200422 Finalarxivversion.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

200422 Finalarxivversion.Pdf Classical and Nonclassical Time Dilation for Quantum Clocks A. J. Paige,1, ∗ A. D. K. Plato,1 and M. S. Kim1 1QOLS, Blackett Laboratory, Imperial College London, South Kensington, London, SW7 2AZ, UK. Proper time, ideal clocks, and boosts are well understood classically, but subtleties arise in quan- tum physics. We show that quantum clocks set in motion via momentum boosts do not witness classical time dilation. However, using velocity boosts we find the ideal behaviour in both cases where the quantum clock and classical observer are set in motion. Without internal state depen- dent forces additional effects arise. As such, we derive observed frequency shifts in ion trap atomic clocks, indicating a small additional shift, and also show the emergence of non-ideal behaviour in a theoretical clock model. Ideal clocks and proper time are key concepts in special observer and quantum clock being set in motion is cap- and general relativity [1]. Full understanding of the union tured by translation operators, and that it is the trans- between relativity and quantum mechanics, must include formation under translation operators that enables the how these ideas extend to the quantum realm. Recent velocity boost to describe both situations. We demon- work in this area can broadly be divided by whether the strate how these translation operators can be understood quantum clocks follow classical or quantum trajectories. via considering the placement of the origin for the re- Adopting the former approach [2{5] enables the utiliza- quired potentials. In addition, we show that considering tion of techniques from quantum field theory in curved the velocity kick as the classical observer changing frames spacetime. In particular this has allowed explorations immediately tells us that entanglement is frame depen- into consequences of the Unruh effect [6], and applica- dent and demonstrate consistency with the equivalence tions of techniques from relativistic quantum metrology principle. We highlight that without an internal state de- [7,8]. On the other hand, for quantum clocks following pendent force one should expect additional effects. We quantum mechanical trajectories [9{19], most progress demonstrate this for frequency shifts in ion traps, predict- has been made investigating connections between proper ing the already observed shifts and an additional smaller time and mass superpositions [20]. This has necessitated shift. We also analyse the effect on a Salecker-Wigner- the rejection of the Bargmann mass superselection rule Peres clock [24, 25] finding non-ideal clock behaviour. [21], on the grounds that our universe is not Galilean. Modified Hamiltonian | We begin by presenting the Notably this paradigm was used to investigate ideas for simplest argument for the modified Hamiltonian. The intrinsic time dilation decoherence caused by gravity [10]. modification was introduced and used to study quantum In this work we follow the second approach, where the mechanical proper time [9], and has also been shown to clock's motion is described quantum mechanically. We resolve paradoxes in quantum optics [26, 27]. For a free show that a quantum clock set into motion by a force composite particle of mass M; the non-relativistic Hamil- 2 that does not depend on the internal state is not wit- p tonian will consist of a kinetic energy term 2M ; and an nessing classical time dilation. This is because quantum internal energy term H0: However the internal energy clocks require coherence in some non-degenerate energy should contribute to the inertial mass since special rela- states [22, 23] but the inertial mass of this energy means tivity dictates that energy and inertial mass are equiva- 2 that assigning an identical momentum to each branch of lent. This leads to M = m + H0=c ; where we take m as the superposition does not correspond to a well defined the rest mass of the particle in its internal energy ground velocity. We therefore show that momentum boosts lead state j0i; and set H0j0i = 0: Thus we have to a nonclassical dilation due to the lack of a unique Lorentz factor. On the other hand, by suitably coupling p2 H = + H ; the motional and internal degrees of freedom, one can ap- 2M 0 (1) ply a velocity boost which exactly recovers the expected p2 p2 = + H 1 − : classical time dilation results for the \twin paradox," in 2m 0 2mMc2 both cases where the observer and the quantum clock are respectively the ones set in motion. To arrive at the second line we have used 1=(x + y) = We start from a Hamiltonian modified to account for 1=x − y=x(x + y): Note that since M is now operator the inertial mass of internal energy. We then consider valued, there is potential for ambiguity with operator or- sequences of appropriately centred boosts and evolution dering. However if the internal Hamiltonian commutes −1 operators to derive the different possible clock behaviours with the total momentum [H0; p] = 0; then [M ; p] = 0: in a twin paradox scenario. From the classical observer's Fully accounting for relativity would strictly imply that frame we show that the difference between the classical the internal degrees of freedom should be described by 2 a relativistic wave equation (or a quantum field theory). pbi: This represents the physical situation typically con- However the approach here is that regardless of the for- sidered for use in the laboratory [30], with no internal malism, the effect on the centre of mass dynamics should state dependence as per the potentials typically used to only be via a mass change, otherwise we could not claim move quantum systems (e.g. an ion moved via an Elec- that energy and inertial mass are equivalent. tromagnetic potential). 2 This Hamiltonian is often expanded in H0=mc ne- Using this boost, the translation operator T (pbt=m) = glecting higher order terms [10, 27]. It is then tempting e−ippbt=m~, and the free evolution under the Hamiltonian p2 of Eq. (1), we have to claim that (1 − 2m2c2 ) represents our familiar notion of time dilation, however, this is not correct as will be shown later. It is also important to emphasise that we Bp(pb)U(t)T (pbt=m)Bp(−2pb)T (−pbt=m)U(t)Bp(pb) shall always be working in the limit where the energy E = 2 p2 p2 − i2t p 2it b − 2it H (1− b ) p 2M 2m 0 2mMc2 p2c2 + M 2c4 is approximated by E = p2=2M + Mc2: = e ~ e ~ e ~ : (3) In words, one can consider the regime we utilise as one The first exponential term is the unaltered motional evo- where the mechanics can be treated in a \Newtonian" lution of the state that we would expect if we had not sense, but the rest mass of the internal energy is now ac- applied any of the boosts. This term has no p depen- counted for. On a technical level one must appreciate (as b dent relativistic corrections, which is not surprising since noted in [13]) that there are two relevant small quanti- the adopted formalism does not include the relevant rel- ties: H =mc2 and p2=m2c2; where the first relates to the 0 ativistic motional terms. The second term is a global internal degrees of freedom and the second can be viewed phase that is connected to the choice of the translation as a motional v2=c2 term (note p2=m2c2 > p2=M 2c2;). It operators, discussed in detail below. However, it is the is therefore not sufficient to merely think of approxima- final term that captures the effect on the evolution of the tions in terms of how many factors of 1=c2; are present. 2 internal state and therefore is our primary focus. One can consider the regime where H0=mc 1; but 2 2 2 2 The third exponential term in Eq. (3) has the internal H0=mc p =m c : With this in mind one arrives at Eq. 2 pb (1) (plus ground state rest mass energy) by expanding Hamiltonian multiplied by a factor (1 − 2mMc2 ) that is the full relativistic energy E = pM 2c4 + p2c2 = γMc2; less than unity. This is precisely the factor we would get neglecting terms of O(p4=m4c4) in the Lorentz factor by considering Eq.1 acting on a momentum eigenstate 2 jp i: We see that if we have some coherence in the in- whilst retaining the H0=mc terms and translating the b zero of energy by mc2: Note that in practise the order ternal state and are using it as a clock, then it appears 2 that the clock is running slower. Note it is not dilated of H0=mc terms kept would be dictated by the physical system under consideration and depends on the integer by a constant inverse Lorentz factor as in classical rela- 2 n 2 2 2 tivity. We can see why this is so by asking what Lorentz n for which (H0=mc ) p =m c : However, as will become apparent, it will prove more straightforward for factor we would expect. The clock has been given a mo- our initial theoretical study to work with the untruncated mentum pb but because our clock is in a superposition (1 + H =mc2)−1: We shall denote the unitary evolution of energies En, we also have a superposition of different 0 2 generated by Eq. (1) over time t as U(t): masses Mn = m + En=c : Hence we can write various Different boosts | We now explore the consequences velocities and thus Lorentz factors. For example, the N p 2 2 2 of the modified Hamiltonian. Time is a complex topic single shot values γn = 1 + pb =Mnc ; or the expec- in quantum mechanics [28, 29], but here we shall sim- tation value of an operator hγi: Furthermore, Eq.
Recommended publications
  • Information and Entropy in Quantum Theory
    Information and Entropy in Quantum Theory O J E Maroney Ph.D. Thesis Birkbeck College University of London Malet Street London WC1E 7HX arXiv:quant-ph/0411172v1 23 Nov 2004 Abstract Recent developments in quantum computing have revived interest in the notion of information as a foundational principle in physics. It has been suggested that information provides a means of interpreting quantum theory and a means of understanding the role of entropy in thermodynam- ics. The thesis presents a critical examination of these ideas, and contrasts the use of Shannon information with the concept of ’active information’ introduced by Bohm and Hiley. We look at certain thought experiments based upon the ’delayed choice’ and ’quantum eraser’ interference experiments, which present a complementarity between information gathered from a quantum measurement and interference effects. It has been argued that these experiments show the Bohm interpretation of quantum theory is untenable. We demonstrate that these experiments depend critically upon the assumption that a quantum optics device can operate as a measuring device, and show that, in the context of these experiments, it cannot be consistently understood in this way. By contrast, we then show how the notion of ’active information’ in the Bohm interpretation provides a coherent explanation of the phenomena shown in these experiments. We then examine the relationship between information and entropy. The thought experiment connecting these two quantities is the Szilard Engine version of Maxwell’s Demon, and it has been suggested that quantum measurement plays a key role in this. We provide the first complete description of the operation of the Szilard Engine as a quantum system.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Languages Shape Our Understanding of Time in Physics Physics Is Formulated in Terms of Timeless, Axiomatic Mathematics
    comment Corrected: Publisher Correction Mathematical languages shape our understanding of time in physics Physics is formulated in terms of timeless, axiomatic mathematics. A formulation on the basis of intuitionist mathematics, built on time-evolving processes, would ofer a perspective that is closer to our experience of physical reality. Nicolas Gisin n 1922 Albert Einstein, the physicist, met in Paris Henri Bergson, the philosopher. IThe two giants debated publicly about time and Einstein concluded with his famous statement: “There is no such thing as the time of the philosopher”. Around the same time, and equally dramatically, mathematicians were debating how to describe the continuum (Fig. 1). The famous German mathematician David Hilbert was promoting formalized mathematics, in which every real number with its infinite series of digits is a completed individual object. On the other side the Dutch mathematician, Luitzen Egbertus Jan Brouwer, was defending the view that each point on the line should be represented as a never-ending process that develops in time, a view known as intuitionistic mathematics (Box 1). Although Brouwer was backed-up by a few well-known figures, like Hermann Weyl 1 and Kurt Gödel2, Hilbert and his supporters clearly won that second debate. Hence, time was expulsed from mathematics and mathematical objects Fig. 1 | Debating mathematicians. David Hilbert (left), supporter of axiomatic mathematics. L. E. J. came to be seen as existing in some Brouwer (right), proposer of intuitionist mathematics. Credit: Left: INTERFOTO / Alamy Stock Photo; idealized Platonistic world. right: reprinted with permission from ref. 18, Springer These two debates had a huge impact on physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on the Theory of Quantum Clock
    NOTES ON THE THEORY OF QUANTUM CLOCK I.Tralle1, J.-P. Pellonp¨a¨a2 1Institute of Physics, University of Rzesz´ow,Rzesz´ow,Poland e-mail:[email protected] 2Department of Physics, University of Turku, Turku, Finland e-mail:juhpello@utu.fi (Received 11 March 2005; accepted 21 April 2005) Abstract In this paper we argue that the notion of time, whatever complicated and difficult to define as the philosophical cat- egory, from physicist’s point of view is nothing else but the sum of ’lapses of time’ measured by a proper clock. As far as Quantum Mechanics is concerned, we distinguish a special class of clocks, the ’atomic clocks’. It is because at atomic and subatomic level there is no other possibility to construct a ’unit of time’ or ’instant of time’ as to use the quantum transitions between chosen quantum states of a quantum ob- ject such as atoms, atomic nuclei and so on, to imitate the periodic circular motion of a clock hand over the dial. The clock synchronization problem is also discussed in the paper. We study the problem of defining a time difference observable for two-mode oscillator system. We assume that the time dif- ference obsevable is the difference of two single-mode covariant Concepts of Physics, Vol. II (2005) 113 time observables which are represented as a time shift covari- ant normalized positive operator measures. The difficulty of finding the correct value space and normalization for time dif- ference is discussed. 114 Concepts of Physics, Vol. II (2005) Notes on the Theory of Quantum Clock And the heaven departed as a scroll when it is rolled together;..
    [Show full text]
  • Engineering Ultrafast Quantum Frequency Conversion
    Engineering ultrafast quantum frequency conversion Der Naturwissenschaftlichen Fakultät der Universität Paderborn zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades Dr. rer. nat. vorgelegt von BENJAMIN BRECHT aus Nürnberg To Olga for Love and Support Contents 1 Summary1 2 Zusammenfassung3 3 A brief history of ultrafast quantum optics5 3.1 1900 – 1950 ................................... 5 3.2 1950 – 2000 ................................... 6 3.3 2000 – today .................................. 8 4 Fundamental theory 11 4.1 Waveguides .................................. 11 4.1.1 Waveguide modelling ........................ 12 4.1.2 Spatial mode considerations .................... 14 4.2 Light-matter interaction ........................... 16 4.2.1 Nonlinear polarisation ........................ 16 4.2.2 Three-wave mixing .......................... 17 4.2.3 More on phasematching ...................... 18 4.3 Ultrafast pulses ................................. 21 4.3.1 Time-bandwidth product ...................... 22 4.3.2 Chronocyclic Wigner function ................... 22 4.3.3 Pulse shaping ............................. 25 5 From classical to quantum optics 27 5.1 Speaking quantum .............................. 27 iii 5.1.1 Field quantisation in waveguides ................. 28 5.1.2 Quantum three-wave mixing .................... 30 5.1.3 Time-frequency representation .................. 32 5.1.3.1 Joint spectral amplitude functions ........... 32 5.1.3.2 Schmidt decomposition ................. 35 5.2 Understanding quantum ........................... 36 5.2.1 Parametric
    [Show full text]
  • HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P Letizia
    HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P Letizia To cite this version: P Letizia. HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas: A possible explanation of Dark Energy. 2017. hal-01424099 HAL Id: hal-01424099 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01424099 Preprint submitted on 3 Jan 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution - NonCommercial - ShareAlike| 4.0 International License SUBMITTED FOR STUDY January 1st, 2017 HYPOTHESIS: How Defining Nature of Time Might Explain Some of Actual Physics Enigmas P. Letizia Abstract Nowadays it seems that understanding the Nature of Time is not more a priority. It seems commonly admitted that Time can not be clearly nor objectively defined. I do not agree with this vision. I am among those who think that Time has an objective reality in Physics. If it has a reality, then it must be understood. My first ambition with this paper was to submit for study a proposition concerning the Nature of Time. However, once defined I understood that this proposition embeds an underlying logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on the Theory of Quantum Clock
    NOTES ON THE THEORY OF QUANTUM CLOCK I.Tralle1, J.-P. Pellonp¨a¨a2 1Institute of Physics, University of Rzesz´ow,Rzesz´ow,Poland e-mail:[email protected] 2Department of Physics, University of Turku, Turku, Finland e-mail:juhpello@utu.fi (Received 11 March 2005; accepted 21 April 2005) Abstract In this paper we argue that the notion of time, whatever complicated and difficult to define as the philosophical cat- egory, from physicist’s point of view is nothing else but the sum of ’lapses of time’ measured by a proper clock. As far as Quantum Mechanics is concerned, we distinguish a special class of clocks, the ’atomic clocks’. It is because at atomic and subatomic level there is no other possibility to construct a ’unit of time’ or ’instant of time’ as to use the quantum transitions between chosen quantum states of a quantum ob- ject such as atoms, atomic nuclei and so on, to imitate the periodic circular motion of a clock hand over the dial. The clock synchronization problem is also discussed in the paper. We study the problem of defining a time difference observable for two-mode oscillator system. We assume that the time dif- ference obsevable is the difference of two single-mode covariant Concepts of Physics, Vol. II (2005) 113 time observables which are represented as a time shift covari- ant normalized positive operator measures. The difficulty of finding the correct value space and normalization for time dif- ference is discussed. 114 Concepts of Physics, Vol. II (2005) Notes on the Theory of Quantum Clock And the heaven departed as a scroll when it is rolled together;..
    [Show full text]
  • The Boundaries of Nature: Special & General Relativity and Quantum
    “The Boundaries of Nature: Special & General Relativity and Quantum Mechanics, A Second Course in Physics” Edwin F. Taylor's acceptance speech for the 1998 Oersted medal presented by the American Association of Physics Teachers, 6 January 1998 Edwin F. Taylor Center for Innovation in Learning, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213 (Now at 22 Hopkins Road, Arlington, MA 02476-8109, email [email protected] , web http://www.artsaxis.com/eftaylor/ ) ABSTRACT Public hunger for relativity and quantum mechanics is insatiable, and we should use it selectively but shamelessly to attract students, most of whom will not become physics majors, but all of whom can experience "deep physics." Science, engineering, and mathematics students, indeed anyone comfortable with calculus, can now delve deeply into special and general relativity and quantum mechanics. Big chunks of general relativity require only calculus if one starts with the metric describing spacetime around Earth or black hole. Expressions for energy and angular momentum follow, along with orbit predictions for particles and light. Feynman's Sum Over Paths quantum theory simply commands the electron: Explore all paths. Students can model this command with the computer, pointing and clicking to tell the electron which paths to explore; wave functions and bound states arise naturally. A second full year course in physics covering special relativity, general relativity, and quantum mechanics would have wide appeal -- and might also lead to significant advancements in upper-level courses for the physics major. © 1998 American Association of Physics Teachers INTRODUCTION It is easy to feel intimidated by those who have in the past received the Oersted Medal, especially those with whom I have worked closely in the enterprise of physics teaching: Edward M.
    [Show full text]
  • Terminology of Geological Time: Establishment of a Community Standard
    Terminology of geological time: Establishment of a community standard Marie-Pierre Aubry1, John A. Van Couvering2, Nicholas Christie-Blick3, Ed Landing4, Brian R. Pratt5, Donald E. Owen6 and Ismael Ferrusquía-Villafranca7 1Department of Earth and Planetary Sciences, Rutgers University, Piscataway NJ 08854, USA; email: [email protected] 2Micropaleontology Press, New York, NY 10001, USA email: [email protected] 3Department of Earth and Environmental Sciences and Lamont-Doherty Earth Observatory of Columbia University, Palisades NY 10964, USA email: [email protected] 4New York State Museum, Madison Avenue, Albany NY 12230, USA email: [email protected] 5Department of Geological Sciences, University of Saskatchewan, Saskatoon SK7N 5E2, Canada; email: [email protected] 6Department of Earth and Space Sciences, Lamar University, Beaumont TX 77710 USA email: [email protected] 7Universidad Nacional Autónomo de México, Instituto de Geologia, México DF email: [email protected] ABSTRACT: It has been recommended that geological time be described in a single set of terms and according to metric or SI (“Système International d’Unités”) standards, to ensure “worldwide unification of measurement”. While any effort to improve communication in sci- entific research and writing is to be encouraged, we are also concerned that fundamental differences between date and duration, in the way that our profession expresses geological time, would be lost in such an oversimplified terminology. In addition, no precise value for ‘year’ in the SI base unit of second has been accepted by the international bodies. Under any circumstances, however, it remains the fact that geologi- cal dates – as points in time – are not relevant to the SI.
    [Show full text]
  • Time and Frequency Division Report
    Time and Frequency Division Goal The broad mission of the Time and Frequency Division is to provide official U.S. time and related quantities to support a wide range of uses in industry, national infrastructure, research, and among the general public. DIVISION STRATEGY The division’s research and metrology ac- tivities comprise three vertically integrated components, each of which constitutes a strategic element: 1. Official time: Accurate and precise realization of official U.S. time (UTC) and frequency. 2. Dissemination: A wide range of mea- surement services to efficiently and effectively distribute U.S. time and frequency and related quantities – pri- marily through free broadcast services available to any user 24/7/365. 3. Research: Research and technolo- gy development to improve time and frequency standards and dissemination. Part of this research includes high-impact programs in areas such as quantum information processing, atom-based sensors, and laser development and applications, which evolved directly from research to make better frequency standards (atomic clocks). Overview These three components – official time, dissemination, and research – are closely integrated. For example, all Division dissemination services tie directly to the Division’s realization of official time (UTC), and much of the Division’s research is enabled by the continual availability of precision UTC. Our modern technology and economy depend critically on the broad availability of precision timing, frequency, and synchronization. NIST realization and dissemination of time and frequency – continually improved by NIST research and development – is a crucial part of a series of informal national timing infrastructures that enable such essential technologies as: • Telecommunications and computer networks • Utility distribution • GPS, widely available in every cell phone and smartphone as well as GPS receivers • Electronic financial transactions 1 • National security and intelligence applications • Research Strategic Goal: Official Time Intended Outcome and Background U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure of Change Brittany A
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations Spring 2019 Time: A Measure of Change Brittany A. Gentry Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gentry, B. A.(2019). Time: A Measure of Change. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/5247 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Time: A Measure of Change By Brittany A. Gentry Bachelor of Arts Houghton College, 2009 ________________________________________________ Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2019 Accepted by Michael Dickson, Major Professor Leah McClimans, Committee Member Thomas Burke, Committee Member Alexander Pruss, Committee Member Cheryl L. Addy, Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School ©Copyright by Brittany A. Gentry, 2019 All Rights Reserved ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Michael Dickson, my dissertation advisor, for extensive comments on numerous drafts over the last several years and for his patience and encouragement throughout this process. I would also like to thank my other committee members, Leah McClimans, Thomas Burke, and Alexander Pruss, for their comments and recommendations along the way. Finally, I am grateful to fellow students and professors at the University of South Carolina, the audience at the International Society for the Philosophy of Time conference at Wake Forest University, NC, and anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on various drafts of portions of this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Physics in Space
    Quantum Physics in Space Alessio Belenchiaa,b,∗∗, Matteo Carlessob,c,d,∗∗, Omer¨ Bayraktare,f, Daniele Dequalg, Ivan Derkachh, Giulio Gasbarrii,j, Waldemar Herrk,l, Ying Lia Lim, Markus Rademacherm, Jasminder Sidhun, Daniel KL Oin, Stephan T. Seidelo, Rainer Kaltenbaekp,q, Christoph Marquardte,f, Hendrik Ulbrichtj, Vladyslav C. Usenkoh, Lisa W¨ornerr,s, Andr´eXuerebt, Mauro Paternostrob, Angelo Bassic,d,∗ aInstitut f¨urTheoretische Physik, Eberhard-Karls-Universit¨atT¨ubingen, 72076 T¨ubingen,Germany bCentre for Theoretical Atomic,Molecular, and Optical Physics, School of Mathematics and Physics, Queen's University, Belfast BT7 1NN, United Kingdom cDepartment of Physics,University of Trieste, Strada Costiera 11, 34151 Trieste,Italy dIstituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare, Trieste Section, Via Valerio 2, 34127 Trieste, Italy eMax Planck Institute for the Science of Light, Staudtstraße 2, 91058 Erlangen, Germany fInstitute of Optics, Information and Photonics, Friedrich-Alexander University Erlangen-N¨urnberg, Staudtstraße 7 B2, 91058 Erlangen, Germany gScientific Research Unit, Agenzia Spaziale Italiana, Matera, Italy hDepartment of Optics, Palacky University, 17. listopadu 50,772 07 Olomouc,Czech Republic iF´ısica Te`orica: Informaci´oi Fen`omensQu`antics,Department de F´ısica, Universitat Aut`onomade Barcelona, 08193 Bellaterra (Barcelona), Spain jDepartment of Physics and Astronomy, University of Southampton, Highfield Campus, SO17 1BJ, United Kingdom kDeutsches Zentrum f¨urLuft- und Raumfahrt e. V. (DLR), Institut f¨urSatellitengeod¨asieund
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Temporal Arrows in Space-Time Temporality
    Temporal Arrows in Space-Time Temporality (…) has nothing to do with mechanics. It has to do with statistical mechanics, thermodynamics (…).C. Rovelli, in Dieks, 2006, 35 Abstract The prevailing current of thought in both physics and philosophy is that relativistic space-time provides no means for the objective measurement of the passage of time. Kurt Gödel, for instance, denied the possibility of an objective lapse of time, both in the Special and the General theory of relativity. From this failure many writers have inferred that a static block universe is the only acceptable conceptual consequence of a four-dimensional world. The aim of this paper is to investigate how arrows of time could be measured objectively in space-time. In order to carry out this investigation it is proposed to consider both local and global arrows of time. In particular the investigation will focus on a) invariant thermodynamic parameters in both the Special and the General theory for local regions of space-time (passage of time); b) the evolution of the universe under appropriate boundary conditions for the whole of space-time (arrow of time), as envisaged in modern quantum cosmology. The upshot of this investigation is that a number of invariant physical indicators in space-time can be found, which would allow observers to measure the lapse of time and to infer both the existence of an objective passage and an arrow of time. Keywords Arrows of time; entropy; four-dimensional world; invariance; space-time; thermodynamics 1 I. Introduction Philosophical debates about the nature of space-time often centre on questions of its ontology, i.e.
    [Show full text]