Deconstructing Quirky Subjects Ethan Poole University of Massachusetts Amherst [email protected]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Deconstructing Quirky Subjects Ethan Poole University of Massachusetts Amherst Ejpoole@Linguist.Umass.Edu North East Linguistic Society ¦¢ MIT ⋅ ìÕ October óþÕ¦ Deconstructing quirky subjects Ethan Poole University of Massachusetts Amherst [email protected] (Õ) a. Can bind subject-oriented anaphora Main claim Hennii þykir [bróðir sinni ] leiðinlegur DPs exhibit a set of subjecthood properties as a function of how high they her.oZ± thinks brother. her.§u boring raise in the functional sequence. ‘Shei thinks heri brother boring’ [Zaenen et al. ÕÉ¢:¦¢þ] Empirical motivation b. Can be PRO Quirky subjects in Icelandic, German, Hindi, Basque, and Laz show that the Égi vonast til [PROi að vanta ekki peninga ] subjecthood properties exhibited by DPs obey the Quirky Subject Hierarchy: I. hope for PRO.Zhh to lack not money.Zhh binding ≫ PRO ≫ reduced relatives ‘I hope not to lack money’ [Zaenen et al. ÕÉ¢:¦¢¦] Analysis in a nutshell 7 Hindi • Tý is decomposed into two separate heads, Persp(ective)ý to host PRO and Hindi quirky subjects can bind subject-oriented anaphora, but cannot be PRO B(inding)ý to bind anaphora, where fseq = ⟨C ≻ Persp ≻ B ≻ v ≻ V⟩. (e.g. Mohanan ÕÉɦ; Bhatt óþþì): • DPs dier in (i) how high they raise in the functional sequence and (ii) (ó) a. Can bind subject-oriented anaphora whether they can undergo projecting movement from [Spec, PerspP], the Mujhei [apnei sab rishtedar¯ ] pasand hε˜ highest syntactic position, to form a reduced relative. I.oZ± §u..£ all relative. like be.£§«.£ ý ý [NP [PerspP Perspective [BP Binding [ QS ...]]]] ‘I like all my relatives’ [Bhatt óþþì:Õó] b. Cannot be PRO *Ravii [PROi Rina pasand a-n¯ a¯ ] nah˜¯ı Õ Introduction Ravi. PRO.oZ± Rina. like come- u chah-t¯ a.¯ • Quirky (nonnominative) subjects dier across languages in whether they display want-Zf..« the full range of properties exhibited by canonical nominative subjects. To Intended: ‘Ravi doesn’t want to like Rina’ illustrate, consider Icelandic and Hindi quirky subjects. • e consensus in the literature is that quirky subjects in languages like Icelandic 3 Icelandic are “true subjects”, whereas quirky subjects in languages like Hindi are not (e.g. Icelandic quirky subjects are well-known for exhibiting all the properties canon- McFadden óþþ¦; Preminger óþÕÕ, óþÕ¦). ically ascribed to subjects other than bearing nominative case and controlling • e subjecthood status of a quirky subject is determined by a suite of subject- verb agreement, such as binding subject-oriented anaphora and being PRO hood diagnostics, e.g. the diagnostics of Zaenen et al. (ÕÉ¢). (Andrews ÕÉßä; Þráinsson ÕÉßÉ; Zaenen et al. ÕÉ¢; Sigurðsson ÕÉÉ): Õ • However, it is clear that quirky subjects in languages like Hindi are not normal quirky subjects is the result of quirky subjects diering across languages in how obliques. ey possess extra properties that are typical of subjects, but atypical high they raise in the functional sequence. of obliques, such as the ability to bind subject-oriented anaphora. • Structure of this talk • Moreover, given the importance of quirky subjects in our understanding of Õ. I present a suite of crosslinguistic subjecthood diagnostics: binding of subject- the interaction between case, agreement, and movement, we do not want to oriented anaphora, PRO, and reduced relatives. base our theory on something like Icelandic quirky subjects if they might be typologically rare. ó. Applying these diagnostics to quirky subjects in Icelandic, German, Hindi, Basque, and Laz shows that the subjecthood properties exhibited by quirky ⇒ Question subjects constitute an implicational hierarchy, called the Quirky Subject How are subjecthood properties distributed amongst quirky subjects crosslin- Hierarchy (QSH). guistically? For example, one could imagine either of the following distributions: ì. I implement the QSH in the syntax by proposing the Height Conjecture: DPs exhibit subjecthood properties as a function of how high they raise in the functional sequence. ¦. I discuss how the empirical generalisations encoded in the QSH are incom- pÔ patible with the existing views of subjecthood in the literature. pç pò pÔ ó Subjecthood diagnostics • Standard subjecthood diagnostics pò pç e standard suite of subjecthood diagnostics comes from Zaenen et al. (ÕÉ¢) and includes four crosslinguistic tests for subjecthood: Õ. Binding of subject-oriented anaphora • To address this question, I investigated quirky subjects in Icelandic, German, ó. Being PRO Hindi, Basque, and Laz. I used three subjecthood diagnostics: binding of subject-oriented anaphora, being PRO, and undergoing relativisation in reduced ì. Raising-to-object (ECM) relatives. ¦. Conjunction reduction ✳ Quirky Subject Hierarchy • ese diagnostics (or a subset of them) are adopted in the recent literature on e pattern to emerge from the data is that the subjecthood properties crosslin- subjecthood (e.g. Sigurðsson ÕÉÉ, óþþó, óþþ¦; Mohanan ÕÉɦ; Fanselow óþþó; guistically exhibited by quirky subjects obey an implicational hierarchy: Barðdal óþþó; Barðdal & Eyþórsson óþþìa,b, óþþ¢; Bayer óþþ¦; McFadden óþþ¦; Gutiérrez-Bravo óþþä; Rákosi óþþä; Wunderlich óþþÉ; Preminger óþÕÕ, óþÕ¦). (ì) Q¶§í S¶fuh± Hu§Z§hí binding ≫ PRO ≫ reduced relatives • Moreover, following Zaenen et al. (ÕÉ¢), the de facto assumption in the literature is that nominative case and controlling verb agreement are not properties of ⇒ Question that follows subjects. How do we account for this implicational hierarchy? ✳ Answer in this talk A DP exhibits a set of subjecthood properties as a function of how high it raises in the functional sequence. e crosslinguistic variation in the behaviour of ó • Section outline () Arbitrarily-controlled I select three tests to form a revised suite of subjecthood diagnostics: (i) binding a. [ PROarb to hug Fernanda ] is fantastic of subject-oriented anaphora and (ii) being PRO, taken from Zaenen et al. (ÕÉ¢), in addition to (iii) undergoing relativisation in reduced relatives.Ö b. *[ (Fernanda) to hug PROarb ] is fantastic ⇒ erefore, PRO provides a crosslinguistic subjecthood diagnostic: ó.Õ Binding of subject-oriented anaphora (É) PRODZ«±h • Many languages have a special subclass of anaphora whose antecedent must If XP can be PRO, XP is a subject. be the subject, which are called «¶fuh±-§u±uo ZZ£§Z (SOAs). English is not such a language, but Danish is: ó.ì Reduced relatives (¦) Danish at Peteri fortalte Michael j om sig selvi~∗ j • In reduced relative clauses (RRCs), the relativised element can only occur in that Peter told Michael about §u the subject position: ‘that Peteri told Michael j about himself ~∗ ’ [Vikner ÕÉ¢:Õþ] i j (Õþ) a. the Basquei [ ___i giving Stefan the rutabaga ] sig • ere is some variation in whether SOAs need bound locally (e.g. Danish b. *the Germani [ Jon Ander giving ___i the rutabaga ] selv) or nonlocally (e.g. Danish sig), or either (e.g. Finnish itse), but they are crucially always bound by a subject. c. *the rutabagai [ Jon Ander giving Stefan ___i ] ⇒ erefore, SOAs provide a crosslinguistic subjecthood diagnostic: ⇒ erefore, RRCs provide a crosslinguistic subjecthood diagnostic: (¢) Bo DZ«±h (ÕÕ) Ruo¶huo RuZ±êu DZ«±h If XP can bind subject-oriented anaphora, XP is a subject. If XP can be relativised on in reduced relatives, XP is a subject. • Whereas the Binding Diagnostic and the PRO Diagnostic are taken from Zaenen ó.ó PRO et al. (ÕÉ¢) and therefore commonly used in the literature, the Reduced Relative Diagnostic is new. As far as I am aware, it has not before been used to diagnose • PRO can be a subject, but not an object. is generalisation holds regardless subjecthood. of whether PRO is subject-controlled (ä), object-controlled (ß), or arbitrarily- controlled (): ì Experiencer subjects (ä) Subject-controlled • Assumptions a. Fernandai wanted [ PROi to hug Megan ] – A ¤¶§í «¶fuh± is a subject marked with a nonnominative case. b. *Fernandai wanted [ (Megan) to hug PROi ] – e «¶fuh± is the highest base-generated argument (working assumption). (ß) Object-controlled – By these denitions, quirky subjects include experiencers in Icelandic, Ger- man, Hindi, Basque, and Laz; ergatives in Hindi, Basque, and Laz; and a. Fernanda told Hsin-Luni [ PROi to hug Megan ] oblique objects under passivisation in Icelandic, German, and Hindi. b. *Fernanda told Hsin-Luni [ (Megan) to hug PROi ] ⇒ In this presentation, I will focus on experiencer quirky subjects because they ex- ist in all ve languages under investigation and suce to illustrate the empirical Ö In the interest of time, I have omitted the arguments against raising-to-object and conjunction reduction as subjecthood diagnostics. generalisation that emerges from the broader study. ì • Hindi • Basque Quirky subjects in Hindi can bind SOA, but cannot be PRO or undergo relativi- Quirky subjects in Basque can bind SOA, but cannot be PRO or undergo rela- sation in RRCs. tivisation in RRCs. (Õó) a. Binding Diagnostic 3 (Õ¦) a. Binding Diagnostic 3 Mujhei [apnei sab rishtedar¯ ] pasand hε˜ Jon-ii [bere buru-a ]i gusta-tzen zaio I.oZ± §u..£ all relative. like be.£§«.£ Jon-oZ± his head-ou±. like-£ê Z¶ì(ì«.Zf«-ì«.oZ±) ‘I like all my relatives’ [Bhatt óþþì:Õó] ‘Jon likes himself’ 7 b. PRO Diagnostic 7 b. PRO Diagnostic *Ravii [PROi Rina pasand a-n¯ a¯ ] nah˜¯ı *Jon-eki [PROi gustatu Miren ] nahi du Ravi. PRO.oZ± Rina. like come- u Jon-u§ PRO.oZ± like Miren. want Z¶ì(ì«.Zf«-ì«.u§) Intended: chah-t¯ a.¯ ‘Jon wants to like Miren’ want-Zf..« c. Reduced Relative Diagnostic 7 Intended: ‘Ravi doesn’t want to like Rina’ *[ ___i Miren gustatu-ta-ko ] gizon-ai ... c. Reduced Relative Diagnostic 7 ___.oZ± Miren. like-£±h£-h man-ou±. Intended: ‘the man who likes Miren . .’ *[ ___i cot. lag-a¯ ] lar.ka¯i ... ___.oZ± hurt contact-£ê boy • Icelandic Intended: ‘the hurt boy . .’ Quirky subjects in Icelandic can bind SOA and be PRO, but cannot undergo relativisation in RRCs. • German Quirky subjects in German can bind SOA, but cannot be PRO or undergo (Õ¢) a. Binding Diagnostic 3 relativisation in RRCs.
Recommended publications
  • The Syntax of Case and Agreement: Its Relationship to Morphology and Argument Structure
    The Syntax of Case and Agreement: its Relationship to Morphology and Argument Structure By Vita G. Markman A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School – New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Linguistics written under the direction of Professor Mark Baker and approved by Professor Mark Baker Professor Viviane Deprez Professor Ken Safir Professor Carson Schutze New Brunswick, New Jersey October 2005 © 2005 Vita G. Markman ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ABSTRACT OF DISSERTATION The Syntax of Case and Agreement: its Relationship to Morphology and Argument Structure by VITA G. MARKMAN Dissertation Director Professor Mark Baker In this thesis I argue for a non-arbitrary relationship between the syntax of case and agreement and its morphological realization, as reflected in the following linguistic universals: 1. If a language overtly case-marks the subject, it overtly marks the object; 2.If a language has overt object agreement, it has overt subject agreement (Moravcik 1974, Comrie 1988, Lehmann 1982). The goal of this thesis is to explain the nature of the morphology-syntax connection the above universals embody and explore the consequences it has for syntactic theory, grammars of individual languages, and for UG. In this dissertation I depart from the Universal Approach (e.g. Chomsky 1981, Rouveret and Vergnaud 1980, and later in Chomsky 1995, 2000, Harley 1995, Sigurdsson 2003 inter alia) that treats case and agreement as universal properties of language and their overt realization as arbitrary and language specific. Building on a proposal presented in Pesetsky and Torrego 2001 that features are interpretable but may become uninterpetable if placed on a wrong head, I argue that case and agreement features are misplaced interpretable features used by languages to create PF-records of thematic relations.
    [Show full text]
  • A Crosslinguistic Approach to Double Nominative and Biabsolutive Constructions
    A Crosslinguistic Approach to Double Nominative and Biabsolutive Constructions: Evidence from Korean and Daghestanian∗ Andrei Antonenko1 and Jisung Sun2 Stony Brook University1,2 1. Introduction Distribution of case among distinct grammatical relations is one of the most frequently studied topics in the syntactic theory. Canonical cases are, in accusative languages, subjects of both intransitive and transitive verbs being nominative, while direct objects of transitive verbs are usually marked accusative. In ergative languages, subjects of intransitive verbs share properties with direct objects of transitive verbs, and are marked absolutive. Subjects of transitive verbs are usually ergative. When you look into world languages, however, there are ‘non-canonical’ case patterns too. Probably the most extreme kind of non-canonical case system would be so-called Quirky Subject constructions in Icelandic (see Sigurðsson 2002). This paper concerns constructions, in which two nominals are identically case-marked in a clause, as observed in Korean and Daghestanian languages. Daghestanian languages belong to Nakh-Daghestanian branch of North Caucasian family. Nakh-Daghestanian languages are informally divided into Nakh languages, such as Chechen and Ingush, spoken in Chechnya and the Republic of Ingushetia, respectively; and Daghestanian languages, spoken in the Republic of Daghestan. Those regions are located in the Caucasian part of Russian Federation. Some Daghestanian languages are also spoken in Azerbaijan and Georgia. This study focuses on Daghestanian languages, such as Archi, Avar, Dargwa, Hinuq, Khwarshi, Lak and Tsez, due to similar behaviors of them with respect to the described phenomenon. 2. Ergativity in Daghestanian Aldridge (2004) proposes that there are two types of syntactically ergative languages, based on which argument is performing functions typical for subjects.
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Nominative Subjects in Comparison
    NON-NOMINATIVE SUBJECTS IN COMPARISON Josef Bayer University of Konstanz Fachbereich Sprachwissenschaft Universität Konstanz Universitätsstr. 10 D-78457 Konstanz Germany [email protected] 1 NON-NOMINATIVE SUBJECTS IN COMPARISON Josef Bayer University of Konstanz 1. Introduction Among languages with a sufficiently rich system of morphological Case we observe unmarked constituent orderings which deviate from the “nomina- tive preceding non-nominative” pattern. This deviation, if one wants to call it that way, is to a large extent lexically and semantically predictable. Languages of this kind are classified as languages that permit non- nominative subjects. As is well known, however, they differ quite radically as to certain syntactic consequences which the non-nominative-first pat- tern may have. German and Icelandic are closely related Germanic lan- guages which – not surprisingly – show strong similarities in their argu- ment structures and syntax of Case. Nevertheless, they differ by the fact that non-nominative prominent DPs in Icelandic behave like genuine sub- jects while they do not (or do to a lesser extent) in German. The goal of the present article is to explore the possibility of deriving differences in “sub- jecthood” from the basic order of constituents. Icelandic has a head-initial 0 VP which is separated from an external argument by a functional head F 0 (or a number of functional heads), i.e., the order is SpecFP F [VP V …]. Ger- man has a head-final VP instead. There are strong indications that the or- 0 der [VP … V] F does not give rise to a functionally defined position SpecFP.
    [Show full text]
  • Person Versus Default Number in Agreement Peter Ackema University of Edinburgh Ad Neeleman UCL
    Chapter 2 Default person versus default number in agreement Peter Ackema University of Edinburgh Ad Neeleman UCL In this paper, we compare the behaviour of the default in the person system (third person) with the default in the number system (singular). We argue, following Nevins (2007; 2011), that third person pronouns have person features, while singu- lar DPs lack number features. The evidence for these claims comes from situations in which a single head agrees with multiple DPs that have contrasting person and number specifications. In cases where the number of morphological slots inwhich agreement can be realized is lower than the number of agreement relations estab- lished in syntax, such contrasting specification may prove problematic. As it turns out, conflicts between singular and plural do not result in ungrammaticality, but conflicts between third person and first or second person do. Such person clashes can be avoided if the morphological realization of the relevant person features is syncretic. Alternatively, languages may make use of a person hierarchy that reg- ulates the morphological realization of conflicting specifications for person. The argument we present is rooted in, and supports, the theory of person developed in Ackema & Neeleman (2013; 2018). 1 Introduction The problem addressed in this paper is an apparent paradox involving singular number and third person. On the one hand, there is evidence that in the per- son system the default is third person, while in the number system the default is singular. For example, dummy pronouns and verbs that fail to agree (as in impersonal passives) show up in the third person singular: Peter Ackema & Ad Neeleman.
    [Show full text]
  • CASE ALTERNATIONS in ANCIENT GREEK PASSIVES and the TYPOLOGY of CASE Elena Anagnostopoulou Christina Sevdali
    CASE ALTERNATIONS IN ANCIENT GREEK PASSIVES AND THE TYPOLOGY OF CASE Elena Anagnostopoulou Christina Sevdali University of Crete Ulster University This article presents and discusses evidence that genitive and dative objects regularly become nominative in Ancient Greek passives of monotransitives and ditransitives. This is a typologically and theoretically significant state of affairs for two reasons . (i) As is well known, nonaccusative objects are, in many languages, not allowed to enter into Case alternations, a fact that has been ac - counted for in the government-binding /principles-and-parameters literature on the basis of the as - sumption that nonaccusative objects —prototypically datives —bear inherent , lexical , or quirky Case. By this reasoning, Ancient Greek genitives and datives must be concluded to have structural Case. (ii) Even in languages where dative -nominative (DAT-NOM) alternations do obtain, they are often limited to ditransitives, a fact that can been taken to suggest that dative qual - ifies as structural Case only in ditransitives. A language like Ancient Greek , which allows genitive and dative objects to become nominative in all passives (monotransitives and ditransitives) , shows that it is, in principle, possible to have a linguistic system where genitive and dative qualify as structural Cases in both monotransitives and ditransitives. Case theories must be designed in such a way as to allow for this option. We argue for an analysis of Case alternations that combines the view that alternating datives and
    [Show full text]
  • Raising to Quirky Subject in Tatar∗ 1 Introduction
    A-2 Raising to Quirky Subject in Tatar∗ Chihiro Taguchi Nara Institute of Science and Technology [email protected] Keywords— Tatar, Turkic, syntax, morphology, raising, quirky subject Abstract Tatar (< Kipchak < Turkic) has subject-to-subject raising predicates where the raised argument is marked by nominative, dative and genitive case, of which the latter two are “quirky (i.e., non-nominative) subjects” (Sigurðsson 1992). Poole (2016) proposed the Quirky Subject Hierarchy, a three-level hierarchy of the subjecthood of quirky subjects, and classified languages with quirky subject into three categories: Hindi type, Icelandic type, and Laz type. However, the Tatar data in this paper demonstrate that a language may fit more than one categories; a raised subject with dative case-marking in Tatar displays the Icelandic-type characteristics, and a raised subject with genitive displays the Laz-type. I propose that these properties are not language-specific but lexicon-specific. 1 Introduction The Tatar language is a Kipchak language of the Turkic language family. It is an agglutina- tive language with several nominal case suffixes. The canonical word order is SOV, and the modification order is AN. This paper deals with two kinds of subject-to-subject raising (SSR) predicates whose subject is marked by genitive and dative. (1)-(3) are examples of raising constructions in Tatar, (1) with a nominative subject which is a typical way of marking a subject, (2) with a dative, and (3) with a genitive, all having by and large similar deontological meaning. Section 2 outlines what raising is and how it is analyzed in general theoretical linguistics.
    [Show full text]
  • Modality and Causation in Serbian Dative Anticausatives
    MODALITY AND CAUSATION IN SERBIAN DATIVE ANTICAUSATIVES: A CROSSLINGUISTIC PERSPECTIVE A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI‘I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN LINGUISTICS DECEMBER 2013 By Tatjana Ilić Dissertation Committee: Kamil Ud Deen, Chairperson William O’Grady Yuko Otsuka Bonnie D. Schwartz Shuqiang Zhang ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to take the opportunity to thank to all my committee members for providing patient guidance in my work over the years. First and foremost, a warm thank you goes to my committee chair and the advisor of many years, Dr. Kamil Ud Deen, for being such a friend and support on this journey, and for providing the sound of reason when my ideas were pulling me astray. I deeply appreciate the liberty I was given in handling this topic, and admire his willingness and the ability to survive the countless versions, changes of perspective, and even of the theoretical approach that this dissertation has gone through. I have grown as a linguist, as a writer and as a person, and I can only hope to benefit much more from his professional and personal friendship in the years to come. A further warm thank you goes jointly to Dr. Kamil Ud Deen and Dr. Bonnie Schwartz for many a discussion on the first language acquisition, child second language acquisition, second language processing and more. I am particularly indebted to Dr. Bonnie Schwartz for all the hearty laughs I had with her over the years. A further deep appreciation goes to Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Impersonal Constructions in Old French and the Agreement Puzzle∗
    IMPERSONAL CONSTRUCTIONS IN OLD FRENCH AND THE AGREEMENT PUZZLE∗ Eric Mathieu University of Ottawa 1. Introduction Quirky subjects are subjects surfacing with non-nominative case. Although they have clear subject properties (they can appear in first position in main and embedded clauses; they can undergo subject-verb inversion - in V1 and V2 environments; they can bind an anaphor; they can participate in raising constructions; they can be a controllee; and they can participate in conjunction reduction), they have the striking property of not entering into an Agree relation with the predicate. This puzzle remains to be explained, especially since subject- verb agreement is often taken to be a prototypical property of subjecthood. The present paper focuses on Old French impersonal constructions where quirky subjects can be found. The paper relies on the facts introduced in Mathieu (2006a) which show that pre-verbal non-nominative elements in Old French are true subjects. They have all the properties listed above: they can bind an anaphor, be a controllee, etc. In the present study, I concentrate on agreement issues: first, I give a solution to the puzzle as to why there is no Agree relation between the oblique subject and the predicate in Old French impersonal constructions, and second, why in the absence of agreement nominative objects can nevertheless be licensed in these constructions. Section 2 constitutes the body of the paper while Section 3 concludes with a summary. 2. Agreement In Mathieu (2006a), I argue that Old French exhibits structures which call upon a quirky-subject analysis. Dubbed ‘impersonal constructions’ in the traditional literature, such structures typically involve an empty subject position that a dative, accusative or genitive XP comes to fill1.
    [Show full text]
  • Agreement, Case and Locality in the Nominal and Verbal Domains
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Default person versus default number in agreement Citation for published version: Ackema, P & Neeleman, A 2019, Default person versus default number in agreement. in L Franco, MMM & M Reeve (eds), Agreement, Case and Locality in the Nominal and Verbal Domains. Open Generative Syntax, Language Science Press, Berlin, pp. 21-54. https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.3458062 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.5281/zenodo.3458062 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Agreement, Case and Locality in the Nominal and Verbal Domains General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 02. Oct. 2021 Chapter 2 Default person versus default number in agreement Peter Ackema University of Edinburgh Ad Neeleman UCL In this paper, we compare the behaviour of the default in the person system (third person) with the default in the number system (singular). We argue, following Nevins (2007; 2011), that third person pronouns have person features, while singu- lar DPs lack number features.
    [Show full text]
  • LB-Sonderheft 14: Endangered Languages
    Peter Austin / Andrew Simpson (Hg.) Buske Endangered Languages Endangered Languages Linguistische Berichte Sonderheft 14 Edited by Peter K. Austin and Andrew Simpson HELMUT BUSKE VERLAG HAMBURG Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über <http://dnb.d-nb.de> abrufbar. ISBN 978-3-87548-465-6 LB Sonderheft · ISSN 0935-9249 www.buske.de © Helmut Buske Verlag 2007. Alle Rechte, auch die des auszugsweisen Nach- drucks, der fotomechanischen Wiedergabe und der Übersetzung, vorbehalten. Dies betrifft auch die Vervielfältigung und Übertragung einzelner Textabschnitte durch alle Verfahren wie Speicherung und Übertragung auf Papier, Filme, Bän- der, Platten und andere Medien, soweit es nicht §§ 53 und 54 URG ausdrücklich gestatten. Druck und Bindung: Druckhaus „Thomas Müntzer“, Bad Langensalza. Werkdruckpapier: alterungsbeständig nach ANSI-Norm resp. DIN-ISO 9706, hergestellt aus 100% chlorfrei gebleichtem Zellstoff. Printed in Germany. Contents Peter K. Austin and Andrew Simpson Introduction .................................................................................. 5 Nicholas Evans Warramurrungunji undone: Australian languages in the 51st Millennium 19 Knut J. Olawsky ObViouS OVS in Urarina syntax ....................................................... 45 Larry M. Hyman and Imelda Udoh Length harmony in Leggbó: a counter-universal? ...............................
    [Show full text]
  • Case, Agreement and Movement in Arabic a Minimalist Approach
    Case, Agreement and Movement in Arabic A Minimalist Approach Mamdouh Musabhien B.A. AHU / Jordan (2001) M.A. University of Essex (2004) A thesis submitted to the School of English Literature Language and Linguistics for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at Newcastle University November,2008 © 2008 Mamdouh Ayed Ghayad Musabhien All Rights Reserved 2 Abstract This thesis proposes a minimalist analysis that accounts for a number of word-order- related issues in Modern Standard Arabic (MSA) and Jordanian Arabic (JA). Assuming Chomsky's (2005) feature inheritance model, the thesis investigates the issues of Case, the interaction between subject positions and verbal agreement in addition to object movement. In verb-subject-object word orders, subjects are invariably nominative; the Case value on the postverbal subject is an outcome of an Agree relation between these subjects and T, the head of Tense Phrase (TP), which inherits its feature from the complementiser. Chapter four argues that the Case variability on the preverbal subject in subject-verb-object structures is dependent on the type of the complementiser. The complementiser which introduces subject-verb-object clauses has a lexical Case feature that is not interpretable on T, hence T does not inherit this feature. Consequently, the lexical Case feature of the complementiser in subject- verb-object structures is discharged under a local Agree relation between the complementiser and the preverbal noun phrase which is raised from a lower position. It is also claimed in chapter four that the structure of zero copula sentences contains a light Noun Phrase (nP) functional projection that compares to the light Verb Phrase (vP) functional projection in verbal sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • Agreement and Its Failures
    Agreement and its failures Omer Preminger £§u-£¶fhZ± o§Z± August ä, óþÕì – o ± o««uZ±u – to Saa Yaa Contents Acknowledgements ix Abbreviations xi Õ Introduction Õ ó Modeling the obligatoriness of φ-agreement ¢ ó.Õ A working denition of “agreement” .......................... ä ó.ó ree models for the obligatoriness of agreement .................. ß ó.ó.Õ e derivational time-bombs model ..................... ß ó.ó.ó e violable constraints model ......................... Õþ ó.ó.ì e obligatory operations model ........................ ÕÕ ó.ì Failed agreement, and why we should be interested in it ............... Õ¦ ì Agreement in the Kichean Agent-Focus construction: e facts Õß ì.Õ Some basic facts about Kichean and Agent-Focus .................. Õ ì.ó Agreement in Kichean Agent-Focus .......................... óó ì.ì eAFpersonrestriction ................................ ó ì.ì.Õ e phenomenon ................................. ó ì.ì.ó Against a purely morphological analysis of agreement in AF ....... óÉ ì.¦ e morpho-phonology of Kichean agreement markers ............... ìþ ¦ A derivational account of absolutive agreement in Kichean ì¢ ¦.Õ Background: e PCC, and Béjar & Rezac’s (óþþì) account of it .......... ì ¦.ó Relativized probing .................................... ¦É ¦.ó.Õ What’s good for [wh] is good for [plural] and [participant], too . ¢þ ¦.ó.ó Feature relativization in a feature-geometric approach ........... ¢¦ ¦.ó.ì Valuation in a feature-geometric approach .................. ¢É ¦.ó.¦ Summary ..................................... äó vi ¦.ì On the featural coarseness of clitic doubling ...................... äì ¦.¦ Applying Béjar & Rezac’s (óþþì) account to Kichean ................ äÉ ¦.¦.Õ e basic clause structure and derivation ................... äÉ ¦.¦.ó Licensing asymmetries in Kichean AF, and the AF person restriction .. ßÉ ¦.¢ Some alternative analyses, and their drawbacks ...................
    [Show full text]