European Studies in Philosophy of Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

European Studies in Philosophy of Science European Studies in Philosophy of Science Volume 2 Series editors Dennis Dieks , Institute for History & Foundations of Science , Utrecht University , The Netherlands Maria Carla Galavotti , Università di Bologna , Italy Wenceslao J. Gonzalez , University of A Coruña , Spain Editorial Board Daniel Andler, University of Paris-Sorbonne, France Theodore Arabatzis, University of Athens, Greece Diderik Batens, Ghent University, Belgium Michael Esfeld, University of Lausanne, Switzerland Jan Faye, University of Copenhagen, Denmark Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo, Norway Stephan Hartmann, University of Munich, Germany Gurol Irzik, Sabancı University, Turkey Ladislav Kvasz, Charles University, Czech Republic Adrian Miroiu, National School of Political Science and Public Administration, Romania Elizabeth Nemeth, University of Vienna, Austria Ilkka Niiniluoto, University of Helsinki, Finland Samir Okasha, University of Bristol, UK Katarzyna Paprzycka, University of Warsaw, Poland Tomasz Placek, Jagiellonian University, Poland Demetris Portides, University of Cyprus, Cyprus Wlodek Rabinowicz, Lund University, Sweden Miklos Redei, London School of Economics, UK Friedrich Stadler, University of Vienna, Austria Gereon Wolters, University of Konstanz, Germany This new series results from the synergy of EPSA - European Philosophy of Science Association - and PSE - Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective: ESF Networking Programme (2008–2013). It continues the aims of the Springer series “The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective” and is meant to give a new impetus to European research in the philosophy of science. The main purpose of the series is to provide a publication platform to young researchers working in Europe, who will thus be encouraged to publish in English and make their work internation- ally known and available. In addition, the series will host the EPSA conference proceedings, selected papers coming from workshops, edited volumes on specifi c issues in the philosophy of science, monographs and outstanding Ph.D. disserta- tions. There will be a special emphasis on philosophy of science originating from Europe. In all cases there will be a commitment to high standards of quality. The Editors will be assisted by an Editorial Board of renowned scholars, who will advise on the selection of manuscripts to be considered for publication. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/13909 David Ludwig A Pluralist Theory of the Mind David Ludwig Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Amsterdam , The Netherlands European Studies in Philosophy of Science ISBN 978-3-319-22737-5 ISBN 978-3-319-22738-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-22738-2 Library of Congress Control Number: 2015950433 Springer Cham Heidelberg New York Dordrecht London © Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specifi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Printed on acid-free paper Springer International Publishing AG Switzerland is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www.springer.com) For Megan In this sense, however, every sensible and philosophically honest world view must be pluralistic. For the universe is variegated and manifold, a fabric woven of many qualities no two of which are exactly alike. A formal metaphysical monism, with its principle that all being is in truth one , does not give an adequate account; it must be supplemented with some sort of pluralistic principle. Moritz Schlick – General Theory of Knowledge, 1918/1974, p. 333 Acknowledgements The issues raised in this book have been with me since my time as an undergraduate student at Free University Berlin. When I decided to study philosophy in 2002, my intellectual landscape was dominated by a handful of critical theorists in the tradi- tion of the Frankfurt School. My fi rst contact with contemporary academic philoso- phy came as a shock that impressed me so deeply that I quickly changed my enrollment from philosophy and ancient history to philosophy and cognitive sci- ence. As far as I remember, this decision was made during Holm Tetens’ lecture on “Computers, Brains, and other Machines” and one of his melancholic pleas for a naturalist theory of the mind. Holm’s uncompromising insistence on intellectual honesty left us students with the pessimistic suggestion that naturalism was a tragic truth, but a truth nonetheless. The anti-naturalists’ obsession with qualia and other supposedly irreducible entities was well motivated but unfortunately not well justifi ed. Challenged by this pessimistic naturalism, I decided that my philosophical inter- ests require more than anecdotal knowledge about the natural sciences. The cogni- tive science program at the University of Potsdam offered a great opportunity to learn about a large range of fascinating disciplines from excellent teachers like Johannes Haack and Reinhold Kliegl. Now focusing on debates about mind and cognition, my new subjects suggested a neat division of labor. As a student of cogni- tive science, I would learn about empirical problems of human memory, perception, problem solving, and so on. As a student of philosophy, I would be concerned with the remaining metaphysical problems such as consciousness, intentionality, self- knowledge, or free will. However, the problems with this division of labor soon started to appear. While I did my best to follow lectures from neurolinguistics to artifi cial intelligence, the convenient philosophical distinction between “easy” empirical problems and “hard” metaphysical problems made less and less sense. On the one hand, the “easy” empirical problems weren’t so easy after all and the reductive explanations from my Introduction to Philosophy of Mind courses nowhere to be found. On the other hand, there appeared to be a wealth of fascinating empirical research on consciousness, ix x Acknowledgements intentionality, and other entities that were claimed to fall in the philosophers’ realm of competence. Of course, I was soon introduced to a number of philosophical strat- egies of explaining this discomfort away. Models of reductive explanation in phi- losophy of mind were not supposed to provide a realistic account of explanations in scientifi c practice. Furthermore, the “hard problem of consciousness” did not imply that scientists have nothing to say about consciousness. Instead, one just had to separate the empirically unproblematic issues such as access consciousness or neu- ral correlates from the philosophically troubling issue of phenomenal consciousness. My discomfort about the relation between philosophy of mind and the reality of scientifi c practice might have faded without three lucky coincidences during my time as student in Berlin. First, I started to work as a student assistant for Peter Bieri who had been highly infl uential in establishing analytic philosophy of mind in German philosophy but had become disenchanted with the entire discipline. I do not know whether Peter Bieri would agree with the core claims of this book, but our discussions about Wittgenstein, Goodman, and the state of philosophy of mind were the single most important event in the formation of the thoughts of this book. The second lucky coincidence was a seminar on mereology with Olaf Müller at the same time as I was exposed to Peter Bieri’s staunch criticism of the analytic mainstream that he so successfully co-established in Germany. Olaf Müller’s broadly Putnam- inspired criticism of current developments in ontology provided me with a much- needed theoretical framework to formulate my ideas. My term paper on “mereological physicalism” was a fi rst attempt to articulate my discomfort with current philosophy of mind and to sketch a broadly pluralist alternative. The third lucky coincidence was that I started working as a student assistant for Tania Munz at the Max - Planck Institute for the History of Science . I rarely talked with history of science colleagues about philosophy of mind and I rarely talk about history of science thorough this book. Still, this book would not have been possible without a perspective on science that I do not owe to philosophers but to historians. I had learned to approach philosophy of mind by starting with sweeping metaphysi- cal doctrines (mostly physicalism and dualism in their countless varieties) and by looking at the cognitive sciences for support. It took history of science to invert this perspective. Instead of asking how science can validate a presupposed metaphysical picture, I became increasingly
Recommended publications
  • Determinism: Philosophical and Theological Objections Klaus Müller
    010 Muller_175 22-01-2013 12:35 Pagina 175 Determinism: Philosophical and Theological Objections Klaus Müller 1. A Telling Prefix In the second half of the 19th century, something peculiar happened to the English language. In an almost epidemical fashion, countless words were given the prefix “electro.” Electromagnetic waves had just been discovered, and hence everyone who sought to create a name for himself and wanted to be state-of-the-art would talk of “electro”-this and “elec- tro”-that until this new and fascinating technology became common- place and, therefore, uninteresting.1 Something very similar has been go- ing on with the prefix “neuro” for some time now, although this time the backgrounds are probably far more precarious. Neurosurgery and neu- robiology certainly designate a perfectly normal segment in science and research. The same holds true for neurophilosophy, I would say, as a sec- tor of a special theory of science. Still, the case is already different when it comes to neurolinguistics, neuroinformatics and, particularly, neurope- dagogy and neurojurisprudence. All these have long since become com- mon terms, designating processes and programmes which have a pro- found bearing on man’s self-understanding and whose ethical, social and political implications are far-reaching in practical life. Thus, in the case of neurojurisprudence, the concepts of guilt and responsibility that used to be taken for granted are dissolved, as, according to neurojurispru- dence, it is not mind and will which determine human actions, but neu- ronal dispositions. At the same time jurisdiction is being shifted towards prevention policy, since future culprits may be identified neuronally.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Relevance? There Are Several Reasons Why the Answer to This Is Not Evident
    Ethical and Aesthetical Aspects of Group Analysis Dieter Nitzgen, M.A. Group Analysis and Philosophy? As a primarily social-psychological theory, does group analysis also have a philosophical relevance? There are several reasons why the answer to this is not evident. One of these is well stated in M. Weegmann´s recent book on The World Within The Group (Weegman, 2014). Based on the work of H. Cohn (1996), he argues that ´Foulkes` ´wrote little on his philosophy, and what there is is dispersed and suggestive rather than systematic` (Weegmann, 2014, p.37). Whether this is a valid judgement we might leave suspended for the moment. Another argument put forward in favour of philosophy was given by G. Gödde. At the end of his essay on Schopenhauer and Psychoanalysis (2012), he argued that psychoanalysis as any other psychology ´is in need of a philosophical anthropology, because its basic assumptions depend on implicit philosophical concepts and preconceptions` (Gödde, 2012, p. 17; italics mine). According to Gödde, to reflect on its meta-theoretical foundations therefore is ´inevitable` (Gödde, 2012, p. 17). This clearly applies to group analysis too. This applies to group analysis too. Foulkes´ ´basic conviction` (Foulkes in Foulkes&Anthony 1984, p. 23), that ´Man is primarily a social being` (Foulkes in Foulkes&Anthony 1984, p. 234; italics mine) and his conclusion that ´the group is a more fundamental unit than the individual` (Foulkes in Foulkes&Anthony 1984, p. 23) obviously claim an anthropological validity that clearly exceeds the subject area of any psychology. A further argument was provided by Lacan who in his Rome discourse (Lacan, 1953) emphasized that what an analyst in his practice must be prepared to meet ´at its horizon` is ´the subjectivity of one´s time` (Lacan, 1953/2006, p.ö 264).
    [Show full text]
  • Nachtzug Nach Lissabon
    The ensemble is completed by a Scandinavian duo. The Swedish actress Lena Olin THE GERMAN SOCIETY OF beautifully brings the older Estafania to life. But it is Danish director Bille August who probably tops all the schauspielerischen Leistungen with his cinematic exposition of the PENNSYLVANIA beauty of Lisbon, foregrounding the romantic aura of the city via it’s narrow alleys and beautiful villas. The full color shots evoke an indelible aesthetic impression, contrasting Friday Film Fest Series starkly with Switzerland’s rainy Bern. The Philosophy Pascal Mercier quotes from the writings of Amadeu Prado as a device to exposit his own comprehensive philosophy. Philosophy is of course much better suited for a book where the logic and argumentation can be fully fleshed out in prose. In his writing he explores the eternal topics of mankind, God, religion, death and eternal life, the role of chance, free will, recognition of one self and others and time and space. In this philoso- phical prose lies the particular strength of his book. A movie is admittedly a rather lim- ited medium for such explorations. To compensate for this, herein is a small selection of aphorisms which may provide insight into Bieri’s philosophy: Es ist ein Irrtum zu glauben, die entscheidenden Momente eines Lebens, in denen sich seine gewohnte Richtung für immer ändert, müssten von lauter und greller Dramatik sein, unterspült von heftigen inneren Aufwallungen. Das ist ein kitschiges Märchen. … In Wahrheit ist die Dramatik einer lebensbestimmenden Erfahrung oft von unglaublich leiser Art. Sie ist dem Knall, der Stichflamme und dem Vulkanausbruch so wenig ver- wandt, dass die Erfahrung im Augenblick, wo sie gemacht wird, oft gar nicht bemerkt wird.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Dr. Markus Werning (Date of Birth: 03.11.1970) Department Of
    Prof. Dr. Markus Werning (date of birth: 03.11.1970) Department of Philosophy II Philosophy of Language and Cognition Ruhr University Bochum, 44780 Bochum Phone: (0234) 32-24734, Email: [email protected] 1 Research areas Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Cognition, Epistemology, Semantics, Neurophilosophy 2 Academic education Heinrich-Heine University of Düsseldorf, 2005 Dr. phil. (summa cum laude) with a dissertation on The Compositional Brain: A Unification of Conceptual and Neuronal Perspectives Master of Arts, first class honors degree “sehr gut” in the two majors Philosophy 1999 and Physics, Thesis: Erkenntnis und Schlussfolgerung (Knowledge and Inference), supervisors: Prof. Dr. Peter Bieri, Prof. Dr. Holm Tetens, Free University of Berlin Rutgers University, the State University of New Jersey 1997-1998 Research Scholar, associated with the graduate program of philosophy and the cognitive science certificate program Postgraduate studies with the two majors Philosophy and Physics, Free University 1993-1999 of Berlin Undergraduate studies of Philosophy and („Diplom“-)Physics, University of Marburg 1992-1993 Civilian Service 1991-1992 Abitur, Altkönigschule Kronberg (grade: 1.1 “very good”) 1990 3 Academic positions Senior Fellow, ZiF Center for Advanced Studies, Bielefeld 2011/12 Professor (W2) for Philosophy of Language and Cognition, University of Bochum since 10/2009 Replacement Professor (C4) for the Chair of Theoretical Philosophy, University 4-7/2009 Mainz Lecturer (E13), University of Düsseldorf 2002-2009 Junior Lecturer
    [Show full text]
  • Negotiating Free Will: Hypnosis and Crime in Early
    Negotiating Free Will NEGOTIATING FREE WILL: HYPNOSIS AND CRIME IN EARLY TWENTIETH-CENTURY GERMANY ANTHONY D. KAUDERS Keele University Abstract: The history of free will has yet to be written. With few exceptions, the literature on the subject is dominated by legal and philosophical works, most of which recount the ideas of prominent thinkers or discuss hypothetical questions far removed from specific historical contexts. The following paper seeks to redress the balance by tracing the debate on hypnosis in Germany from 1894 to 1936. Examining responses to hypnosis is tantamount to recording common understandings of autonomy and heteronomy, self-control and mind control, free will and automaticity. More specifically, it is possible to identify distinct philosophical positions related to the question as to whether hypnosis could surmount free will or not. The article demonstrates that the discourse often centered on the perceived struggle, located within a particular ‘personality’, between an individual’s ‘character’ or ‘soul’ and the infiltration by a foreign or hostile force. While one group (compatibilists) emphasized the resilience of the ‘moral inhibitions’, another group (henceforth called determinists) doubted that these were sufficient to withstand hypnosis. In December 1894, the Upper Bavarian Jury Court debated the nature of free will. Ceslav Lubicz-Cynski, a Polish-born teacher, hypnotist, and magnetizer, stood accused of having unlawfully seduced Hedwig von Zedlitz, a ‘respectable’ and ‘devout’ Saxon baroness. According to the state prosecutor, Cynski had employed suggestion to bring about a state of abulia (Willenlosigkeit) in his victim. Lacking free will, Zedlitz could no longer resist the defendant’s advances. The court had to decide whether Cynski’s skill as a hypnotist was 1 Negotiating Free Will responsible for a sexual crime (Verbrechen gegen die Sittlichkeit) or whether Zedlitz had simply fallen for the man’s foreign good looks.
    [Show full text]
  • 8. Acquisition of Freedom. Focusing on the Art of Living and the 5 1 6 Development of the Will in Pastoral Care – 7 Aneignung Der Freiheit
    1 Wilfried Engemann 2 3 4 8. Acquisition of freedom. Focusing on the art of living and the 5 1 6 development of the will in pastoral care – 7 Aneignung der Freiheit. Lebenskunst und Willensarbeit in der 8 Seelsorge 9 10 11 12 Summary: The present text presents a discussion between pastoral care and practical 13 philosophy and is therefore linked to the beginnings of Oskar Pfister’s pastoral psychol- 14 ogy. It discusses the causes for the widely missing integration of practical-philosophical 15 impulses into pastoral care. The article examines what it means to focus on the art of living 16 within the field of pastoral care and how to work on basic skills, which are essential to living. In other words, how to lead a non-predetermined life under predetermined cir- 17 cumstances. In this context, nurturing an individual’s free and independent will plays an 18 essential role, which in view of specific social-psychological changes in society presents a 19 special challenge. 20 Zusammenfassung: Der vorliegende Beitrag führt einen Dialog zwischen Seelsorge und 21 Praktischer Philosophie und knüpft damit an die Anfänge der Pastoralpsychologie bei 22 Oskar Pfister an. Dabei werden die Hintergründe für die weithin fehlende Integration 23 praktisch-philosophischer Impulse in die Seelsorge diskutiert. Der Aufsatz erörtert, was es 24 heißt, Lebenskunst ins Blickfeld der Seelsorge zu rücken und an Basiskompetenzen zu 25 arbeiten, derer es bedarf, um leben zu können, d.h. unter vorgegebenen Bedingungen ein 26 nicht vorgegebenes Leben zu führen. In diesem Zusammenhang spielt die Aneignung 27 eines eigenen Willens eine wichtige Rolle, die angesichts spezifischer sozialpsychologi- 28 scher Veränderungen in der Gesellschaft eine besondere Herausforderung darstellt.
    [Show full text]
  • THE ABILITY to DELIBERATE. Elements of a Philosophy of Mind Tópicos, Revista De Filosofía, Núm
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Seel, Martin THE ABILITY TO DELIBERATE. Elements of a Philosophy of Mind Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 36, 2009, pp. 123-141 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323028512004 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative “seel” — 2009/11/6 — 20:13 — page 123 — #123 THE ABILITY TO DELIBERATE Elements of a Philosophy of Mind Martin Seel Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität Frankfurt [email protected] Abstract The paper argues that only in the sphere of deliberation does intentionality exist in the demanding sense of a kind of foresight and planning, memory and imagination that steps out into space and time. Furthermore, only in the sphere of deliberation can something like normativity exist, be it in a logical, moral or legal sense. For only those who can deliberate can have any reasons to believe what they believe and desire what they desire. Following these directions, a analysis of the determinations and indeterminations within the process of deliberation leads to a revised compatibilist understanding of human freedom. Key words: deliberation, normativity, practical reasoning, theoretical reasoning, reasons. Resumen El artículo sostiene que sólo en el campo de la deliberación existe la in- tencionalidad en el sentido de una clase de previsión y planeación, memoria e imaginación que sale al tiempo y el espacio.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Dr. Markus Werning Chair of Philosophy of Language And
    Prof. Dr. Markus Werning Chair of Philosophy of Language and Cognition Department of Philosophy, Ruhr University Bochum, 44780 Bochum Phone: (0234) 32-24734, Email: [email protected] Born: November 1970 in Tübingen, Germany 1 Research areas Philosophy of Language, Philosophy of Memory, Philosophy of Cognition, Epistemology, Semantics, Neurophilosophy 2 Academic positions since 01/2016 Professor for Philosophy of Language and Cognition (tenured, W2), University of Bochum 10/2009-12/2015 Professor for Philosophy of Language and Cognition (W2), University of Bochum 2011-2012 Senior Fellow, ZiF Center for Advanced Studies, Bielefeld 04-07/2009 Replacement Professor for the Chair of Theoretical Philosophy, University Mainz 2002-2009 Lecturer (E13), University of Düsseldorf 2000-2002 Junior Lecturer (BAT IIa-Ost), University of Erfurt 1997-1998 Research Scholar, Rutgers University and Rutgers Center of Cognitive Science, New Jersey 3 Academic education 2005 Heinrich-Heine University of Düsseldorf, Dr. phil. (summa cum laude) with a dissertation on The Compositional Brain: A Unification of Conceptual and Neuronal Perspectives 1999 Master of Arts, first class honors degree “sehr gut” in the two majors Philosophy and Physics, Thesis: Erkenntnis und Schlussfolgerung (Knowledge and Inference), supervisors: Prof. Dr. Peter Bieri, Prof. Dr. Holm Tetens, Free University of Berlin 1997-1998 Rutgers University, the State University of New Jersey Research Scholar, associated with the graduate program of philosophy and the cognitive science certificate
    [Show full text]
  • The Conception of Anthropological Complementarism. an Introduction
    Hans-Ulrich Hoche The Conception of Anthropological Complementarism. An Introduction Appeared in print as the ‘Introduction’ of Hans-Ulrich Hoche, Anthropological Complementarism. Linguistic, Logical, and Phenomenological Studies in Support of a Third Way Beyond Dualism and Monism. Paderborn: mentis, 2008. * Summary The aims of Anthropological Complementarism in a nutshell (sect. 1). Against a watered-down conception of psychophysical complementarity (sect. 2). Linguistic and logical problems of identity and non-identity (sect. 3). A ‘noematic’ approach to consciousness (sect. 4). A plea for a pure noematics (sect. 5). My own consciousness as experienced by myself is not a part of nature (sect. 6). The major ontological tenets of mine (sect. 7). Complementarism proper (sect. 8). Suitable and unsuitable methods in philosophy (sect. 9). How to determine the methods suitable for philosophical inquiries (sect. 10). Linguistic and phenomenological methods (sect. 11). ‘Linguistic phenomenology’ (sect. 12). A note on philosophical truth (sect. 13). 1. The aims of Anthropological Complementarism in a nutshell The present collection of essays 1 (i.e., Hoche 2008a), most of which have been written within the very last years, aims at founding a novel stance concerning that aspect of the time-honoured ‘mind-body’ problem which has to do with the relationship between subjectively experienced consciousness and objectively observable occurrences in the central nervous system (‘consciousness-brain’ problem). Although, from the times of ancient Greek philosophy up to the fashionable though dubious ‘neurophilosophical’ approaches of our days, this problem has found innumerable answers, most of them – and, as far as I can see, all of them that are presently being discussed by mainstream philosophers, psychologists, physiologists, neurobiologists, and other empirical scientists – may be roughly subsumed under the well-known generic labels of either ‘dualism’ or ‘monism’ .
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Univ.-Prof. Dr. Markus Werning Professor (W2) für Philosophie der Sprache und Kognition Institut für Philosophie & Mercator Research Group Ruhr-Universität Bochum Adresse bis 31. Dez. 2009: Philosophisches Institut Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf Universitätsstraße 1 40225 Düsseldorf Germany Institutionelle Zugehörigkeit Ruhr-Universität Bochum Institut für Philosophie Mercator Research Group Theory of Memory Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf Philosophisches Institut DFG-Forschergruppe Funktionalbegriffe und Frames Humanwissenschaftlich-medizinisches Forschungszentrum Beruflicher Werdegang W2-Professur für Philosophie der Sprache und der Kognition, Universität Bochum ab 10/2009 Vertretung der C4-Professur „Theoretische Philosophie“, Universität Mainz 4-7/2009 Wissenschaftlicher Angestellter, Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf seit 2002 Wissenschaftlicher Mitarbeiter, Universität Erfurt 2000-2002 Leiter des Kolloquiums Philosophy Meets Cognitive Science, Charité, Humboldt- 1999-2000 Universität Berlin Research Scholar, Rutgers University and Rutgers Center of Cognitive Science, New 1997-1998 Jersey Tutor, Freie Universität Berlin 1994-1997 Zivildienst, Lebenshilfe e.V. Marburg 1991-92 Berufungsverfahren W2-Professur für Philosophie der Sprache und der Kognition (abgeschlossen) Ruf an die Ruhr-Universität Bochum (10.2.2009) Annahme des Rufes (14.5.2009) W3-Professur Philosophie des Geistes (abgeschlossen) Humboldt-Universität Berlin Einladung zum Probevortrag 2007 W1-Professur (Exzellenzcluster) (abgeschlossen)
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Pascal Mercier's Nachtzug Nach Lissabon and an Idea of Europe
    Another Country, Another Time: Notes on Pascal Mercier’s Nachtzug nach Lissabon and an idea of Europe Paulo de Medeiros University of Warwick Abstract: Pascal Mercier’s best-selling novel Night Train to Lisbon and its film adapation are examined as a case study in the relations between North and South and the image of Europe. The novel is significant inasmuch as it counters hegemonic World-Literature tendencies that privilege mostly central, English or French, novels in the European context. It is argued that even though both have significant differences and the novel manages to escape simple clichéd representations of Portugal, both ultimately stage a failure to conceptualize Europe transnationally. Ultimately, the romanticized desire for a would-be more vibrant form of engagement with life and art that would characterize the South does no more than misappropriate its past. Keywords: Pascal Mercier, Night Train to Lisbon, Europe, North-South Relations, World Literature Resumo: O romance de grande sucesso, Comboio nocturne para Lisboa, de Pascal Mercier, assim como o filme nele baseado, são analisados de modo a reflector sobre as relações entre o Norte eo Sul e a imagem da Europa. O romance distingue-se ao escaper a tendência hegemónica da Literatura-Global que, em context Europeu, privelegia os romances Ingleses e Franceses. Embora o romance e o filme tenham diferenças significantes entre si, e o romance consiga evitar as representações mais estereotipadas de Portugal, ambos acabam por falhar na representação de uma Europa transnacional. Em última análise o desejo romantizado por um Sul cuja relação com a vida e arte seria mais vivrante mais não faz do que se apropriar indevidamente do seu passado.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Groups Zif Research Groups
    Research Groups ZiF Research Groups 2021 / 22 Economic and Legal Challenges in the Advent of Smart Products Gerd Mühlheußer (Hamburg, GER) Herbert Dawid (Bielefeld, GER) Sabine Gless (Basel, SUI) 2020 / 21 Global Contestations of Women’s and Gender Rights Alexandra Scheele (Bielefeld, GER) Julia Roth (Bielefeld, GER) Heidemarie Winkel (Bielefeld, GER) 2020 Multimodal Rhetoric in Online Media Communications Kay O'Halloran (Liverpool, GBR) John Bateman (Bremen, GER) Mehul Bhatt (Örebro, SWE) 2019 / 20 Cognitive Behaviour of Humans, Animals, and Machines: Situation Model Perspectives Werner Schneider (Bielefeld, GER) Helge Ritter (Bielefeld, GER) 2018 / 19 ‘Felix Culpa’? Guilt as Culturally Productive Force Matthias Buschmeier (Bielefeld, GER) Katharina von Kellenbach (St. Marys City, USA) 2 2018 Understanding Southern Welfare. Ideational and Historical Foundations of Social Policies in Brazil, India, China and South Africa Ulrike Davy (Bielefeld, GER) Lutz Leisering (Bielefeld, GER) 2017 / 18 In Search of the Global Labour Market – Actors, Structures and Policies Ursula Mense-Petermann (Bielefeld, GER) Thomas Welskopp (Bielefeld, GER) Anna Zaharieva (Bielefeld, GER) 2016 / 17 Kinship and Politics: Rethinking a Conceptual Split and Its Epistemic Implications in the Social Sciences Erdmute Alber (Bayreuth, GER) David Warren Sabean (Los Angeles, USA) Simon Teuscher (Zürich, SUI) Tatjana Thelen (Wien, AUT) 2015 / 16 Genetic and Social Causes of Life Chances Martin Diewald (Bielefeld, GER) Rainer Riemann (Bielefeld, GER) 3 ZiF Research Groups
    [Show full text]