Bibliography

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bibliography BIBLIOGRAPHY [1] Adam, Ch. and Tannery P. (eds.) Oevres de Descartes. Vrin, 1. IC.N.R .S ., Paris, 1964-1976. This is a revised version ofthe Cerfedition, published in 12 volumes, 1897 -1910. [2] Alexander, H.G . (ed.) The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence. Manchester University Press, Manchester, 1970. [3] Allison, H. E.(ed. and trans.) The Kant-Eberhard Contro versy . The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London, 1973. [4] Anapolitanos, D. A. "Leibniz on Dens ity and Sequential or Cauchy Completeness". In P. Nicolacopoulos (ed.) Greek Studies in the Philosophy and History ofScience. Boston Studies in the Philosophy ofScience. Kluwer Acad. Publ. , vol. 121, pp. 361­ 372, 1990. [5] Anderson, 1. L. Principles ofRelativity Physics. Academic Press, 1967 [6] Apostol, T.M. Math ematical Analysis:A modern Aproach to Advanced Calculus. Addison-Wesley Student Series Edition.Reading Massachusettes, Fifth Printing, 1971. [7] Ariew , R. and Garber, D. (eds . and trans .) Leibniz: Philosophical Essays. Hackett Publ. Co ., Indianapolis, Cambridge Mass., 1989. [8] Aristotle. Metaphysics. Jaeger, W. (ed.) Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1957. [9] Aristotle. Physics. Ross, W.D. (ed.). Oxford University Press, Oxford,1973. [10] Barbour, 1. B. "Relational Concepts ofSpace and Time". British Journalfor the Philosophy ofScience. vol. 33, pp. 251-274, 1982. [II] Barnes, J. (ed.) The Complete Works ofAristotle. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1984. [12] Brandom, R.B. "Leibniz and Degrees ofPerception". Journal ofthe History of Philosophy. vol. XIX, pp. 447-479, 1981. [13] Broad, C. D. "Leibniz's Last Controversy with the Newtonians". Theoria , vol. 12, pp . 143-168, 1946. [14] Broad, C.D. "Leibniz's Predicate-in-Notion Principle and Some of its Alleged Consequences". In H.G. Frankfurt (ed.) Leibniz:A collection ofCritical Essays. University ofNotre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1972, pp. 1-18. [15] Broad, C.D. Leibniz: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975 . [16] Brown,G. "Compossibility, Harmony and Perfection in Leibniz". The Philosophical Review, vol. XCVI, pp. 173-203 , 1987. [17] Buchdahl, G. Metaphysics and the Philosophy ofScience. The Classical Origins: Descartes to Kant . Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1969. [18] Burkhardt, H. and Degen,W. "Mereology in Leibniz's Logic and Philosophy". Topoi, vol. 9, pp . 3-13 , 1990. [19] Buchenau, A. (trans.) and Cassirer,E. (ed.) G. W. Leibniz: Philosophische Werke. In 2 volumes. Meiner, F. Leipzig, 1924. 175 176 BIBLIOGRAPHY [20] Cantor, G. Contributions to the Founding ofthe Theory ofTransfinite Numbers. Dover, New York, 1955. [21] Cassirer, E. Leibniz System in seinen wissenschaftlichen Grundlagen. N.G. Elwert, Marburg an der Lahn, 1902. [22] Chang, C. C. and Keisler, H. J. Model Theory. North Holland, Amsterdam, 1973. [23] Cottincham, 1. , Stoothoff, R . and Murdoch, D., (trans.) The Philosophical Writings ofDescartes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1984. [24] Couturat , L. (ed.) Opuscules etfragments inedits de Leibniz. In 2 volumes. Felix Alcan, Paris, 1903. [25] Couturat, L, La Logique de Leibniz d'apres documents inedits. Felix Alcan, Paris, 1901. [26] Couturat, L. "On Leibniz's Metaphysics". In H.G. Frankfurt (ed.) Leibniz:A Collection ofCritical Essays . University ofNotre Dame Press, Notre Dame , pp. 19-46, 1972 . [27] Duncan, G.M. (trans.) The Philosophical Works ofLeibniz. Second edition. Tuttle, Morehouse and Taylor Company, New Haven, 1908. [28] Earman, 1. "Who's Afraid ofAbsolute Space". Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 48, pp. 287-317, 1970. [29] Earman, 1. "Infinities, Infinitesimals and Indivisibles: The Leibnizian Labyrinth". Studia Leibnitiana , vol. VII, pp. 236-251, 1975. [30] Earman, J. "Perceptions and Relations in the Monadology". Studia Leibnitiana , vol. IX, pp. 212-230,1977. [31] Earman, J. World Enough and Space-Time. Absolute Versus Relational Theories ofSpace and Time. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts,1989. [32] Einstein, A. "Die formale Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitatstheorie", Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften , Berlin, Sitzungsberichte, pp. 831-839, 1914. [33] Einstein, A. "On The Electrodynamics ofMoving Bodies", 1905 Translated and reprinted in W . Perret and G. B. Jeffrey (ed .) The Principle ofRelativity. Dover, New York, pp. 37-65, 1952. [34] Einstein, A. "The Foundations ofthe General Theory ofRelativity", 1916. Translated and reprinted in W . Perret and G.B. Jeffrey (ed .) The Principle ofRelativity. Dover, New York, pp. 111-173, 1952. [35] Einstein, A. The Meaning ofRelativity. 5th edition. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1955. [36] Einstein, A. Relativity: The Special and the General Theory. Bonanza Books, New York, 1961. [37] Einstein, A. and Grossmann, M. "Entwurfeiner verallgemeinerten Relativitatstheorie und einer Theorie der Gravitation". Zeitschrijifur Mathematik und Physik, vol. 62, pp . 225-261,1913. BIBLIOGRAPHY 177 [38] Einstein, A. and Grossmann, M. "Kovarianzeigenschaften der Feldgleichungen der aufdie verallgemeinerte Relativitatstheory gegrundenten Gravitationstheorie", Zeitschriftfiir Mathematic und Physik, vol 63, pp. 215-225,1914. [39] Erdmann, I.E . (ed.) God. Guil. Leibnitii Opera Philosophica quae extant Latina, Gallica, Germanica Omnia. In 2 volumes, S.G. Eichleri, Berlin 1840. [40] Erlichson, H. 'The Leibniz-Clarke Controversy: Absolute Versus Relative Space and Time". American Journal ofPhysics, vol. 35, pp. 89-98, 1967. [41] Enderton, H. B. A Mathematical Introduction to Logic. Academic Press, New York,1977. [42] Enderton, H. B. Elements ofSet Theory . Academic Press, New York, 1977. [43] Farrer, A. (ed.) and Huggart, E.M., (trans.) G.w. Leibniz: Theodicy. Open Court, La Salle, 1985. [44] Fleming, N. "On Leibniz on Subject and Substance". The Philosophical Review, vol. XCVI , pp. 69-95, 1987. [45] Foucher, A. de Careil (ed.) Nouvelles lettres et opuscules inedits de Leibniz. A. Durand, Paris , 1857. [46] Fox, M. "Leibniz's Metaphysics ofSpace and Time". Studia Leibnitiana , vol. II, pp.29-55 , 1970. [47] Fraenkel, A.A. Abstract Set Theory. North Holland, Amsterdam, 1968. [48] Fraenkel, A. A. ,Bar-Hillel, Y. and Levy, A. Foundations ofSet Theory. North Holland, Amsterdam, 1973. [49] Frankfurt, H.G. (ed.) Leibniz: A Collection ofCritical Essays. University ofNotre Dame Press, Notre Dame, 1972. [50] Friedman, M. Foundations ofSpace-Time Theories. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1973. [51] Friedman, M. "Kant's Theory ofGeometry". The Philosophical Review, vol. XCIV, pp. 455-506, 1985 [52] Furth, M. "Monadology". In H.G. Frankfurt (ed.) Leibniz:A Collection ofCritical Essays, University ofNotre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp. 99-136, 1972. [53] Gale, G. "The Physical Theory ofLeibniz". Studia Leibnitiana, vol. II, pp.114­ 126, 1970. [54] Gale, R. M. (ed.) The Philosophy ofTime: A Collection ofEssays. Humanities Press, New Jersey, 1968. [55] Garber, D. "Leibniz and the Foundations ofPhysics: The Middle Years". In K. Okruhlik and J. B. Brown (eds.) The Natural Philosophy ofLeibniz, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 27-130, 1985. [56] Gavroglu, K. "Theoretical Frameworks for Theories ofGravitation: A Case ofa «Sui Generis» Research Program". Methodology and Science, vol. 19, pp. 91-123, 1986. [57] Gebhardt, C. (ed.) Spinoza Opera . In 4 volumes. Carl Winter, Heidelberg, 1925. 178 BIBLIOGRAPHY [58] Gerhardt, C. 1. (ed.) Leibnizens mathematische Schriften. In 7 volumes. Volumes 1-2 published by A. Asher and Co., Berlin, volumes 3-7 published by H.W. Schmidt, Halle, 1849-1863. [59] Gerhardt, C. 1.Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. In 7 volumes. Weidman, Berlin, 1875-1890 . [60] Grene, M. and Ravetz, 1.R. "Leibniz's Cosmic Equation: A Reconstruction". The Journal ofPhilosophy, vol. LIX, pp. 141-146, 1962. [61] Grua, G. (ed.) G.W. Leibniz: Textes inedits d'apres les Manuscripts de la Bibliotheque Provincial de Hanovre . Presses Universitaire de France, Paris, 1948. [62] Grunbaum, A. Philosophical Problems ofSpace and Time. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973. [63] Gueroult, M. Leibniz: Dynamique et Metaphysique. Aubier-Montaigne, Paris, 1967. [64] Gueroult, M. "Space, Point, and Void in Leibniz's Philosophy". In M. Hooker (ed.) Leibniz: Critical and Interpretative Essays, University ofMinnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp. 284-30I, 1982. [65] Haldane, E. and Ross , G. R. T. (eds. and trans .) The Philosophical Works of Descartes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1969. [66] Hall, A.R. Philoshophes at War. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1980. [67] Hartz, G.A. "Leibniz's Phenomenalisms". The Philosophical Review, vol. 101, pp. 511-549, 1992. [68] Hartz, G.A. and Cover, J. A. "Space and Time in the Leibnizian Metaphysic". Nous 22, pp. 493-519, 1988 [69] Heller, M. and Staruszkiewicz, A. "A Physicist's View on the Polemics between Leibniz and Clarke". Organon vol. II, pp. 205-213, 1975. [70] Hooker, C.A. "Relational Doctrines ofSpace and Time". British Journalfor the Philosophy ofScience, vol. 22, pp. 97-130, 1971. [71] Hooker, M. (ed.) Leihniz. Critical and interpretative Essays. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1982. [72] Hunter, G. "Monadic Relations". In K. Okruhlik and J. B. Brown (eds .) The Natural Philosophy of Leibniz, D. Reidel , Dordrecht, pp. 151-171, 1985. [73] Ishiguro, H. Leibniz 's Philosophy ofLogic and Language. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1972. [74] Ishiguro, H. "Leibniz's Theory ofthe Ideality of Relations". In H.G. Frarkfurt (ed.) Leibniz: A Collection ofCritical Essays . University ofNotre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp. 191-213,1972.
Recommended publications
  • On the Boundary Between Mereology and Topology
    On the Boundary Between Mereology and Topology Achille C. Varzi Istituto per la Ricerca Scientifica e Tecnologica, I-38100 Trento, Italy [email protected] (Final version published in Roberto Casati, Barry Smith, and Graham White (eds.), Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences. Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium, Vienna, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1994, pp. 423–442.) 1. Introduction Much recent work aimed at providing a formal ontology for the common-sense world has emphasized the need for a mereological account to be supplemented with topological concepts and principles. There are at least two reasons under- lying this view. The first is truly metaphysical and relates to the task of charac- terizing individual integrity or organic unity: since the notion of connectedness runs afoul of plain mereology, a theory of parts and wholes really needs to in- corporate a topological machinery of some sort. The second reason has been stressed mainly in connection with applications to certain areas of artificial in- telligence, most notably naive physics and qualitative reasoning about space and time: here mereology proves useful to account for certain basic relation- ships among things or events; but one needs topology to account for the fact that, say, two events can be continuous with each other, or that something can be inside, outside, abutting, or surrounding something else. These motivations (at times combined with others, e.g., semantic transpar- ency or computational efficiency) have led to the development of theories in which both mereological and topological notions play a pivotal role. How ex- actly these notions are related, however, and how the underlying principles should interact with one another, is still a rather unexplored issue.
    [Show full text]
  • The Joint Philosophical Program of Russell and Wittgenstein and Its Demise
    The Joint Philosophical Program of Russell and Wittgenstein and Its Demise Abstract Between April and November 1912, Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein were en- gaged in a joint philosophical program. Wittgenstein‘s meeting with Gottlob Frege in De- cember 1912 led, however, to its dissolution – the joint program was abandoned. Section 2 of this paper outlines the key points of that program, identifying what Russell and Wittgenstein each contributed to it. The third section determines precisely those features of their collabora- tive work that Frege criticized. Finally, building upon the evidence developed in the preced- ing two sections, section 4 recasts along previously undeveloped lines Wittgenstein‘s logical– philosophical discoveries in the two years following his encounter with Frege in 1912. The paper concludes, in section 5, with an overview of the dramatic consequences the Frege- Wittgenstein critique had for Russell‘s philosophical development. 1. Introductory Remarks The subject of our investigation is the interaction between the three founding fathers of analytic philosophy, Russell, Wittgenstein and Frege, in a most important period of their philosophical development. We discuss the joint program that Russell and Wittgenstein worked on from April till November 1912, as well as its collapse after Wittgenstein visited Frege in Jena in December the same year. Frege‘s criticism of elements of the program underpinned and motivated Wittgenstein‘s attack on Russell‘s approach in philosophy that culminated in May and June 1913 when, facing Wittgenstein‘s criticism, Russell stopped writing the Theory of Knowledge book project. Frege‘s arguments also urged Wittgenstein to rethink and reformulate his own philosophical ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract 1. Russell As a Mereologist
    THE 1900 TURN IN BERTRAND RUSSELL’S LOGIC, THE EMERGENCE OF HIS PARADOX, AND THE WAY OUT Prof. Dr. Nikolay Milkov, Universität Paderborn, [email protected] Abstract Russell‘s initial project in philosophy (1898) was to make mathematics rigorous reducing it to logic. Before August 1900, however, Russell‘s logic was nothing but mereology. First, his acquaintance with Peano‘s ideas in August 1900 led him to discard the part-whole logic and accept a kind of intensional predicate logic instead. Among other things, the predicate logic helped Russell embrace a technique of treating the paradox of infinite numbers with the help of a singular concept, which he called ‗denoting phrase‘. Unfortunately, a new paradox emerged soon: that of classes. The main contention of this paper is that Russell‘s new con- ception only transferred the paradox of infinity from the realm of infinite numbers to that of class-inclusion. Russell‘s long-elaborated solution to his paradox developed between 1905 and 1908 was nothing but to set aside of some of the ideas he adopted with his turn of August 1900: (i) With the Theory of Descriptions, he reintroduced the complexes we are acquainted with in logic. In this way, he partly restored the pre-August 1900 mereology of complexes and sim- ples. (ii) The elimination of classes, with the help of the ‗substitutional theory‘,1 and of prop- ositions, by means of the Multiple Relation Theory of Judgment,2 completed this process. 1. Russell as a Mereologist In 1898, Russell abandoned his short period of adherence to the Neo-Hegelian position in the philosophy of mathematics and replaced it with what can be called the ‗analytic philoso- phy of mathematics‘, substantiated by the logic of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereology and the Sciences SYNTHESE LIBRARY
    Mereology and the Sciences SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor-in-Chief LUCIANO FLORIDI, University of Oxford, Oxford Internet Institute, United Kingdom Editors THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen Fac. Philosophy, The Netherlands TEDDY SEIDENFELD, Carnegie Mellon University Dept. Philosophy, USA PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University Ctr. Study of Language & Information, USA JAN WOLEÑSKI, Jagiellonian University of Kraków Institute of Philosophy, Poland DIRK VAN DALEN, Utrecht University Department of Philosophy, The Netherlands VOLUME 371 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6607 Claudio Calosi Pierluigi Graziani Editors Mereology and the Sciences Parts and Wholes in the Contemporary Scientific Context 123 Editors Claudio Calosi Pierluigi Graziani Department of Basic Sciences and Department of Basic Sciences and Foundations Foundations University of Urbino University of Urbino Urbino Urbino Italy Italy ISBN 978-3-319-05355-4 ISBN 978-3-319-05356-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05356-1 Springer Cham Heidelberg New York Dordrecht London Library of Congress Control Number: 2014939928 c Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. Exempted from this legal reservation are brief excerpts in connection with reviews or scholarly analysis or material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work.
    [Show full text]
  • Plurals and Mereology
    Journal of Philosophical Logic (2021) 50:415–445 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09570-9 Plurals and Mereology Salvatore Florio1 · David Nicolas2 Received: 2 August 2019 / Accepted: 5 August 2020 / Published online: 26 October 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In linguistics, the dominant approach to the semantics of plurals appeals to mere- ology. However, this approach has received strong criticisms from philosophical logicians who subscribe to an alternative framework based on plural logic. In the first part of the article, we offer a precise characterization of the mereological approach and the semantic background in which the debate can be meaningfully reconstructed. In the second part, we deal with the criticisms and assess their logical, linguistic, and philosophical significance. We identify four main objections and show how each can be addressed. Finally, we compare the strengths and shortcomings of the mereologi- cal approach and plural logic. Our conclusion is that the former remains a viable and well-motivated framework for the analysis of plurals. Keywords Mass nouns · Mereology · Model theory · Natural language semantics · Ontological commitment · Plural logic · Plurals · Russell’s paradox · Truth theory 1 Introduction A prominent tradition in linguistic semantics analyzes plurals by appealing to mere- ology (e.g. Link [40, 41], Landman [32, 34], Gillon [20], Moltmann [50], Krifka [30], Bale and Barner [2], Chierchia [12], Sutton and Filip [76], and Champollion [9]).1 1The historical roots of this tradition include Leonard and Goodman [38], Goodman and Quine [22], Massey [46], and Sharvy [74]. Salvatore Florio [email protected] David Nicolas [email protected] 1 Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, United Kingdom 2 Institut Jean Nicod, Departement´ d’etudes´ cognitives, ENS, EHESS, CNRS, PSL University, Paris, France 416 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Asya Passinsky
    Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Asya Passinsky Visiting Assistant Professor, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill “NORM AND OBJECT: A NORMATIVE HYLOMORPHIC THEORY OF SOCIAL OBJECTS” Thursday, March 4, 2021, 5:00-6:00 pm Via Zoom Draft, February 19, 2021. For UCLA Workshop. Please Don’t Cite Or Quote Without Permission. Norm and Object: A Normative Hylomorphic Theory of Social Objects Asya Passinsky ABSTRACT: This paper is an investigation into the metaphysics of social objects such as political borders, states, and organizations. I articulate a metaphysical puzzle concerning such objects and then propose a novel account of social objects that provides a solution to the puzzle. The basic idea behind the puzzle is that under appropriate circumstances, seemingly concrete social objects can apparently be created by acts of agreement, decree, declaration, or the like. Yet there is reason to believe that no concrete object can be created in this way. The central idea of my positive account is that social objects have a normative component to them, and seemingly concrete social objects have both normative and material components. I develop this idea more rigorously using resources from the Aristotelian hylomorphic tradition. The resulting normative hylomorphic account, I argue, solves the puzzle by providing a satisfying explanation of creation-by-agreement and the like, while at the same time avoiding the difficulties facing extant accounts of social objects. 1. Introduction This paper is an investigation into the metaphysics of social objects such as political borders, states, and organizations. Roughly speaking, social objects are things that can be created through the performance of social acts such as agreement, decree, declaration, or the like.
    [Show full text]
  • Mereology Then and Now
    Logic and Logical Philosophy Volume 24 (2015), 409–427 DOI: 10.12775/LLP.2015.024 Rafał Gruszczyński Achille C. Varzi MEREOLOGY THEN AND NOW Abstract. This paper offers a critical reconstruction of the motivations that led to the development of mereology as we know it today, along with a brief description of some questions that define current research in the field. Keywords: mereology; parthood; formal ontology; foundations of mathe- matics 1. Introduction Understood as a general theory of parts and wholes, mereology has a long history that can be traced back to the early days of philosophy. As a formal theory of the part-whole relation or rather, as a theory of the relations of part to whole and of part to part within a whole it is relatively recent and came to us mainly through the writings of Edmund Husserl and Stanisław Leśniewski. The former were part of a larger project aimed at the development of a general framework for formal ontology; the latter were inspired by a desire to provide a nominalistically acceptable alternative to set theory as a foundation for mathematics. (The name itself, ‘mereology’ after the Greek word ‘µρoς’, ‘part’ was coined by Leśniewski [31].) As it turns out, both sorts of motivation failed to quite live up to expectations. Yet mereology survived as a theory in its own right and continued to flourish, often in unexpected ways. Indeed, it is not an exaggeration to say that today mereology is a central and powerful area of research in philosophy and philosophical logic. It may be helpful, therefore, to take stock and reconsider its origins.
    [Show full text]
  • A Formal Mereology of Potential Parts
    Not Another Brick in the Wall: an Extensional Mereology for Potential Parts Contents 0. Abstract .................................................................................................................................................................................................. 1 1. An Introduction to Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................... 1 2. The Physical Motivation for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................................ 5 3. A Model for Potential Parts .................................................................................................................................................................... 9 3.1 Informal Semantics: Dressed Electron Propagator as Mereological Model ...................................................................................... 9 3.2 Formal Semantics: A Join Semi-Lattice ............................................................................................................................................ 10 3.3 Syntax: Mereological Axioms for Potential Parts ............................................................................................................................ 14 4. Conclusions About Potential Parts .......................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Handbook of Mereology Total
    Simons, P., 1987. Part I is a standard The notion of structure is of central im- reference for extensional mereology. portance to mereology (for the following Parts II and III treat further topics and see also Koslicki 2008, ch. IX). Histori- question some assumptions of extension- cal contributions had this clearly in view; ality. Has an extensive bibliography. for example, as is brought out in Harte 2002, Plato in numerous dialogues grap- ples with the question of how a whole References and further readings which has many parts can nevertheless be a single unified object and ultimately Cartwright, R., 1975, “Scattered Ob- endorses a structure-based response to jects”, as reprinted in his Philosophical this question (see Plato). Wholes, ac- Essays, 1987, Cambridge, MIT Press: cording to Plato’s mature views (as de- 171-86. veloped primarily in the Sophist, Par- Lewis, D., 1991, Parts of Classes, Ox- menides, Philebus and Timaeus), have a ford: Blackwell. dichotomous nature, consisting of both material as well as structural compo- Sanford, D. H., 2003, “Fusion Confu- nents; it is the job of structure to unify sion”, Analysis 63: 1-4. and organize the plurality of material Sanford, D. H., 2011, “Can a sum change parts that are present in a unified whole. its parts?”, Analysis 71: 235-9. A similar conception is taken up and worked out further by Aristotle who Simons, P., 1987, Parts: A Study in On- famously believed that ordinary material tology, Oxford: Clarendon Press. objects, such as houses, are compounds Tarski, A., 1929, “Foundations of the of matter (viz., the bricks, wood, etc.) Geometry of Solids” as reprinted in his and form (viz., the arrangement exhibited Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, by the material components for the pur- Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1959: pose of providing shelter).
    [Show full text]
  • Unifying Three Notions of Concepts∗ Scientists Use ‘Concept’ to Refer to Word Types (As Opposed of Word Tokens)
    Edward N. Zalta 2 If the notion of concept used in cognitive science doesn't fall among the three notions just mentioned, then I believe it can be analyzed in some other way within object theory. For example, I think some cognitive Unifying Three Notions of Concepts∗ scientists use `concept' to refer to word types (as opposed of word tokens). If that is what they mean, then there is a way to analyze that notion in object theory, namely, by taking types (e.g., word types, sentence symbols Edward N. Zalta and, in general, symbol types) to be the abstract objects that encode just Center for the Study of Language and Information the defining properties exemplified by the tokens of that type. At other Stanford University times, cognitive scientists use `concept' to mean certain mental tokens, [email protected] possibly mental tokens in some language of thought. If that is what they mean, then object theory would analyze only the content of those tokens as Fregean senses, i.e., in terms the second notion of concept that arises There isn't universal agreement as to what `concept' means. Indeed, from Frege's work. So I hope that the notion of concept used by the the present discussion might seem circular, since it may come across as cognitive scientists will be covered in what follows. an investigation into the concept of `concept' and so presupposes an un- derstanding of the technical term concept. But I'll try to avoid circularity in what follows by considering how certain primitive entities, or entities 1 Frege's Notion of Begriff known under a different name, could reasonably be called `concepts'.
    [Show full text]
  • Strange Parts: the Metaphysics of Non-Classical Mereologies
    Philosophy Compass 8/9 (2013): 834–845, 10.1111/phc3.12061 Strange Parts: The Metaphysics of Non-classical Mereologies A. J. Cotnoir* University of St Andrews Abstract The dominant theory of parts and wholes – classical extensional mereology – has faced a number of challenges in the recent literature. This article gives a sampling of some of the alleged counterexam- ples to some of the more controversial principles involving the connections between parthood and identity. Along the way, some of the main revisionary approaches are reviewed. First, counterexam- ples to extensionality are reviewed. The ‘supplementation’ axioms that generate extensionality are examined more carefully, and a suggested revision is considered. Second, the paper considers an alternative approach that focuses the blame on antisymmetry but allows us to keep natural supplementation axioms. Third, we look at counterexamples to the idempotency of composition and the associated ‘parts just once’ principle. We explore options for developing weaker mereologies that avoid such commitments. 1. Introduction The smallest bits of matter – the bosons and fermions of microphysics – are parts of larger material objects – the wholes of our everyday macrophysical experience. The formal study of this relation is called mereology. But the notion of parthood is notoriously puzzling.1 Witness van Inwagen, All, or almost all, of the antinomies and paradoxes that the philosophical study of material objects is heir to involve the notion of parthood ...[M]ost of the great, intractable metaphysical puzzles about material objects could be seen to have quite obvious solutions by one who had a clear understanding of what it was for one material object to be a part of another.
    [Show full text]
  • Matter and Mereology∗
    Matter and mereology∗ Jeremy Goodman Draft of March 22, 2015 I am a material thing. But I am not the same thing as the matter out of which I am composed, since my matter, unlike me, could have existed as scattered interstellar dust. The distinction between matter and objects that are merely composed of matter is central to our ordinary conception of the material world. According to that conception, material objects have a hierarchical structure with matter at its foundation. This paper shows how matter and material constitution can be understood in terms of the part-whole relation.1 I present a novel mereology and apply it to debates about the persistence and plenitude of material objects, and compare my view to more familiar hylomorphic ones. A formal model of the theory is given in an appendix. 1 Anti-symmetry Consider the following principle: weak supplementation: If x is a proper part of y, then y has a part that does not overlap x. where x is a proper part of y =df x is a part of y and x 6= y. x overlaps y =df some part of x is part of y. Everyday cases of material coincidence are counterexamples to weak supple- mentation. A statue s composed of some clay c. c is distinct from s, since squashing c would destroy s but would not destroy c.2 c is part of s, since any ∗Thanks to Andrew Bacon, Cian Dorr, Maegan Fairchild, Kit Fine, Peter Fritz, John Hawthorne, Harvey Lederman, Gabriel Uzquiano, Tim Williamson and an anonymous referee for No^us for comments on previous versions of this paper, and to an audience at the University of Cambridge.
    [Show full text]