1 Metaphysical Vagueness and Metaphysical Indeterminacy Matti

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Metaphysical Vagueness and Metaphysical Indeterminacy Matti Metaphysical Vagueness and Metaphysical Indeterminacy Matti Eklund [Published in Metaphysica 14 (2013)] 1. I will here discuss vagueness, specifically whether there is “metaphysical” vagueness, vagueness in the world. Let me start with an important preliminary concerning what the phenomenon under discussion, vagueness, is. The term tends to get used one way in ordinary parlance and one way in philosophy. If I reply to a question about where Holger is by saying “he is in some bar”, I can fairly be said to have been ‘vague’ about Holger’s whereabouts. But that’s just a way of saying that I was unspecific about his whereabouts. Often in philosophy, ‘vague’ is used with a different meaning. Vagueness is that phenomenon, whatever it is, that paradigmatically rears its head in sorites reasoning.1 How we decide to use ‘vague’ is just a matter of terminology. The important point is that there is a distinction between what I call ‘vague’ and what I call ‘indeterminate’. Being careful about what the topic under discussion is, is especially important when we consider the possibility of metaphysical vagueness. Many authors freely go back and forth between considering metaphysical indeterminacy and metaphysical vagueness, but one may wish to render one verdict on the possibility of metaphysical indeterminacy and another on the possibility of metaphysical vagueness. The question I will deal with is whether vagueness is associated with semantic indeterminacy, metaphysical indeterminacy, or at best epistemic indeterminacy. Here are rough thumbnail sketches of these types of indeterminacy. (Some qualifications will be introduced later.) On the view that vagueness is associated with semantic indeterminacy it is indeterminate what the expression stands for.2 On the view that vagueness is 1 Note the formulation “paradigmatically rears its head”. This characterization of vagueness does not immediately entail that vagueness, understood as characterized, is always associated with sorites phenomena. (Although I happen myself to believe a version of this stronger claim myself.) 2 Arguably other representational items than expressions can be vague, and a more appropriate label for what I will here keep referring to as semantic indeterminacy would be representational indeterminacy. I will however stick with standard terminology and use “semantic” instead of “representational”. 1 associated with metaphysical indeterminacy, vague expressions stand for objects that are in and of themselves vague. On the view that vagueness is associated with epistemic indeterminacy, vague expressions have semantically determinate reference, and the objects they stand for are not in themselves vague: the only indeterminacy (if we can even call it that) associated with vagueness is epistemic: for principled reasons we cannot know the reference of vague expressions. In my discussion I will set the possibility of epistemic indeterminacy aside, and focus only on semantic and metaphysical indeterminacy. Throughout, I will speak of the indeterminacy with which vagueness is associated, or vagueness-related indeterminacy, rather that of the indeterminacy which vagueness is. The reason for the perhaps somewhat convoluted formulation is that I want to leave open the possibility that the relation between vagueness and the relevant kind of indeterminacy falls short of identity. My own favored view on vagueness and indeterminacy – briefly summarized and discussed in section 3 – is one on which the relation between vagueness and indeterminacy is less than straightforward, but I believe the talk of indeterminacy “associated with” vagueness is advisable even independently of my own favored view. 2. A fully unified account of indeterminacy is hardly a realistic goal. An account of the indeterminacy associated with vagueness is not necessarily an account of indeterminacy generally. Vagueness-related indeterminacy may be only one kind of the different kinds of indeterminacy, requiring different sorts of treatment, that there are. Already the seeming fact that some purported indeterminacy is semantic and other purported indeterminacy is metaphysical shows, if genuine, that indeterminacy is not a unified phenomenon. But I will also point to how there seem to be distinctions to be drawn between different instances of semantic indeterminacy and between different instances of metaphysical indeterminacy. Let me start by bringing up some rather different instances of semantic indeterminacy. First, consider Quinean indeterminacy. According to Quine, nothing in what determines what a speaker means by her words and symbols determine exact 2 reference – nothing determines that ‘rabbit’ in a given speaker’s mouth refers to rabbits and not e.g. undetached rabbit parts, timeslices of rabbits, etc. Given the holistic features of interpretation, there are other hypotheses about the reference of words that fit all the facts equally well. Second, consider an example made famous by Field (1973). We know from modern physics that nothing satisfies all the claims that Newtonian physics makes about ‘mass’. Instead there exist two different possible referents of Newtonian ‘mass’, proper mass and relativistic mass, both of which approximately satisfy the claims Newtonian physics makes about ‘mass’. It seems wrong to say that ‘mass’ as it occurs in Newtonian physics does not refer. Rather, ‘mass’ as used in Newton is indeterminate in reference as between proper mass and relativistic mass.3 Third, something for which we can use the label semantic indecision or the label incompleteness of meaning. (Both have been used. Maybe the former label is preferable since it carries less theoretical baggage.) 4 Consider a predicate ‘nice’ introduced by incomplete stipulations: n is nice iff n<13 n is nice iff n>15 The predicate ‘nice’ is partially defined. We have been somewhat semantically indecisive with regard to ‘nice’. Maybe it is right to say that its meaning is incomplete. Next, turn to different instances of metaphysical indeterminacy. First, there is the metaphysical indeterminacy that is sometimes said to be shown by quantum physics to obtain. Second, there is the open future. Third, there is indeterminacy as it comes up in certain realist/antirealist discussions. For example, some claims of set theory, 3 To explain, briefly, Field’s point: Two central tenets of Newtonian mechanics is (a) that momentum equals mass times velocity and (b) that for any two frames of reference, mass is the same with respect to both frames. Relativity theory shows that it can’t be that both tenets are correct, for the momentum of a particle divided by its velocity has different values in different frames of reference. But this does not mean that any specific Newtonian tenet has been refuted. For relativity theory posits one thing that satisfies (a) – relativistic mass (total energy divided by the square of the speed of light) – and another thing that satisfies (b) – proper mass (nonkinetic energy divided by the square of the speed of light). Relativity theory would have refuted a specific tenet of Newtonian physics if Newton’s ‘mass’ determinately referred to either relativistic mass or proper mass (or determinately referred to neither). But Field’s claim is that precisely because relativistic mass and proper mass approximately satisfy the claims Newton made about ‘mass’, Newton’s term ‘mass’ is indeterminate in reference as between these two possible referents. (See Field 1973, pp. 466-7.) 4 Modulo minor details, this example is from Fine (1975). 3 prominently the continuum hypothesis, are such that both they and their negations are consistent with the currently accepted axioms of set theory; and there are no obvious additions to the axioms that settle the continuum hypothesis, or so the standard account goes. One dividing line between realism and (prominent types of) antirealism about sets concerns whether the continuum hypothesis anyway has a determinate truth-value. The realist says yes, while the antirealist in one way or other demurs. The antirealist view is that this in one way or other is a matter of indeterminacy of mathematical reality. I find it natural, when considering the different instances of semantic and metaphysical indeterminacy, to say that there are different kinds of semantic indeterminacy and of metaphysical indeterminacy. Putting it this way immediately invites the question of what exactly it means to say that two instances of indeterminacy are, or are not, of different kinds. But for present purposes the important question is just whether there is reason to believe that the questions about indeterminacy raised in the literature are likely to have univocal answers. These are questions about, for example, the logic of indeterminacy and about the cognitive (or normative) role of indeterminacy – where the question of the cognitive role of indeterminacy is the question of what an agent’s attitude toward p ought to be when she takes it to be indeterminate whether p. First, consider the logic of indeterminacy. One popular view on vagueness – although not one I subscribe to myself – is that fuzzy logic is the logic of vagueness: the indeterminacy with which vagueness is associated is a matter of vague sentences taking truth-values on a continuum. But this idea seems like a non-starter in the case of some of the kinds of semantic indeterminacy listed. What we have here is one consideration given which vagueness-related indeterminacy would be a different kind of indeterminacy from the just listed kinds of semantic indeterminacy, even if vagueness-related indeterminacy is indeed semantic. This point about the logic of indeterminacy does nothing to distinguish between purported kinds of semantic indeterminacy distinct from vagueness. But consider then a second issue: the cognitive roles of the indeterminacies. One reasonable view on “14 is nice” is that this is simply to be rejected. But even if one holds this view one can think that “this object has mass ” is one we ought to have a more 4 ambivalent attitude toward, if this is true given one but not the other of the candidate 5 referents of mass. If so, these two types of indeterminacy have different cognitive roles.
Recommended publications
  • The Linguistic Description of Opaque Contexts Pdf, Epub, Ebook
    THE LINGUISTIC DESCRIPTION OF OPAQUE CONTEXTS PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Janet Dean Fodor | 384 pages | 26 Nov 2015 | Taylor & Francis Ltd | 9781138989535 | English | London, United Kingdom The Linguistic Description of Opaque Contexts PDF Book This also concerns noun phrases embedded under attitude verbs; consider:. A naturalobjectionto ourproposalis thatthe T-sentencewe give for 'Galileo said that the earthmoves' will not enable someone who grasps it alone to under- stand the sentence for which it gives truthconditions. Peter Trudgill offers examples of non-transparent and transparent compounds: "The English word dentist is not semantically transparent whereas the Norwegian word tannlege , literally 'tooth doctor,' is" A Glossary of Sociolinguistics , This cannot mean as if they had asserted them, so we take it that the idea is basically the same as the one we have in mind. See Lepore and Ludwig for a suggestion for an importantmodificationof Davidson's proposal in the context of a general truth-theoreticaltreatmentof tense and temporaladverbs. The above observation about translationhelps on another front. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. This way of drawing attentionto the appropriaterelation is does not commit us to the existence of propo- sitions; rather,it is a useful heuristicgiven the familiarityof puttingit this way. Perhaps the most popular solution to the problem of providing a compositional semantics for naturallanguages aims to exploit this fact by treat- ing that-clausesas referringto intensional entities-entities at least as as finely individuatedas the meanings of sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics for Opaque Contexts1
    PHIL 9812-6 Philosophical Perspectives, 12, Language, Mind, and Ontology, 1998 SEMANTICS FOR OPAQUE CONTEXTS1 Kirk Ludwig and Greg Ray University of Florida 1. Introduction In this paper, we outline an approach to giving extensional truth-theoretic semantics for what have traditionally been seen as opaque sentential contexts.2 If the approach outlined here is correct, it resolves a longstanding complex of prob- lems in metaphysics, the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of language. We take as our starting point the requirement that any semantics for a natural language be compositional, that is, that it provide an interpretation of each of the infinity of sentences in it on the basis of a finite primitive vocabulary and a finite number of rules. At least since Frege,3 it has been recognized that sentences such as (1), (1) Galileo said that the earth moves, present a prima facie difficulty for the project of providing a compositional se- mantics for natural languages. A compositional semantics for a fragment of En- glish which does not include sentences of indirect discourse, psychological attitude sentences (henceforth ‘attitude sentences’), modal sentences, sentences about entailments, and similar constructions can be given straightforwardly in the form of a first-order interpretive truth theory for the language.4 The approach breaks down when we turn to sentences such as (1), whose truth value is not a function of the truth value of the embedded sentence ‘the earth moves’. In general, one term can be substituted for another in ‘that-clauses’salva veritate only if they are synonymous. Perhaps the most popular solution to the problem of providing a compositional semantics for natural languages aims to exploit this fact by treat- ing that-clauses as referring to intensional entities–entities (at least as) as finely individuated as the meanings of sentences.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Propositional Attitudes
    On the Propositional Attitudes KEITH COLEMAN The University of Kansas An adequate account of the nature of the so called 'propositional attitudes' has long been sought by philosophers of mind, and most theories which have been proposed have suffered from certain logical or epistemological defects or have been limited in scope. The issues centering around the nature of beliefs, desires, and the other attitudes pertain to two principal areas of investigation: the explication of a (psychological) theory concerning the objects of the propositional attitudes and the analysis of the logical structure of such sentences as those with the form 'A believes that p' or 'A wishes (desires) that p.' My main concern in this paper is with problems associated with the latter endeavor. Such problems in an important respect are more basic, for a successful attempt at characterizing the typical form of sentences that express propositional attitudes must be made before any theory about the objects of beliefs, desires, and other intentions can possibly take shape.1 The sentence "Jones believes that there are unicorns" has the typical form of the members of a class of sentences each one consisting of one or more names or denoting phrases followed by an intentional idiom of the kind 'believes that', 'desires that', 'wishes that', 'hopes that', 'fears that', 'says that', 'wonders whether', etc. followed by a complete sentence. Such complex sentences when taken as assertions have usually been seen as expressing a relationship (or a propositional attitude) of one kind or another between an object (usually a person) and a belief, desire, wish, hope, or other intention (or object of the propositional attitude).
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 18: Negative Contexts and Intensional Contexts: Similarities and Differences 1. Introduction to the Puzzle
    The Structure of Meaning, Lecture 18 Barbara H. Partee, May 22, 2006 Lecture 18: Negative Contexts and Intensional Contexts: Similarities and Differences 1. Introduction to the puzzle..........................................................................................................................................1 2. Background. “Scope ambiguity,” NP interpretations, and the semantics of operators.............................................2 3. Natural language patterns – strategies of marking different interpretations differently. ...........................................4 3.1. Some languages mark opaque readings, e.g. Romance languages - subjunctive................................................4 3.2. Negative Polarity Items (NPIs)...........................................................................................................................5 3.3. Russian Genitive of Negation and intensional verbs ..........................................................................................6 4. Hypotheses ................................................................................................................................................................7 4.1 Scope differences.................................................................................................................................................7 4.2 Possible non-uniform NP meanings. .................................................................................................................7 4.3 Property types and other “demotions”
    [Show full text]
  • A Logic for 'Because'
    THE REVIEW OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC Volume 4, Number 3, September 2011 A LOGIC FOR ‘BECAUSE’ BENJAMIN SCHNIEDER University of Hamburg Abstract. In spite of its significance for everyday and philosophical discourse, the explanatory connective ‘because’ has not received much treatment in the philosophy of logic. The present paper develops a logic for ‘because’ based on systematic connections between ‘because’ and the truth- functional connectives. §1. Introduction. 1.1. The project. In the philosophy of logic, the natural language connectives ‘and’, ‘or’, ‘not’, and ‘if . then’ are widely discussed and so are their formal counterparts, such as the truth-functional connectives of classical logic or counterfactual and strict con- ditionals in modal systems. Considerably less attention has been paid to the explanatory connective ‘because’. One simple reason may be that ‘because’ is quite complicated to handle. ‘Because’ is obviously not an extensional operator: the truth of the two clauses in a ‘because’-sentence is compatible both with the truth of the sentence (JFK died because he was shot) and with its falsity (JFK died because Chernobyl exploded). But not only is ‘because’ nonexten- sional, it is even hyperintensional: necessarily equivalent clauses are not substitutable salva veritate in its context. This immediately follows if (i) some true ‘because’-sentences have a main clause expressing a necessary truth, and (ii) not all necessary truths are explained by exactly the same things. For, assume that S expresses a necessary truth (e.g., that {2} contains a prime number), and that there is at least one true instance of S because φ (e.g., ‘{2} contains a prime number because it contains 2 and 2 is prime’).
    [Show full text]
  • The Functional Composition of Sense
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03099-3 The Functional Composition of Sense Bryan Pickel1 Received: 10 June 2020 / Accepted: 22 February 2021 © The Author(s) 2021 Abstract A central dispute in understanding Frege’s philosophy concerns how the sense of a complex expression relates to the senses of its component expressions. According to one reading, the sense of a complex expression is a whole built from the senses of the component expressions. On this interpretation, Frege is an early proponent of structured propositions. A rival reading says that senses compose by functional application: the sense of a complex expression is the value of the function denoted by its functional component for the arguments denoted by its remaining components. I argue that two non-negotiable Fregean theses entail that senses compose by functional application. One thesis is that referents compose by functional application. The other thesis is that an expression in an indirect context refers to its customary sense. Keywords Frege · Semantics · Sense · Reference · Structured propositions 1 Introduction Two aspects of Frege’s mature semantic theory have each been heralded as central advances in the development of a rigorous semantics. One aspect—introduced in Function and Concept—is that reference is not merely compositional, but functionally compositional. According to Frege, each expression has a Bedeutung, or referent. Some expressions refer to functions. Others expressions refer to arguments for these functions. A complex expression refers to the value of the function referred to by one This paper improved significantly as a result of advice and feedback from Fiona Doherty, Philip Ebert, Bjørn Jesperen, Lorraine Juliano Keller, Casey McCoy, Joey Pollack, Brian Rabern, Alex Radelescu, Stephen Read, David Rey, Wolfgang Schwarz, Alex Yates, and two referees for Synthese.
    [Show full text]
  • Williamson Traces the History of the Problem from Discussions of the Heap Paradox in Ancient Greece to Modern Formal Approaches, Such As Fuzzy Logic
    Vagueness If you keep removing single grains of sand from aheap,when is it no longer a heap? This question, and many others like it, soon lead us to the problem of vagueness. Timothy Williamson traces the history of the problem from discussions of the heap paradox in ancient Greece to modern formal approaches, such as fuzzy logic. He discusses the view that classical logic and formal semantics do not apply to vague languages and shows that none of the alternative approaches can give a satisfying account of vagueness without falling back on classical logic. Against this historical and critical background, Williamson then develops his own epistemicist position. Vagueness, he argues, is an epistemic phenomenon, a kind of ignorance: there really is a specific grain of sand whose removal turns the heap into a non-heap, but we cannot know which one it is. Williamson’s argument has ramifications far beyond the study of vagueness. It reasserts the validity of classical logic and semantics; more generally, it makes the thoroughly realist point that even the truth about the boundaries of our concepts can be beyond our capacity to know it. The approach throughout keeps technicalities to a minimum; this is partly to counter the illusion, encouraged by the emphasis on formal systems, that vagueness can be studied in a precise metalanguage. For the technically minded, an appendix shows how the epistemic view can be formalised within the framework of epistemic logic. Timothy Williamson is Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at the University of Edinburgh. He is the author of Identity and Discrimination.
    [Show full text]
  • D-SCRIPT: a COMPUTATIONAL THEORY of DESCRIPTIONS Artificial Intelligence
    Session 8 Formalisms for D-SCRIPT: A COMPUTATIONAL THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS Artificial Intelligence Robert C. Moore Massachusetts Institute of Technology Cambridge, Massachusetts Abstract 1.2 Problems In Representing Knowledge This paper describes D-SCRIPT, a language for representing knowledge in artificial Before presenting the details of D- Intelligence programs. D-SCRIPT contains a SCRIPT, we will try to give some Idea of the powerful formalism for descriptions, which type of problem It Is designed to solve. A permits the representation of statements that classic problem Is that of representing opaque are problematical for other systems. contexts. An opaque context is one which does Particular attention is paid to problems of not allow substitution of referentially opaque contexts, time contexts, and knowledge equivalent expressions or does not allow about knowledge. The design of a deductive existential quantification. For example the system for this language is also considered. verb "want" creates an opaque context: 1. Int roduction (1.1) John wants to marry the prettiest girl. 1.1 Ways of Representing; Knowledge This sentence is ambiguous. it can mean either: Methods advocated for representing knowledge in artificiall intelligence programs (1.2) John wants to merry a specific girl who have Included logical statements (McCarthy, also happens to bp the prettiest. Sandewall), semantic networks (Quillian, Schank), and procedures (Hewitt, Sussman and or: McDermott), All these approaches shpre one fundamental concept, the notion of (1.3) John wants to marry whoever is the predication. That Is, the basic data prettiest girl, although he may not know structure In each system Is some who that is.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantifier Scope, Lexical Semantics, and Surface Structure Constituency
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science December 1996 Quantifier Scope, Lexical Semantics, and Surface Structure Constituency Jong Cheol Park University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Park, Jong Cheol, "Quantifier Scope, Lexical Semantics, and Surface Structure Constituency" (1996). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 106. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/106 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-96-28. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/106 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Quantifier Scope, Lexical Semantics, and Surface Structure Constituency Abstract We present a novel conjecture concerning the scope ambiguities that arise in sentences including multiple nonreferential quantifiers. eW claim that many existing theories of the phenomenon fail to correctly limit the set of readings that such sentences engender by failing to distinguish between referential and non-referential quantifiers. Once the distinction is correctly drawn, we show that surface syntax can be made, via an extended notion of surface constituency, to identify the set of available differently-scoped readings for such sentences. We examine various English constructions to show that the scopings predicted by the conjecture are the only ones that are available to human language understanders. We show how to incorporate this conjecture into a theory of quantifier scope, yb couching it in a unification-based Combinatory Categorial Grammar framework and implementing it in SICStus Prolog. Finally, we compare the proposal with related approaches to quantifier scope ambiguity. Comments University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Representational Foundations of Computation
    The Representational Foundations of Computation Michael Rescorla Abstract: Turing computation over a non-linguistic domain presupposes a notation for the domain. Accordingly, computability theory studies notations for various non-linguistic domains. It illuminates how different ways of representing a domain support different finite mechanical procedures over that domain. Formal definitions and theorems yield a principled classification of notations based upon their computational properties. To understand computability theory, we must recognize that representation is a key target of mathematical inquiry. We must also recognize that computability theory is an intensional enterprise: it studies entities as represented in certain ways, rather than entities detached from any means of representing them. 1. A COMPUTATIONAL PERSPECTIVE ON REPRESENTATION Intuitively speaking, a function is computable when there exists a finite mechanical procedure that calculates the function’s output for each input. In the 1930s, logicians proposed rigorous mathematical formalisms for studying computable functions. The most famous formalism is the Turing machine: an abstract mathematical model of an idealized computing device with unlimited time and storage capacity. The Turing machine and other computational formalisms gave birth to computability theory: the mathematical study of computability. 2 A Turing machine operates over strings of symbols drawn from a finite alphabet. These strings comprise a formal language. In some cases, we want to study computation over the formal language itself. For example, Hilbert’s Entscheidungsproblem requests a uniform mechanical procedure that determines whether a given formula of first-order logic is valid. Items drawn from a formal language are linguistic types, whose tokens we can inscribe, concatenate, and manipulate [Parsons, 2008, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics for Opaque Contexts Author(S): Kirk Ludwig and Greg Ray Source: Noûs, Vol
    Semantics for Opaque Contexts Author(s): Kirk Ludwig and Greg Ray Source: Noûs, Vol. 32, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 12, Language, Mind, and Ontology (1998), pp. 141-166 Published by: Wiley Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2676144 . Accessed: 19/11/2014 12:40 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 150.209.80.79 on Wed, 19 Nov 2014 12:40:42 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PhilosophicalPerspectives, 12, Language,Mind, and Ontology,1998 SEMANTICS FOR OPAQUE CONTEXTS Kirk Ludwig and Greg Ray University of Florida 1. Introduction In this paper, we outline an approachto giving extensional truth-theoretic semanticsfor what have traditionallybeen seen as opaque sententialcontexts.2 If the approachoutlined here is correct,it resolves a longstandingcomplex of prob- lems in metaphysics, the philosophy of mind and the philosophy of language. We take as our startingpoint the requirementthat any semantics for a natural language be compositional, that is, that it provide an interpretationof each of the infinity of sentences in it on the basis of a finite primitive vocabularyand a finite numberof rules.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics of Gradation
    MANFRED BIERWISCH The Semantics of Gradation 1 Introduction The term 'gradation' is meant to cover a range of phenomena which for the time being I shall call quantitative evaluations regarding dimensions or features. I shall actually be looking into the principles governing the way gradation is expressed in language. The quantitative aspect of the adjectives of dimension occupies a key position which can be systematically explained and this aspect will be the crucial point of the discussion. I shall focus on the various grammatical forms of comparison: comparative, equative, superlative and some related constructions, and indications of measurement and adverbial indications of degree. A substantial number of the relevant facts have been researched in a series of analyses and theoretical proposals on the semantics of comparison." There are two main reasons why the present essay, while building on the insights gained 50 far, attempts to formulate a new theory concerning the same facts. Firstly, there remain many relevant and revealing facts that have not been taken into account in previous analyses and could in fact not be incorporated without radical changes.' " Secondly, while the facts dealt with so far have been systematically analysed and explicitly described, they have not been traced back to the general conditions and principles underlying the interactions of the phenomena observed; A fresh approach also seems called for if we are to bring together system­ atically the explanations and insights provided by existing analyses, because of their sometimes widely differing orientation regarding (a) the way they treat the central facts, (b) their aims in doing 50 and (c) the methods they use.
    [Show full text]