<<

84TH ACSA ANNUAL MEETING THEORY AND CRITICISM 1996 263

Appreciation and , and

ALEX T. ANDERSON University of Pennsylvania

INTRODUCTION journey in this enlightened way must satisfy themselves with 'nutrition' and 'digesting,' the rationalized and limited Architecture differentiates itself from other forms of art by forms of tasting, savoring and incorporation of food. It is demanding a different sort of attention. Rapt concentration difficult for tourists to fully experience the places they visit does not reveal it. Appreciation is not enough. Architecture because they cannot live with them. demands appropriation. This becomes particularly evident when we consider the In this essay I demonstrate that art and architecture difference between tourist's experience of a building and a distinguish thernselves not in their physical constitutions, lived experience of it. "Buildings," according to Benjamin, but according to the relationships they form with those who "are appropriated in a twofold manner: by use and percep- observe them. In making a work of architecture, it is crucial tio~rrather by touch and by sight."' The tourist's expe- first to understand these relationships, and then to create a rience of a building is limited because the inevitable brevity field that is capable of sustaining them. of 'touring' precludes tactile appropriation, which, Ben- jamin asserts, "is accomplished not so much by attention as VISUAL EXPERIENCE by habit."4 The true experience of a building involves a In his well-known essay, "Art in the Age of Mechanical gradual incorporatio~notthe "introjection of an 'out- Reproduction" Walter Benjamin disparages "the attentive side"' that Calvino's sophisticated tourist experiences, but concentration of the tourist before a famous building."' He an extended temporal involvement. Buildings are hlly implies by this that there is something almost ludicrous about experienced by living with them, not by merely looking at examining a building in this way, as if it were a work of art them. hung on a gallery wall-for he goes on to say that this is how This assumption, though now widely held, fundamentally one looks at art. His contention opens a fundamental insight rejects tenets that drove architecture from the Renaissance to into the nature of architecture and of art: they must be the middle of the nineteenth century. Much of the architec- experienced in radically different ways. While one can, with ture of that period assumed that linear perspective could suitable knowledge and concentration, appreciate art, archi- precisely represent architectural works, and that, in turn, tecture yields itself only to a deeper kind of experience. their configuration could be fully resolved from particular Unlike art, architecture must be appropriated. points of view. Erwin Panofsky notes that this faith in For Benjamin the tourist's appreciation of the world can perspective demonstrates an understanding of the world very only be a limited 'seeing', a vision that is only capable of different from our own, "for," he says, "the structure of an grasping part of , no matter how attentive it might be. infinite, unchanging and homogenous space [which perspec- Recognizing this fact, tourists today place increasing de- tive assumes to exist] is quite unlike the structure of mands on themselves in an attempt to 'get a feel' for places, psychophysiological space [as we understand it in the twen- to experience 'local flavor'. As Italo Calvino says, "the true tieth cent~ry]."~As this understanding began to emerge, it journey, as the introjection of an 'outside' different from our became clear that traditional, perspectival seeing could not normal one, implies a complete change of nutrition, a fully apprehend the world. Indeed, architectural theorists of digesting ofthe visited country This is the only kind oftravel the late nineteenth century (e.g. Semper, Ruskin, Morris and that has meaning nowadays, when everything visible you can Viollet-le-duc) asserted that architecture had to present see from your easy o hair."^ Such efforts, though certainly much more than a visual aspect, because no matter how rewarding, are not sufficient to hlly experience a place. In elegantly and precisely construed, a work of architecture the end the tourist is only by great effort extending simple held within it fundamental but ephemeral truths about the seeing into the realms of the other senses. Tourists who nature of its physical constitution, the that engen- 264 841H ACSA ANNUAL MEETING THEORY AND CRITICISM 1996 people that lived with it."y the early twentieth century this visual existence. Since the same body sees and touches, notion had helped to drastically alter architecture's scope. visible and tangible belong to the same world."" For example, in 1912 Robert Mallet-Stevens declared, "If a Bergson and Merleau-Ponty demonstrated that perspec- fastidiously drawn scale drawing, of a temple overloaded tival seeing can no longer be considered an adequate means withuseless columns can be mounted on a chassis and served of understanding the world. Because modem architecture up to the public classified as 'architecture', then a living insinuates itself into the world of our experience, perspec- room or kitchen, displayed as they really are, complete with tival seeing cannot form the basis of our experience of it. furniture and utensils, which they can move around in, can In his essay of 19 10, "Architecture," Adolf Loos asserted also be classified as architecture, and as living, animated as much: "the mark," he says, "of a building which is truly architecture, which will captivate and interest the visitor in established is that it remains ineffective in two dimen- another way."' Modem architecture had to be perceived in sions."14 Perspective and photography15 are incapable of action, not merely from a limited point of view. This remains adequately representing Loos' work because, to be under- true of architecture today. Perspectival seeing, like 'the stood, it must be appropriated, as Benjamin might say, by attentive concentration of the tourist,' cannot wholly appro- both " and use." According to Loos, an architect priate, nor can it adequately represent a building because it must supply much more than visual effects in a built work. presupposes a strictly limited experience of the world and "The room has to be comfortable," he says, "the house has thus dispenses with the complexities of tactility and the other to look habitable."16 Imbedded in these notions of comfort senses. and habitability is the same principle that underlies the 'tactile appropriation' that Benjamin tourists are VISION AND ACTION incapable of experiencing. Indeed what is 'habitability' but, Henri Bergson provides the basic framework for a modem quoting Benjamin, "appropriation accomplished not so much assertion that architecture must be appropriated, not merely by attention as by habit"? If a work of architecture is to be observed, tobe adequately understood. InMatterandMemory habitable it must satisfy vision, but it must also involve itself he demonstrates that no representational system can ad- fully with human actions equately describe reality; no individual sense can fully perceive it, because "there is in matter something more than APPRECIATING ART what is actually gi~en."~Contrary to what traditional per- Art, on the other hand, requires a fundamentally different spective assumes, perception happens not in ourselves, not kind of understanding. It remains separate from human in our eyes, but in a reciprocal relationship that our body action and, unlike architecture, resists appropriation. Ac- maintains with the world.9 "The objects which surround cording to Loos: [one's] body" he says, "reflect its possible action on them."1° Seeing and physical action become part of the same system "The work of art wants to draw people out oftheir state of appropriation. Thus a point of view and the "the distance of comfort. The house has to serve comfort. Man loves which separates [one's] body from an object perceived really everything that satisfies his comfort. He hates every- measures the greater or less imminence of danger, the nearer thing that wants to draw him out of this acquired and or more remote fulfillment of a promise."" Perspectival secured position and that disturbs him. Thus he loves seeing cannot fully appropriate the world because it fails to the house and hates art. Only a small part of architec- accommodate both vision and action, because it assumes, ture belongs to art: the tomb and the monument."" according to Panofsky, "that we see with a single immobile That people hate art may be questionable, but it is clear eye."I2 that art and architecture place fundamentally different de- Maurice Merleau-Ponty demonstrates the limitations of mands on people, that they require different sorts of attention this kind of seeing even more emphatically in his posthu- to comprehend them. mously published work, The Visible and the Invisible. In it According to Benjamin, a traditional work of art main- he declares: tains an aura about it-a "unique phenomenon of a dis- "[as] every experience of the visible has always been tance."'This distance, for at least, enforces purely given to me within the context of the movements of the visual appropriation. Indeed Benjamin asserts that the aura look, the visible spectacle belongs to the touch neither of art can be destroyed by tactile appropriation.I9To handle more nor less than do the 'tactile qualities.' We must a work of visual art is to do it violence. This is a lesson that habituate ourselves to thlnk that every visible is cut out every child understands on a first visit to the art : in the tangible, every tactile being in some manner works of art may be scrutinized, but they must not be promised to visibility, and that there is encroachment, touched. infringement, not only between the touched and the Such prohibitions appear difficult to sustain as touching, but also between the tangible and the visible, attempt to draw even the most mundane objects into their which is encrusted in it, as conversely, the tangible gamut; nevertheless, the relationship between people and itself is not a nothingness of visibility, is not without art has not changed substantially. This is because, accord- 84lH ACSA ANNUAL MEETING THEORY AND CRITICISM 1996 265 ing to , "what is interesting and essential in art fulfill their purpose.26They are fully absorbed in human is the spontaneous ability the has of enabling us to see action. For example, while a hammer concentrates muscular his way of seeing the world-not just the world as if the energy on the head of a nail it functions as an extension of the painting were like a window, but the world as given by hanckhus its handle-rather than a discrete element in the him."20 This seeing of someone else's vision enforces my process. It does not attempt to stand apart, distinct from distance from the art object because, no matter what my human action, as a work of art does. But Le Corbusier notes level of empathy with the artist, I am incapable of encroach- that by alleviating an individual of irksome or time-consum- ing on what is essential to the work. I can destroy the thing ing tasks, tools make available the time and energy neces- by handling it, but I cannot destroy the artist's vision of the sary for attentive contemplation of art.27He believed that it thing. Though this explanation is somewhat facile, it has is architecture's task to choreograph these actions. become clear that the limits of an art work lie not so much In the contemporary world, however, these distinctions in its physical constitution as in one's perception of it. This are often difficult to maintain, because the limits of art and is why, even though twentieth century artists have often of equipment are ill-defined. Modem equipment, or the introduced ordinary objects into artistic consideratio- technological device as Albert Borgmann calls it, has be- scraps ofnewspaper in the by Picasso and Braq~e,~' come so ubiquitous that virtually nothing demands our unaltered tools in the ready-mades of Duchamp, Brillo attentive concentrati~n.~~At the same time, as Benjamin boxes and Campbell's soup cans in 's work22- shows, the mechanical reproduction of art has dulled our the notion of 'distance' that establishes the limits of art is sensibility to it.29Contemporary critics of technology de- sustained. One appreciates these admittedly challenging spair of reversing this trend without a serious reconsideration works according to the same rules that people have always of our relationship with the world, with the equipment that appreciated art. While a snow shovel or a can of Campbell's we choose to assist in our interaction with it and with the soup would typically assume an unobtrusive position in the things that make it meaningful.30As Borgmann notes, "the array of things with which we become habituated in every- further technological liberation from the duress of daily life day existence, a certain inviolability and distance is con- is only leading to more disengagement from skilled and ferred upon them when they are placed within art's tradi- bodily commerce with reality. [New technologies] will fail tional milieus. In these works, as in all works of art, an aura to center and illuminate our lives their diversion will more separates the art object from the individual. A limit of and more lead to distraction, the scattering of our attention appropriation sustains the thing as art. This is what sepa- and the atrophy of our capacities."" What is required is not rates art from modem architecture. only a re-consideration of technology's role in modem life, but of the actions which constitute our existence and of the field upon which these actions take place. APPROPRIATING ARCHITECTURE For architects this means first of all defining the relation- Indeed one of the great of modem architecture ships that people form with architectural works. If, as was that it extended itselfbeyond the 'aura' ofart, beyond the Benjamin states, architecture is appropriated 'by use and limits of perspective and insinuated itself into ordinary perception'-that is, immediately or from a distance--when human habits and experience. This entirely changed the in a work of architecture are these best accommodated? scope of architecture, making it something different from According to Le Corbusier, architecture must open itself art. Certainly one can examine works of modem architecture to any number of human actions. In his scenario, a well attentively and from a distanceas art; however, to do so to designed room either disappears in human action or stands the exclusion of more visceral and temporal forms of appro- apart from it according one's immediate intentions: "We priation severely limits their potential value as architec- pick up a book or a pen. In this mechanical, discrete, silent, t~re.~'In The Decorative Art of Today Le Corbusier makes attentive comfort, there is a very fine painting on the wall. Or a crucial point about modern architecture that is often else: our movements take on a new assurance and precision overlooked in more recent works: architecture's "objec- among walls whose proportions make us happy, and whose tive," he says "is to create relationship^."^^ It sets in motion colors stimulate us."j2 In Loos' view, architecture distances the complementary play of art and the ordinary equipment itself from human action, as art does, only in the tomb and that makes life's tasks easier; in so doing it acts as a field for the monument. Unlike other architectural types, these en- meaningfbl human interaction with the world. force a distance between themselves and people which The distinction that Le Corbusier makes here between art precludes tactile or distracted appropriation. A house, on the and equipment is an important one. Equipment, though it can other hand, in order to be comfortable, requires, and indeed appear beautiful because of its evident refinement, does not implies habituation and tactile appropriation. demand appreciation the way art does.25In a sense it attempts Ultimately, then, architecture begins to take shape out of to accomplish a task precisely opposed to art: it insinuates a clear understanding of the human actions that join with it itself unobtrusively into human activity. According to Le and in the understanding that one does not merely appreciate Corbusier, tools and other equipment act as extensions of our architecture, but that one must appropriate it in the fullness limbs and efface themselves, disappearing from view as they of lived experince. 266 84TH ACSA ANNUAL MEETING THEORY AND CRITICISM 1996

NOTES their exterior aspect, with the result that physical relationships that lead to architectural appropriation were all but ignored I Walter Benjamin, "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical (witness for example Venturi's decorated boxes). Other recent Reproduction," Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt (New York: architectural works based on intellectual models derived from Schocken Books, 1969) 240. linguistics and literary criticism, though ostensibly critical of Italo Calvino, "Under the Jaguar Sun," Under the Jaguar Sun, post 's stylistic in their outlook, also tend trans. William Weaver(New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, to concentrate their energies on the visual aspects of buildings Publishers, 1986) 12. or their representations, largely ignoring the notions of habitu- Benjamin 240. ation and comfort that distinguish works of modem architec- Benjamin 240. ture from . Erwin Panofsky, Perspective as a Symbolic Form, trans. Chris- 24 Le Corbusier, The Decorative Art of Today, 1925, trans. James topher S. Wood (New York: Zone Books, 1991) 30-3 1. Dunnett (Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1987) For example, in "The Lamp of Truth" Ruskin says, "architec- 126. tural deceits can be broadly considered under three heads:- 25 The human-limb objects that Le Corbusier describes in The 1 st. The suggestion of a mode of structure or support, other than Decorative Art of Today are generally products of refinements the true one; as in pendants of late Gothic roofs. 2nd. The brought about by a culture or through processes of produc- painting of surfaces to represent some other material than that tion--of "mechanical selection." See Le Corbusier, chapter 6 of which it actually consists (as in the marbling ofwood), or the "Type-Needs Type-Fumiture."Thisprocessis well-documented deceptive of sculptured upon them. for a number of deviceslocks, chairs, kitchenein Siegfried 3rd. The use of cast or machine-made ornaments of any kind." Giedion, Mechanization Takes Command, (New York: W W John Ruskin, The Seven Lamps of Architecture, 1880 (New Norton & Company, 1948). See also Reyner Banham, Theory York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1989) 35. and Design in the First Machine Age (Cambridge, Massachu- Viollet-le-duc makes a similar point: "Once out of the way of setts: The MIT Press, 1986) 2 1 1. truth, architecture has been more and more mislead into degen- 26 Le Corbusier 72. erating paths. [it adopts] certain forms without analyzing them 27 "Happiness lies in the creative faculty, in the most elevated or recurring to their causes, seeing nothing but the effects, it has possible activity. For our comfort, to facilitate our work, to become Neo-Greek, Neo-Roman, Neo-Gothic" Eugene- avoid exhaustion, to refresh ourselves, in one word to free our Emmanuel Viollet-le-Duc, Lecture X, Lectures on Architec- spirit and distance us from the clutter that encumbers our life ture, Vol. I, 1877-1881, trans. Benjamin Bucknall (New York: and threatens to kill it, we have equipped ourselves through our Dover Publications, Inc., 1987) 447. ingenuity with human-limb objects, extensions of our limbs; Yvonne Brunharnmer, "Robert Mallet-Stevens as Interior Ar- and by making use of these tools, we avoid unpleasant tasks, chitect," Rob Mallet-Stevens, Architecte, ed. D. Deshoulieres accidents, the sterile drudgery, we organize our affairs and, and J. Janneau, trans. Susan Day (Brussels: Editions des having won our freedom, we think about something-about art Archives d' Architecture Modeme, 1980) 1 1 1-1 12. for example (for it is very comforting)." Le Corbusier 74-5. Henri Bergson, Matter and Memory, 1896, trans. N. M. Paul Borgmann describes the devices that make such a situation and W. S. Palmer (New York: Zone Books, 1991) 71. possible, and the process that engenders them as follows: "A Bergson 43. device such as the central heating plant procures mere warmth In Bergson 2 1. and disburdens us of all other elements. These are taken over by It Bergson 57. the machinery of the device. The machinery makes no demands l2 Panofsky 29. on our skill, strength or attention, and it is less demanding the l3 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, 1964, less it makes its presence felt. In the of technology, the ed. Claude Lefort, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: North- machinery of a device has therefor a tendency to become western University Press, 1968) 134. concealed or to shrink. Of all the physical properties of a device, l4 Adolf Loos, "Architecture," 1910, 106. those alone are crucial and prominent which constitute the l5 adheres to the same principles of experience as commodity that the device procures." Albert Borgmann, Tech- does perspective: the camera is the 'single eye' par excellence. nology and the Character of Contemporary Life: A Philosophi- '"00s 108. cal Inquiry (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984) l7 Loos 108. 42. '"enjamin 222. 29 Reproduction destroys the 'aura' of an artwork as much as l9 "to pry an object from its shell, to destroy its aura, is the mark handling it does, because it makes appropriation by habituation of a perception whose 'sense of the universal equality of things' virtually inevitable. To habituate one's self to a work of art is has increased to such a degree that it extracts it even from a to appropriate it in a non-visual way, which does violence to the unique object by means of reproduction." Benjamin 223. work of art as it is traditionally considered. Habituation be- 2n Arthur C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace: A comes possible, even inevitable, in the age of mechanical of Art (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard Uni- reproduction, because a work of art can be widely dissemi- versity Press, 1981) 207. nated, diminishing its uniqueness as well as its authority over 2' For a discussion of the invention of , see Christine particular circumstances. It can no longer command a particu- Poggi, In Defiance of Painting: , Futurism, and the lar point of view. "Even the most perfect reproduction of an Invention of CoNage, (New Haven: Yale University Press, object is lacking one element: its presence in time and space, its 1992). unique existence at the place where it happens to be." Benjamin mn 22 Danto discusses Duchamp's and Warhol's contribution to LLU. debates about the nature of art. See especially Chapter 2, 30 AS Calvin0 does above. "Content and Causation." 3' Borgmann 15 1. The promise of devices, for those who were 23 Unfortunately have recently made this sort of appre- experiencing them for the first time, was quite different be- ciation a major, even a primary, motivation in their work. This cause they made possible the attentive enjoyment of art on was the case for many so-called post-modem works of architec- one's own terms. Paul Valery emphasizes this point in "The ture, which concentrated a tremendous amount of energy on Conquest of Ubiquity" (Paul Valery, "The Conquest of Ubiq- 84THACSA ANNUAL MEETING THEORY AND CRITICISM 1996

uity", , Ralph Manheim, trans., (New York: Pan- finds the conditions essential to the most perfect aesthetic theon Books, 1964) 227-8): "[Formerly] we were dependent for returns." This is a true appreciation of equipment, but one our enjoyment on an occasion, a place, a date and a program. which requires an equal appreciation of art. In order to clearly How many coincidences were needed! Today we are liberated understand either art or equipment, we must recognize our from a servitude so contrary to pleasure and, by token, to the relationship with each and recognize the sort of appropriation most sensitive appreciation of . To be able to choose the that it demands. In order to appreciate works of art in an age of moment of enjoyment, to savor the pleasure when not only our mechanical reproduction, we must, like a tourist, sustain a level mind desires it, but our soul and whole being craves and as it of attentive concentration toward things while maintaining our were anticipates it, is to give fullest scope to the composer's distance from them. intention In recorded music the work of composer or performer 32 Le Corbusier 77.