Glossary Ethics in Epidemiology and Public Health I. Technical Terms

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Glossary Ethics in Epidemiology and Public Health I. Technical Terms J Epidemiol Community Health: first published as 10.1136/jech.55.12.855 on 1 December 2001. Downloaded from J Epidemiol Community Health 2001;55:855–857 855 Glossary Ethics in epidemiology and public health I. Technical terms D L Weed, R E McKeown Ethics in epidemiology and public health has Beneficence (see also: Prima facie, Principles emerged from several sources: most obvious is and Principlism, Utility and Utilitarianism) the discipline of bioethics, with its theories, Literally, doing good; in bioethics, a prima facie methods, case studies, and familiar textbooks. principle underlying utilitarian approaches. Bioethics has primarily been focused upon Implies an obligation to promote benefits of medical ethics and research ethics and only things judged to be good, typically balancing recently has turned its attention to public produced goods against risks or harms. In pub- health. Another source of scholarship is philo- lic health, beneficence implies acting in the best sophical ethics. Here the sourcebooks are the interest of the population or society as a writings of Aristotle, Kant, Mill, Rawls, and whole.56 many others, the so called “high ground” philosophers of the past 2000 years.1 Philo- Bioethics (see also: Ethics) A field of inquiry and academic discipline at sophical ethics provides a rich lode from which 7 to mine theories and concepts and to observe the intersection of ethics and the life sciences. intellectual trends. A third source for ethics in Emerging with an emphasis upon problems epidemiology and public health is closer to faced in the practice of medicine and biomedi- home and is not so closely connected to cal research, bioethics has overlapping areas of bioethics nor philosophical ethics. Public scholarship and application: theory and health practitioners and scholars have written method, clinical practice, regulatory policy, research practice, cultural and social concerns,8 about the ethical problems that underlie 9 professional practice. Advocacy, coercion, and and recently, public health and epidemiology. scientific misconduct are a few representative Case or Case study (see also: Casuistry) examples, but there are many others, including A detailed description of a concrete situation privacy, conflicts of interest, and the rights of requiring ethical analysis and a resultant judg- vulnerable communities. ment or action. Cases provide specific circum- Given the scope and connectedness of these stances involving a patient (in medical ethics), sources, a vast number of words and phrases a study participant or group (in research http://jech.bmj.com/ could be included in a glossary on ethics in ethics) or a population (in public health epidemiology and public health. To organise ethics). Cases are typically grouped by subject what could be a very long list, we identify two matter and as such represent the input to the categories of terms. There are the more techni- methods of practical ethical reasoning.10 cal terms of ethics, such as casuistry, commu- nitarian ethics, obligations, and virtues. These Casuistry (see also: Case or Case study, we define below in the first installment of the Principles and Principlism, Specification) glossary. There are also more applied terms— A method of practical ethical reasoning empha- equipoise, informed consent, privacy and the sising particular cases over theories or princi- on October 3, 2021 by guest. Protected copyright. precautionary principle—representing impor- ples. From paradigm cases and the selection of tant practical issues with significant ethical morally relevant maxims indicating the right content. These will appear in a second install- judgment or action, the user of casuistry finds ment. As the discipline of public health ethics generalisable guidance for judgments and matures, we expect to see many other terms actions when confronted with similar cases. surface. More importantly, we hope to see Casuistry is not incompatible with the methods OYce of Preventive more scholarly discussions of ethical issues. of principlism and specified principlism.11–13 Oncology, Division of Cancer Prevention, Communitarian ethics National Cancer Autonomy (see also: Respect for Persons) An approach to ethics emphasising communal Institute, EPS T-41, Literally, self ruling. Related to, and sometimes values, the common good, social goals, and 6130 Executive Blvd, used in lieu of the bioethical principle of Bethesda, MD traditional practices. Closely aligned with the 20892–7105, USA respect for persons. Implies intentionality and cooperative virtues and a community’s shared freedom from coercion. In the Kantian tradi- understanding of the good life. Often pitted Correspondence to: tion, autonomy implies freely embracing a against liberal individualism (that is, rights- Dr Weed ([email protected]) moral obligation.2 In public health, individual based approaches) in its militant forms, a Accepted for publication autonomy may be limited by interventions moderate communitarian view makes room for 13 June 2001 applied to populations.34 individual rights.41415 www.jech.com J Epidemiol Community Health: first published as 10.1136/jech.55.12.855 on 1 December 2001. Downloaded from 856 Weed,McKeown Deontological (see also: Respect for persons) Respect for persons (see also: Autonomy, A duty-based theoretical approach to ethics, Deontological, Prima facie, Principles and associated with the philosopher Kant. Right Principlism) actions stem from freely embraced obligations A prima facie principle in bioethics underlying to universal moral imperatives, such as the the obligation for informed consent in research obligation to respect persons as ends and not as and decisions regarding study design and means.25 interventions. From the Kantian tradition: per- sons should be treated as ends in themselves and not as means to an end. Implies two Ethics (see also: Bioethics) distinct moral requirements: acknowledge au- A philosophical discipline concerned with tonomy and protect those with diminished understanding how human beings should act, autonomy.46 what is good, and what kind of life is best. Rights Justice (see also: Prima facie, Principles and Justified claims made by individuals or groups Principlism) upon others and based on a system of rules In bioethics, a prima facie principle implying authorising us to aYrm or demand what is due. equity or fairness, especially regarding the fair Possessing a right validly constrains others distribution in the population of benefits and from interfering with the exercise of that right. risks of research, health care, or other goods. Moral rights are claims justified by moral prin- Contrasted with retributive justice operating in ciples and are correlated with obligations. In the criminal justice system.16 17 public health, a broadly defined set of human rights are often asserted.19 20 21 Non-maleficence (see also: Beneficence, Prima Specification (see also: Principles and facie, Principles and Principlism) Principlism) Literally, not causing harm. A prima facie A methodological technique for interpreting a principle in bioethics, sometimes subsumed more general ethical principle to bring its under the principle of beneficence. An obliga- implications closer to—to better “apply” it tion traditionally at the heart of medical to—actions and decisions. Specification may ethics—the “first do no harm” component of be used to resolve conflicts among, to balance, the Hippocratic Oath—non-maleficence can or to rank principles. In public health, the Pre- be seen as distinct from the obligation to cautionary Principle is a specified version of produce good. the more general principle of beneficence.12 22 23 Obligation (see also: Principles and Utility and Utilitarian Principlism, Rights) An approach to ethics asserting that one should Used interchangeably with duty. That which is always strive to produce the greatest possible required, although tempered by competing balance of good over harm. Historically, identi- duties. Obligations are correlated with rights. fied with social reform movements of 18th In epidemiology and public health, profes- century England. Classically expressed as the sional role obligations derive from basic ethical obligation to produce the greatest good for the principles and are articulated in codes of greatest number; more recent accounts empha- http://jech.bmj.com/ professional conduct. sise optimisation of benefits and harms.42021 Prima facie (see also: Principles and Values Principlism, Specification) Concepts used to explain how and why things A term used to describe bioethical principles as matter. Values are involved wherever we distin- neither rules of thumb nor absolute prescrip- guish between things good and bad, better or tions but rather as binding in all cases unless an worse. Values are characterised as scientific, obligation found in one principle conflicts with professional, cultural, social, personal, family, on October 3, 2021 by guest. Protected copyright. another. In such situations, balancing of religious, and organic (for example, health). competing principles is undertaken using the Scientific values include: objectivity, accuracy, technique of specification.18 generalisability, validity and others. Values are pervasive in epidemiology and public health.24–26 Principles and Principlism (see also: Beneficence, Justice, Nonmaleficence, Prima Virtues facie, Respect for Persons, Specification) Character traits—not skills nor techniques— Four prima facie principles remain at the cen- that make an individual a good professional tre of education
Recommended publications
  • A Philosophical Investigation of Principlism and the Implications Raised by the Treatment of the Mentally Ill
    Aporia vol. 24 no. 1—2014 A Philosophical Investigation of Principlism and the Implications Raised by the Treatment of the Mentally Ill BENJAMIN FOSTER Introduction he objective of this investigation is to identify reasonable and relevant problems and issues posed for Principlism by the mentally T ill. Two concepts of Principlism will be presented: a normative con- ceptualization of the bioethical theory and a descriptive conceptualization. In reference to both, two philosophical questions will be asked: can we know the natures of other minds and, if so, how? These two questions have theoretical and practical implications for the treatment of the mentally ill. And, in so far as the questions have implications for the treatment of the mentally ill, they have implications for the bioethical theory of Principlism. There is a lack of concurrence on the meaning, nature, and function of mental phenomena, producing conceptual difficulties concerning the common morality that provides Principlism its normative authority. Similarly, a contradiction appears to arise when one considers the imaginative leap of predicting another’s desires, feelings, and thoughts, a maneuver that professionals participating in the treatment of the mentally ill must perform. There is also significant ambiguity surrounding the concept of mental illness, which produces pragmatic problems when professionals attempt to diagnose and treat an individual in conjunction Benjamin Foster graduated with a degree in philosophy and a minor in biology from the University of Alaska Fairbanks. While there he served as president of the univer- sity’s philosophy club, The Socratic Society. His primary philosophical interests include ethics and epistemology. He currently plans to attend medical school.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Ethical Reasoning in Design Through the Lens of Reflexive Principlism
    Paper ID #23427 Understanding Ethical Reasoning in Design Through the Lens of Reflexive Principlism Danielle Corple, Purdue University, West Lafayette Danielle Corple is a Ph.D. student in the Brian Lamb School of Communication at Purdue University. She studies organizational communication as well as qualitative and computational research methods. Her specific research interests are gender, organizing, and ethics in online and offline contexts. Mr. David H. Torres, Purdue University, West Lafayette David is a fourth year doctoral candidate in the Brian Lamb School of Communication at Purdue Uni- versity pursuing a PhD in Organizational Communication with a minor in data analysis and research methodology. His research interests reside at the intersection of organizational communication, identity, design, and organizational ethics. Dr. Carla B. Zoltowski, Purdue University, West Lafayette Carla B. Zoltowski is an assistant professor of engineering practice in the Schools of Electrical and Com- puter Engineering and (by courtesy) Engineering Education at Purdue University. She holds a B.S.E.E., M.S.E.E., and Ph.D. in Engineering Education, all from Purdue. Prior to this she was Co-Director of the EPICS Program at Purdue where she was responsible for developing curriculum and assessment tools and overseeing the research efforts within EPICS. Her academic and research interests include the profes- sional formation of engineers, diversity and inclusion in engineering, human-centered design, engineering ethics, leadership, service-learning, and accessibility and assistive-technology. Katharine E. Miller Katharine E. Miller is a second-year doctoral student studying Organizational Communication and Public Relations at Purdue University, with minors in corporate social responsibility and research methods.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Health Principlism Craig M
    Online Journal of Health Ethics Volume 4 | Issue 1 Article 4 Public Health Principlism Craig M. Klugman Ph.D. Department of Health Ecology/MS 274; Nevada Center for Ethics and Health Policy Follow this and additional works at: http://aquila.usm.edu/ojhe Recommended Citation Klugman, C. M. (2007). Public Health Principlism. Online Journal of Health Ethics, 4(1). http://dx.doi.org/10.18785/ojhe.0401.04 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Aquila Digital Community. It has been accepted for inclusion in Online Journal of Health Ethics by an authorized administrator of The Aquila Digital Community. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Running head: PUBLIC HEALTH 1 Public Health Principlism Craig M. Klugman, Ph.D. Assistant Professor Department of Health Ecology/MS 274 Nevada Center for Ethics and Health Policy Reno, Nevada 89557-0036 Abstract Public health ethics has grown out of the medical ethics movement and has remained in individualistic biomedical models. However, as public health is a different enterprise than medicine dealing with communities rather than individuals. The author develops public health principlism based on the idea of common citizenship in the community. When the four principles of public health ethics—solidarity, efficacy, integrity, and dignity—are in balance, a state of justice exists. The goal is to have programs that are the least destructive to communities and the least restrictive to people. These principles provide guidance in ethical reasoning when analyzing programs and interventions such as mandatory helmet laws, water fluoridation, and smallpox vaccination to improve the aggregate health of a community.
    [Show full text]
  • A Conscience Sensitive Approach to Teaching Caring Attitude
    A CONSCIENCE SENSITIVE APPROACH TO ETHICS AND TEACHING CARING ATTITUDES IN MEDICAL EDUCATION MARGARET GAFFNEY MD CLINICAL ASSOCIATE PROFESSOR INDIANA UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF MEDICINE Conscience Centered Medical Ethics • Augments and expands upon the principles and theories • Identifies 5 domains of conscience • Bedrock value for each domain • Principles do not take into account moral connections or moral emotions • Conscience language allows the actor to locate self directly in the action or question • Helps address medical mistakes, reparation, forgiveness, and healing of self and others • Takes account of the moral relationships between patients and families, patients and providers, and providers with each other. CONSCIENCE PROJECT Conscience Programs Conscience Research Conscience Teaching Conscience Sensitive Treatment CONSCIENCE THEORY Conscience Theory Stages Domains Intrinsic Values • invariant hierarchical stages • interdependent developmental domains • intrinsic values CONSCIENCE STAGES STAGE I EXTERNALIZED CONSCIENCE Age 6 and Under STAGE II BRAIN OR HEART CONSCIENCE AGES 7 -11 BRAIN CONSCIENCE Age 11 HEART CONSCIENCE Ages 12-13 STAGE III: PERSONIFIED CONSCIENCE Age 10 PERSONIFIED CONSCIENCE #2 Age 12 STAGE IV CONFUSED CONSCIENCE Ages 14-15 CONFUSED CONSCIENCE #2 Age 15 CONFUSED CONSCIENCE #3 Age 15 STAGE V INTEGRATED CONSCIENCE #2 Age 17 CONSCIENCE DOMAINS Domains and Values • Conceptualization: meaning • Attachment: connectedness • Emotional responsiveness: balance • Valuation: worth • Volition: freedom CONCEPTUALIZATION OF CONSCIENCE
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories
    A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Gavin G. Enck June 2009 © 2009 Gavin G. Enck. All Rights Reserved. 2 This thesis titled A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories by GAVIN G. ENCK has been approved for the Department of Philosophy and the College of Arts and Sciences by Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy Benjamin M. Ogles Dean, College of Arts and Sciences 3 ABSTRACT ENCK, GAVIN G., M.A., June 2009, Philosophy A Comparison of Two Bioethical Theories (81 pp.) Director of Thesis: Arthur Zucker This thesis compares two bioethical theories in order to determine which theory is better for use by medical professionals. The two theories are Tom L. Beauchamp and James Childress’s “Principlism” and Bernard Gert, K. Danner Clouser, and Charles M. Culver’s “Moral Rules.” The structure of the paper is as follows: an explication of both theories, an examination of the similarities and differences between the theories, an evaluation of criticisms of both theories, and identification of the three advantages the Moral Rules theory has over Principlism. In the conclusion, I claim the Moral Rules is the better bioethical theory for the medical profession. Approved: _____________________________________________________________ Arthur Zucker Associate Professor of Philosophy 4 TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Abstract ..............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons of Reproductive Ethics for Principlism
    Lessons of Reproductive Ethics for Principlism Morten Dige Department of Philosophy and History of Ideas, Aarhus University, [email protected] DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v13i1.2726 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. This article brings together two debates in bioethics more substantively than has been the case until now. One is the methodological debate over “principlism,” i.e., the theoretical framework for analyzing and solving (bio)ethical problems proposed by Beauchamp and Childress in Principles of Biomedical Ethics (PBE). The other is the normative debate about reproductive ethics, i.e., procreative rights and obligations in a time of pervasive opportunities for making detailed choices about the properties and capacities of future people. The obvious point of bringing the debates together is to show how they can illuminate each other in fruitful ways consistent with the method of reflective equilibrium endorsed in PBE. Furthermore, discussions of reproductive ethics is almost absent in PBE, making it an interesting “test case” on how principlist theory can have an impact on and be affected by confrontations with new practices and considerations in biomedicine. Reproductive ethics is especially interesting due to the so-called non-identity considerations, which pose a challenge to common morality views on harm to and respect for persons. My focus is mainly on some methodological points about the import of concrete normative discussions for formulating basic normative principles.
    [Show full text]
  • LIB 63.3 06. Mathiesen 427–447 Copy.Indd
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Illinois Digital Environment for Access to Learning and... Toward a Political Philosophy of Information Kay Mathiesen Abstract Many of the most pressing issues in information ethics—informational privacy, surveillance, intellectual property, access to information, and the distribution of information resources—can only be addressed at the level of global politics. This paper develops an approach to theorizing about political questions of concern to information ethics. It begins by situating a political philosophy of information within the broader field of ethics and defending a theoretical approach that is practical, person-centered, and pluralistic. The method of dialogic public reason, as articulated by John Rawls and supplemented with insights from Jürgen Habermas, is described and defended. It is argued that dialogic public reason provides a way to justify political principles in a diverse global context. The paper concludes by relat- ing the idea of dialogic public reason to international human rights. The putative human right to intellectual property is criticized on the grounds that it does not pass the test of public reason. Introduction Information ethics is the study of normative questions related to the cre- ation, preservation, organization, access, presentation, and control of in- formation; it addresses such concerns as “equity of access to information, intellectual freedom, information privacy and confidentiality, and intellec- tual
    [Show full text]
  • Humanity at the Heart of Practice
    Humanity at the Heart of Practice Humanity at the Heart of Practice: A Study of Ethics for Health- Care Students and Practitioners By Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander Humanity at the Heart of Practice: A Study of Ethics for Health-Care Students and Practitioners By Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander This book first published 2019 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2019 by Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-3280-1 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-3280-9 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction to the Text .............................................................................. 1 Section One: Values and Practical Reasoning Chapter 1 .................................................................................................... 6 Values Introduction Ethical Decisions are Similar to Clinical Decisions Community Values Personal Values Seeking the Principle-based Action Student Starters and Submissions Outline Terminology Chapter 2 .................................................................................................. 13 Practical Reasoning Introductions to
    [Show full text]
  • Making Environmental Ethics More Practical: a Model of Principlism
    4 MAKING ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS MORE PRACTICAL: A MODEL OF PRINCIPLISM Juan Alberto Lecaros Urzúa & Gonzalo López Gaete Abstract: Environmental Ethics is a type of applied ethic whose objec- tive is to guide, using principles and rules, the analysis, the deliberation, and the resolution of conflicts that are environmental and social at the same time. Within the different theoretical approaches of Environmental Ethics, there is a tension between normative ethical level and the meth- odological level that prevents integration between the two of them. The problem of Environmental Ethics to reconcile these two orders is the issue addressed in this paper. Our proposal regarding this subject is to approach it from a theoretical strategy of mid-level principles and this is why it does not aim at suggesting a theoretical foundation of ethics, but a referential framework that makes a pluralistic outline of principles compatible with a well-defined methodology of rules and meta-rules, thus contributing to a more practical Environmental Ethics. Keywords: environmental ethics, socio-environmental conflicts, mid- level principles, framework principle, derivative principles, strategic principles, environmental citizenship. Ramon Llull Journal_09.indd 95 6/6/18 9:40 96 RAMON LLULL JOURNAL OF APPLIED ETHICS 2018. issue 9 pp. 95-116 1. INTRODUCTION We start from the premise that Environmental Ethics (EE) is a type of applied ethics whose objective is to guide, using principles and rules, the analysis, the deliberation, and the resolution of conflicts that are en- vironmental and social. With this purpose, two aspects of a different order must be made compatible: the normative ethical level and the methodological level.
    [Show full text]
  • Identity, Personhood and Power
    Identity, personhood and power: a critical analysis of the principle of respect for autonomy and the idea of informed consent, and their implementation in an androgynous and multicultural society Dr Theresa Marié Rossouw Dissertation presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at Stellenbosch University Promotor: Prof AA van Niekerk March 2012 Stellenbosch University http://scholar.sun.ac.za DECLARATION By submitting this dissertation electronically, I declare that the entirety of the work contained therein is my own, original work, that I am the authorship owner thereof (unless to the extent explicitly otherwise stated) and that I have not previously in its entirety or in part submitted it for obtaining any qualification. Signature: Date: March 2012 Copyright © 2012 Stellenbosch University All rights reserved 2 Stellenbosch University http://scholar.sun.ac.za Abstract Autonomy and informed consent are two interrelated concepts given much prominence in contemporary biomedical discourse. The word autonomy, from the Greek autos (self) and nomos (rule), originally referred to the self-governance of independent Hellenic states, but was extended to individuals during the time of the Enlightenment, most notably through the work of Immanuel Kant and John Stuart Mill. In healthcare, the autonomy model is grounded in the idea of the dignity of persons and the claim people have on each other to privacy, self-direction, the establishment of their own values and life plans based on information and reasoning, and the freedom to act on the results of their contemplation. Autonomy thus finds expression in the ethical and legal requirement of informed consent. Feminists and multiculturalists have however argued that since autonomy rests on the Enlightenment ideals of rationality, objectivity and independence, unconstrained by emotional and spiritual qualities, it serves to isolate the individual and thus fails to rectify the dehumanisation and depersonalisation of modern scientific medical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Bernard Lonergan's Structure of the Human Good in Dialogue With
    Bernard Lonergan’s Structure of the Human Good in dialogue with Bioethics. Maria-Veronika Pereira A Thesis in The Department of Theology Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts (Theology) at Concordia University Montreal, Quebec, Canada August 2013 © Maria-Veronika Pereira, 2013 Abstract This thesis examines how Bernard Lonergan’s structure of the human good might serve as a tool to bridge the tension between principle-based and communitarian approaches to bioethical enquiry. The first chapter discusses one of the current mainstream tools used in clinical and medical research bioethical evaluation which is principlism. Though there are many principles and a variety of interpretations, I will focus on the four major principles as laid out by Beauchamp and Childress which are autonomy, non maleficence, justice and beneficence. In particular, this chapter investigates in some detail the principle of autonomy and its relationship with the notions of respect for persons, liberal individualism and the human rights ideology. Chapter two explores an alternative approach to bioethics based on communitarian philosophy and will draw on the works of Daniel Callahan, in particular his arguments on the common good. From the first two chapters it appears that there may be a tension between the concepts of individual good and common good that, up till now, some argue bioethicists have not been able to bridge. The final chapter explores how Bernard Lonergan’s structure of the human good might bridge these two areas of tension by reframing the meaning and significance of rights, liberty, individual good and common good.
    [Show full text]
  • Proposal to Create a Graduate Minor in Bioethics
    Center for Bioethics and Medical Humanities Proposal for a Graduate Minor in Bioethics June, 2015 [Revised September, 2015] [Revised October, 2015] Graduate Studies Committee Proposing the Graduate Program MA in Bioethics: Ryan Nash, MD, MA (Chair) Alan Litsky, MD, ScD Karla Zadnik, OD, PhD 1. Title of the proposed graduate minor: Graduate Minor in Bioethics 2. Rational for its development Currently, the University does not offer any programs on the graduate level in bioethics. In light of the established presence of bioethics as a multidisciplinary and interdisciplinary field, the Center for Bioethics was launched in 2013 with the task of addressing this need. An MA in Bioethics has been proposed, and a Graduate Minor in Bioethics is a natural programmatic extension of the proposed MA in Bioethics. In short, the primary rational for developing the Graduate Minor is to offer scholarship and training in ethics for graduate students in a field that warrants the University’s attention. As part of the planning process for the MA program, Ryan Nash (Director, Center for Bioethics) met with deans and directors from the OSU health campus colleges and schools—including College of Medicine, Biomedical Science, Health and Rehabilitation Sciences, College of Nursing, College of Optometry, College of Pharmacy, and College of Veterinary Medicine—to discuss the MA and Graduate Minor. The leaders from the health campus colleges and schools have all expressed agreement that a Graduate Minor in Bioethics would serve their graduate students well. Further conversations with leadership in the Colleges of Public Affairs, Law, Public Health, Social Work, the Department of Philosophy, and other “stakeholder” disciplines for bioethics have led to the same consensus that a Graduate Minor is a welcome addition for the University.
    [Show full text]