, in terms of language and the limitations of human understanding, can transcendence ever be made known? Does its very appearance not undermine its transcendence, its condition of unknowability? Speech and Theology: Language and the Logic of Incarnation posits that the paradigm for the encounter between the material and the divine, or the immanent and transcen- dent, is found in the Incarnation: God’s voluntary self-immersion in the human world as an expression of his love for his creation. By this key act of grace, hinged upon Christ’s condescension to human finitude, philosophy acquires the means not simply to speak of perfection, which is to speak theologically, but to bridge the gap between word and thing in a general sense. Responding to the works of Augustine, Husserl, and Heidegger through the lens of contemporary French phenomenolo- gists such as Derrida, Levinas, and Marion, Speech and Theology reconsiders the perennial theological challenge of speaking of God, as traditionally reflected by devotional poles of predication and silence and of confession and praise. In the process, it passionately asserts two central truths: first, that God demands the effort of speech – that we are compelled to speak of God because he, in the Incarnation, has first spoken – and, consequently, that theology cannot properly choose silence in the pursuit of worship in view of its urgent need of words to make God visible. From the revolutionary assertion that God’s incarnation is the condition of possibility not only for theological language but for language generally, James K. A. Smith creates a new Christian phenomenology where divine love ultimately functions as the ground for an affirmation of embodiment and materiality, and in which Christ’s bodily endowment of worldly signs with the full reality of his own infinitude signals the basis for an entirely new theology of the arts. James K. A. Smith is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Calvin College in Grand Rapids, MI, and the author of The Fall of Interpretation: Philosophical Foundations for a Creational Hermeneutic (2000). RADICAL ORTHODOXY SERIES Edited by John Milbank, Catherine Pickstock and Graham Ward Radical orthodoxy combines a sophisticated understanding of contemporary thought, modern and postmodern, with a theological perspective that looks back to the origins of the Church. It is the most talked-about development in contemporary theology. RADICAL ORTHODOXY edited by John Milbank, Catherine Pickstock and Graham Ward DIVINE ECONOMY D. Stephen Long TRUTH IN AQUINAS John Milbank and Catherine Pickstock CITIES OF GOD Graham Ward LIBERATION THEOLOGY AFTER THE END OF HISTORY The refusal to cease suffering Daniel M. Bell, Jr. GENEALOGY OF NIHILISM Conor Cunningham SPEECH AND THEOLOGY Language and the logic of incarnation James K. A. Smith SPEECH AND THEOLOGY Language and the logic of incarnation James K. A. Smith London and New York First published 2002 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © 2002 James K. A. Smith All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN 0-203-99527-9 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-415-27695-0 (hbk) ISBN 0-415-27696-9 (pbk) For Mom, who now knows that of which I speak CONTENTS Acknowledgements ix Abbreviations xi PART ONE Horizons 1 1 Introduction: how to avoid not speaking 3 The violence of concepts and the possibility of theology 3 Method and the question of justice 4 Phenomenology’s other: the French challenge to phenomenology 7 Towards a new phenomenology 9 2 Phenomenology and transcendence: genealogy of a challenge 16 Transcendence in early phenomenology 16 Three phenomenological reductions: an heuristic 16 First reduction: the possibility of transcendent knowledge in Husserl 20 Second reduction: Heidegger’s critique of Husserl 24 The violence of immanence: the French critique 26 A third reduction to unconditioned givenness 26 The same and the other: Levinas 27 The “Saturated Phenomenon”: Marion’s critique of Husserl 32 Incommensurability and transcendence: the violence of the concept 42 A formalization of the question 42 Phenomenology as respect: Derrida 44 Thinking the concept otherwise: towards an incarnational phenomenology 50 PART TWO Retrieval 65 3 Heidegger’s “new” phenomenology 67 Towards a new phenomenology with the young Heidegger 67 vii CONTENTS Taking Husserl at his word: a phenomenology of the natural attitude 70 Horizons: Husserl’s phenomenological worlds 70 Critique: Heidegger’s factical world 75 Finding words for facticity: formal indication as a “grammar” 82 “Words are lacking”: the demand for new “concepts” 82 A factical grammar: the logic of formal indications 86 Religious experience, the religious phenomenon, and a phenomenology of religion 94 The return of the concept: Destrukting Being and Time 102 4 Praise and confession: how (not) to speak in Augustine 114 Lost for words?: the challenge of speaking for Augustine 114 Between predication and silence: how (not) to speak of God 116 Words and things: the incommensurability of signa and res 116 Use, enjoyment, and reference: Augustine’s phenomenology of idolatry 120 How (not) to speak of God: the icon of praise 127 How (not) to tell a secret: interiority and the strategy of “confession” 134 Interior secrets: on not knowing who we are 134 Silence and secrets: interiority and the problem of communication 136 Confession: the strategy of the interior self 140 PART THREE Trajectories 151 5 Incarnational logic: on God’s refusal to avoid speaking 153 The problem of theology 153 On (not) knowing the Wholly Other: a critique of revelation in Levinas and Marion 157 The appearance of the paradox: revelation in Kierkegaard 161 Analogy and respect: retrieving analogy in a French context 163 The specter of Platonism: reconsidering participation and incarnation 170 Index 183 viii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Augustine would often quote the Pauline maxim, “What do we have that we have not received?” (1 Cor. 4:7). That never becomes more apparent than in the completion of a work such as this in which I have incurred many debts, of which I can mention only a few here. First, I am grateful to Jack Caputo, for his shepherding hand and encouragement throughout these early stages of my career. His own groundbreaking work has cleared a path which has made this study possible, and his insights have provided important directions for not only this work, but many of my labors. I am also thankful that I can count Jack a friend in addition to a mentor. James McCartney and Anthony Godzieba both read the manuscript in its entirety and offered both helpful criticisms and encouraging support. Robert Dodaro and Tom Martin (re)introduced me to Augustine at a critical phase of my research, for which I am grateful. Jim Olthuis continues to be a treasured mentor and important dialogue partner for me, and Merold Westphal has been a generous source of support, exemplifying the model of a Christian scholar. And John Milbank and Graham Ward, whose work has provoked my own, have provided both encouragement and critical engagement which, I hope, have improved the book. My colleagues and students at Loyola Marymount University aided me in honing these ideas and provided a receptive environment for my work. Thanks especially to Bil Van Otterloo and Shannon Nason for their help with the manuscript in its various stages. I would also like to thank Kenyon Chan, Dean of the Bellarmine College of Liberal Arts, and Joseph Jabbra, Academic Vice President, for their tangible support of my research, including a Summer Research Grant which enabled me to complete the book. I would also like to thank my new colleagues at Calvin College for welcoming me into the rich heritage of philosophy at Calvin – the heritage which spawned this book. The bulk of this manuscript was penned during our time in the Philadelphia area, where we were blessed to be part of a wonderful church community at Cornerstone Christian Fellowship. I would especially like to thank Pastor Ron Billings for his warm encouragement and persistent interest in my work. David and Stephanie Burton, our Youth Pastor and Music Director, have also been sources of inspiration ix ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS and have become cherished friends for us. Our Friday nights together with the “Magnificent Seven” kept me – and Deanna – sane and grounded. My family, my parents and in-laws, have all been a part of this process and project for a number of years. And I couldn’t have done it without them. The book is dedicated to my mother, to whom I owe so much, especially a confidence born of her praise and encouragement. But those who have borne the heaviest load throughout this project have been my own family: my wife, Deanna, and the kids, Grayson, Coleson, Madison, and Jackson.
Recommended publications
  • Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last Updated : Apr
    - Institute for scientific and technical information - Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Vocabulary of PHILOSOPHY Version 1.1 (Last updated : Apr. 05, 2018) This resource contains 4435 entries grouped into 89 collections. Controlled vocabulary used for indexing bibliographical records for the "Philosophy" FRANCIS database (1972-2015, http://pascal-francis.inist.fr/ ). This vocabulary is browsable online at: https://www.loterre.fr Legend • Syn: Synonym. • →: Corresponding Preferred Term. • FR: French Preferred Term. • DE: German Preferred Term. • SC: Semantic Category. • DO: Domain. • URI: Concept's URI (link to the online view). This resource is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license: LIST OF ENTRIES List of entries English French Page • 10th century Xe siècle 176 • 11th - 13th centuries XIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 11th century XIe siècle 176 • 12th -13th centuries XIIe - XIIIe siècles 176 • 12th century XIIe siècle 176 • 13th - 14th centuries XIIIe - XIVe siècles 176 • 13th - 15th centuries XIIIe - XVe siècles 176 • 13th century XIIIe siècle 176 • 14th - 15th centuries XIVe - XVe siècles 176 • 14th - 16th centuries XIVe - XVIe siècles 176 • 14th - 17th centuries XIVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 14th century XIVe siècle 176 • 15th - 17th centuries XVe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 15th century XVe siècle 176 • 1656-1658 1656-1658 176 • 16th - 17th centuries XVIe - XVIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 18th centuries XVIe - XVIIIe siècles 176 • 16th - 20th centuries XVIe - XXe siècles 176 • 16th century XVIe siècle 176 • 1735-1985 1735-1985
    [Show full text]
  • 19 Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX a Support for the So-Called Second Oldest Or 'Mediaeval' Interpre
    Another Interpretation of Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX A support for the so-called second oldest or 'mediaeval' interpretation JOB VAN ECK Controversies regarding propositions about the future, occasioned by Aristotle's De Interpretatione IX have occurred throughout the history of logic from Antiquity to the 20th century, especially in the Middle Ages. The question under discussion is: must some such propositions be denied a truth value in order to escape determinism? Or does the law of bivalence also hold for future contingency propositions? And what is Aristotle's position in De Interpretatione IX? Does he say that bivalence implies determinism and thus abandons universal bivalence (this is called the oldest, or traditional, interpretation), or does he reconcile bivalence with indeterminism (the so-called second oldest in- terpretation). Boethius, in his two commentaries on De Interpretatione, shows himself a representantive of the second oldest interpretation. His main thesis is that according to Aristotle it is necessary for a future con- tingency proposition and its negation that one is true and the other false, but not definitely true, nor definitely false. In a recent article Pro- fessor Norman Kretzmann stressed the influence this point of view of Boethius has had on the subsequent discussion' . The second oldest interpretation became so prominent among mediaeval philosophers that some call it the mediaeval interpretation. In modern times most authors reject this interpretation, partly because the phrase "definitely true", which is at the heart of it, is rather obscure and its Greek analogue alêthes aphorismends does not oc- cur in De Interpretatione IX at all.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Verbal Communication: the First Chapters of De Interpretatione
    EJPC 7 (2) pp. 239–253 Intellect Limited 2016 Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication Volume 7 Number 2 © 2016 Intellect Ltd Critical Review. English language. doi: 10.1386/ejpc.7.2.239_3 CRITICAL REVIEW ANITA KASABOVA Sofia University VLADIMIR MARINOV New Bulgarian University Aristotle on verbal communication: The first chapters of De Interpretatione ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This article deals with the communicational aspects of Aristotle’s theory of significa- Aristotle tion as laid out in the initial chapters of the De Interpretatione (Int.).1 We begin De Interpretatione by outlining the reception and main interpretations of the chapters under discussion, verbal communication rather siding with the linguistic strand. We then argue that the first four chap- signification ters present an account of verbal communication, in which words signify things via linguistic expressions thoughts. We show how Aristotle determines voice as a conventional and hence acci- convention dental medium of signification: words as ‘spoken sounds’ are tokens of thoughts, language use which in turn are signs or natural likenesses of things. We argue that, in this way, 1. We follow the standard linguistic expressions may both signify thoughts and refer to things. This double edition of the Greek account of signification also explains the variety of ontological, logical and psycho- text of Int. by Minio- logical interpretations of the initial chapters of Int. Paluello (1949: 47–72), unless otherwise stated. All references to Aristotle’s works 239 11_EJPC 7.2_Critical review article_239-253.indd 239 11/22/16 1:55 PM Anita Kasabova and Vladimir Marinov follow the citation 1.
    [Show full text]
  • From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category Is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected]
    REDESCRIPTIONS Sandford, Stella. 2019. “From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”?” Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory 22(1): 4–17. DOI: https://doi.org/10.33134/rds.314 RESEARCH From Aristotle to Contemporary Biological Classification: What Kind of Category is “Sex”? Stella Sandford Kingston University London, UK [email protected] This paper examines the nature of the categories of ‘male’ and ‘female’ as ­classificatory­groupings,­via­an­examination­of­this­question­in­Aristotle’s­zoology­ and­metaphysics.­Tracing­the­use­of­Aristotle’s­logical­categories­of­‘genus’­and­ ‘species’­in­his­zoological­works­and­contrasting­this­with­the­use­of­the­terms­ in­contemporary­taxonomy,­the­paper­demonstrates­that­‘male’­and­‘female’­are,­ in­a­significant­sense,­unclassifiable.­Although­Aristotle­has­no­generic­concept­of­ ‘sex’­at­his­disposal,­the­paper­shows­how­many­English­translations­of­his­works­ introduce­‘sex’­as­if­in­answer­to­the­question­of­the­nature­of­the­categories­of­ male­and­female.­The­paper­then­argues­that­the­generic­concept­of­sex­covers­ over­the­problem­of­the­classification­of­male­and­female­in­both­Aristotle­and­ contemporary­biology­(including­botany,­mycology­and­bacteriology),­by­introduc- ing­a­classificatory­genus­(‘sex’)­that­does­not­in­fact­explain­anything­but­rather­ (in­its­trans-species­generality)­needs­explaining. Keywords:­Sex;­male/female;­Aristotle;­biology;­taxonomy;­classification All living organisms that have been scientifically recorded or studied are named according to the relevant international code for nomenclature. Naming and denoting a taxonomical clas- sification are two sides of the same coin.
    [Show full text]
  • CBC IDEAS Sales Catalog (AZ Listing by Episode Title. Prices Include
    CBC IDEAS Sales Catalog (A-Z listing by episode title. Prices include taxes and shipping within Canada) Catalog is updated at the end of each month. For current month’s listings, please visit: http://www.cbc.ca/ideas/schedule/ Transcript = readable, printed transcript CD = titles are available on CD, with some exceptions due to copyright = book 104 Pall Mall (2011) CD $18 foremost public intellectuals, Jean The Academic-Industrial Ever since it was founded in 1836, Bethke Elshtain is the Laura Complex London's exclusive Reform Club Spelman Rockefeller Professor of (1982) Transcript $14.00, 2 has been a place where Social and Political Ethics, Divinity hours progressive people meet to School, The University of Chicago. Industries fund academic research discuss radical politics. There's In addition to her many award- and professors develop sideline also a considerable Canadian winning books, Professor Elshtain businesses. This blurring of the connection. IDEAS host Paul writes and lectures widely on dividing line between universities Kennedy takes a guided tour. themes of democracy, ethical and the real world has important dilemmas, religion and politics and implications. Jill Eisen, producer. 1893 and the Idea of Frontier international relations. The 2013 (1993) $14.00, 2 hours Milton K. Wong Lecture is Acadian Women One hundred years ago, the presented by the Laurier (1988) Transcript $14.00, 2 historian Frederick Jackson Turner Institution, UBC Continuing hours declared that the closing of the Studies and the Iona Pacific Inter- Acadians are among the least- frontier meant the end of an era for religious Centre in partnership with known of Canadians.
    [Show full text]
  • 13. Control the Argument
    13. Control the Argument ̆ HOMER SIMPSON’S CANONS OF LOGIC Logos, inside out A fool may talk, but a wise man speaks. —ben jonson nough with the care and feeding of your audience. You made it think Eyou’re a Boy Scout, insinuated yourself into its mood, put it in an in- genuous state, offered it the rich rewards of its own advantage, and plucked the beliefs and desires from its mind. Now let’s use that audience to your own advantage. It’s time to apply some logos and win our own goals. The commonplace gives us our starting point. Homer Simpson employs a pair of them—the value of safe streets and his audience’s presumed affec- tion for the weak and nerdy—in a speech he gives to a group of Australians. ̈ Persuasion Alert In America we stopped using corporal punishment I bring in Homer and things have never been better. The streets are Simpson so often because The safe. Old people strut confidently through the darkest Simpsons satirizes alleys. And the weak and nerdy are admired for their America’s social fallacies; its humor computer programming abilities. So, like us, let your relies on twists of children run wild and free, because as the saying logic. You couldn’t find a better set of goes, “Let your children run wild and free.” examples in Plato. The passage is doubly notable, for its logical use of commonplaces and its bold unconcern for the facts. If you want your streets to be safe and your nerds to be cherished, Homer says, don’t hit your kids.
    [Show full text]
  • HUMAN CLONING Papers from a Church Consultation
    HUMAN CLONING Papers From a Church Consultation Evangelical Lutheran Church in America October 13-15, 2000 Chicago, Illinois Roger A. Willer, editor HUMAN CLONING Papers From a Church Consultation Roger A. Willer, editor Copyright © 2001 Evangelical Lutheran Church in America. Produced by the Department for Studies of the Division for Church in Society, 8765 W. Higgins Rd., Chicago, Illinois, 60631-4190. Permission is granted to reproduce this document as needed provided each copy carries the copyright notice printed above. Scripture quotations from the New Standard Revised Version of the Bible are copyright © 1989 by the Division of Christian Education of the National Council of Churches of Christ in the United States of America and are used by permission. Cover image © copyright 1999 PhotoDisc, Inc. The figure found on page nine is adapted from the National Institute of Health, Stem Cells: A Primer at <www.nih.gov/ news/stemcell/primer.htm>. ISBN 6-0001-3165-8. Distributed on behalf of the Division for Church in Society of the Evangelical Lutheran Church in America by Augsburg Fortress, Publishers. Augsburg Fortress order code 69-1550. This publication may be found online in its entirety as a downloadable PDF (portable document file) at <www.elca.org/ dcs/humancloning.html>. Printed on recycled paper with soy-based inks. Contents Contributors 3 Preface 4 Introduction 5 Section One, The Science and the Public Debate Kevin Fitzgerald Cloning: Can it be Good for Us? 8 Margaret R. McLean Table Talk and Public Policy Formation in the Clone Age 14 Richard Perry Broadening the Churchs Conversation 23 Section Two, Theological Resources Philip Hefner Cloning: The Destiny and Dangers of Being Human 27 Richard C.
    [Show full text]
  • AUGUSTINE During the Ensuing Centuries, Aristotle's De Interpretatione Became the Subject of Frequent Commentary.1 Ammonius
    CHAPTER TWO AUGUSTINE During the ensuing centuries, Aristotle's De interpretatione became the subject of frequent commentary.1 Ammonius and Boethius report that there had already been commentaries written by Aspasius (first century), Herminus and Alexander of Aphrodisias (second century), Porphyry (third century), Iamblichus (fourth century), and Syrianus of Athens (fifth century); Philoponus also commented on the work (sixth century), and Theophrastus, Aristotle's immediate successor at the Lyceum, may have also discussed it in one of his treatises. Around 363, early in the lifetime of Augustine, Marius Victorinus translated De interpretatione into Latin. There is, however, no indication that Augustine ever read the work. He never cites it and his own discussion of the problem of foreknowledge and future contingents reflects no contact with Aristotle's writing, but seems to have been stimulated principally by Cicero's De fato.2 This is not surprising, for in the time following Aristotle's death the purely logical issues of antecedent truth and semantic necessity tended to be eclipsed by questions concerning freedom of the will and causal determinacy.3 This concern manifests itself in Augustine's own discussions of the prob­ lem of fatalism. TURN TO THEOLOGICAL FATALISM What is of special interest to us, however, is that under the influence of Neo-platonism and Christianity, the problem of fatalism has taken on a new guise: the problem of theological fatalism. Well before the time of Ammonius (d. 241-42) the relation of God's foreknowledge to human freedom was an oft-discussed question.4 Celsus in the second century, for example, had objected to Christianity on the basis of the fatalistic conse­ quences of Christ's predictions of his betrayal.5 Origen defended the compatibility of foreknowledge and human freedom against Celsus's attack, charging that his opponent erred in thinking foreknowledge to be the cause of an event, rather than the reverse.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Aristotelian Method and Aristotelian
    1 The Aristotelian Method and Aristotelian Metaphysics TUOMAS E. TAHKO (www.ttahko.net) Published in Patricia Hanna (Ed.), An Anthology of Philosophical Studies (Athens: ATINER), pp. 53-63, 2008. ABSTRACT In this paper I examine what exactly is ‘Aristotelian metaphysics’. My inquiry into Aristotelian metaphysics should not be understood to be so much con- cerned with the details of Aristotle's metaphysics. I am are rather concerned with his methodology of metaphysics, although a lot of the details of his meta- physics survive in contemporary discussion as well. This warrants an investigation into the methodological aspects of Aristotle's metaphysics. The key works that we will be looking at are his Physics, Meta- physics, Categories and De Interpretatione. Perhaps the most crucial features of the Aristotelian method of philosophising are the relationship between sci- ence and metaphysics, and his defence of the principle of non-contradiction (PNC). For Aristotle, natural science is the second philosophy, but this is so only because there is something more fundamental in the world, something that natural science – a science of movement – cannot study. Furthermore, Aristotle demonstrates that metaphysics enters the picture at a fundamental level, as he argues that PNC is a metaphysical rather than a logical principle. The upshot of all this is that the Aristotelian method and his metaphysics are not threatened by modern science, quite the opposite. Moreover, we have in our hands a methodology which is very rigorous indeed and worthwhile for any metaphysician to have a closer look at. 2 My conception of metaphysics is what could be called ‘Aristotelian’, as op- posed to Kantian.
    [Show full text]
  • Genealogy of Nihilism: Philosophies of Nothing and the Difference Of
    GENEALOGY OF NIHILISM Nihilism is the logic of nothing as something, which claims that Nothing Is. Its unmaking of things, and its forming of formless things, strain the fundamental terms of existence: what it is to be, to know, to be known. But nihilism, the antithesis of God, is also like theology. Where nihilism creates nothingness, condenses it to substance, God also makes nothingness creative. Negotiating the borders of spirit and substance, theology can ask the questions of nihilism that other disciplines do not ask: Where is it? What is it made of? Why is it so destructive? How can it be made holy, or overcome? Genealogy of Nihilism rereads Western history in the light of nihilistic logic, which pervades two millennia of Western thought and is coming to fruition in our present age in a virulently dangerous manner. From Parmenides to Alain Badiou, via Plotinus, Avicenna, Duns Scotus, Ockham, Descartes, Spinoza, Kant, Hegel, Heidegger, Sartre, Lacan, Deleuze and Derrida, a genealogy of nothingness can be witnessed in development, with devastating consequences for the way we live. As a dualistic logic, nihilism has come to ground existence not in life but in the absences beyond it. We who are, are no longer the living, but rather the living dead; in the death-wielding modern approach to knowledge, we are all reduced to cadavers. The Trinitarian theology of Genealogy of Nihilism offers a counterargument that is sustained by nihilism even as it defeats it. In Christ’s ontological synthesis of divine spirit and incarnation, and in the miraculous logic of the resurrection, theology reunites presence with absence, non-being with being.
    [Show full text]
  • The Enthymeme and the Rational Judge
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 101 398 CS 500 960 AUTHOR Perkins, Terry M. TITLE The Enthymeme and the Rational. Judge. PUB DATE Jun 74 NOTE 23p.; Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Western Speech Communication Association (Newport Beach, California, November 1974) EbiS PRICE MF-$0.76 HC-$1.58 PLUS POSTAGE DESCRIPTORS *Cognitive Processes; Educational Research; Higher Education; *Logic; *Logical Thinking; Productive Thinking; *Rhetoric; Thought Processes IDENTIFIERS *Enthymeme ABSTRACT This paper attempts to show that the significant difference between the enthymeme and the dialectic syllogism rests on the similarity of purpose of both dialectic and rhetoric, and on the differences in the respondents to which they address themselves. To support this thesis, the author reviews several contemporary approaches which have dealt with the enthymeme and develops an analysis of the essential requirements of dialectic and rhetoric which affect the characteristics f their respective syllogisms. The author predicts four essential characteristics of the enthymeme based on an assumption made by Aristotle that therhetorical respondent, while untrained in the assessment of arguments, still has an innate understanding and preference for logical reasoning. The four characteristics area(1) it must be short, simple, and to the point; (2) to accomplish this, the rhetorician must make use of common knowledge and draw obvious conclusions;(3) since one is arguing from propositions with which the auditor is already familiar, the enthymeme may be stylistically
    [Show full text]
  • Greco-Roman Legal Analysis: the Topics of Invention
    St. John's Law Review Volume 66 Number 1 Volume 66, Winter 1992, Number 1 Article 3 Greco-Roman Legal Analysis: The Topics of Invention Michael Frost Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/lawreview This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in St. John's Law Review by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GRECO-ROMAN LEGAL ANALYSIS: THE TOPICS OF INVENTION MICHAEL FROST* I. INTRODUCTION Despite a wealth of commentary on legal reas6ning and legal logic, modern writers on the subject demonstrate a curious and re- grettable disregard for the close connections between classical Greco-Roman theories of forensic discourse and modern theories of legal reasoning and analysis. Two recent treatises on logic and legal reasoning, Judge Ruggero Aldisert's Logic for Lawyers' and Pro- fessor Steven Burton's An Introduction to Law and Legal Reason- ing,2 are exceptions to this rule. Their treatises fall within a 2,000- year-old tradition of rhetorical analysis and discourse especially designed for lawyers. Beginning with treatises on rhetoric by Aris- totle, Cicero, and Quintilian, philosophers and lawyers have re- peatedly attempted, some more ambitiously than others, to de- scribe and analyze legal reasoning and methodology. Judge Aldisert implicitly acknowledges his participation in this ancient tradition with an epigraph drawn from Cicero's Republic, with his choice of subject matter, and with his use of centuries-old rhetori- cal terminology.3 Professor Burton's approach to legal analysis and argument can also be traced back to ancient rhetorical treatises especially written for the instruction of beginning advocates.
    [Show full text]