Two Dogmas of Empiricism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Two Dogmas of Empiricism of meanings and independently of fact. Pursuing this line, let OGMAS OF EMPIRICISM us examine the concept of meaning which is presupposed. Meaning, let us remember, is not to be identified with cism has been conditioned in large part by naming.' Frege's example of 'Evening Star' and 'Morning Star', is a belief in some fundamental cleavage and Russell's of 'Scott' and 'the author of Waverley', illustrate hitch are analytic, or grounded in meanings that terms can name the same thing but differ in meaning. 'afters of fact, and truths which are synthetic, The distinction between meaning and naming is no less impor- The other dogma is reductionism: the belief tant at the level of abstract terms. The terms '9' and 'the number ful statement is equivalent to some logical of the planets' name one and the same abstract entity but us which refer to immediate experience. Both presumably must be regarded as unlike in meaning; for astro- ne, are ill-founded. One effect of abandoning nomical observation was needed, and not mere reflection on II see, a blurring of the supposed boundary meanings, to determine the sameness of the entity in question. e metaphysics and natural science. Another The above examples consist of singular terms, concrete and Ard pragmatism. abstract. With general terms, or predicates, the situation is somewhat different but parallel. Whereas a singular term pur- Background for Analyticity ports to name an entity, abstract or concrete, a general term ) between analytic and synthetic truths was does not; but a general term is tr'413 of an entity, or of each of ume's distinction between relations of ideas many, or of none The class of all entities of which a general ,, and in Leibniz's distinction between truths term is true is called the extension of the term. Now paralleling ,hs of fact. leibniz spoke of the truths of the contrast between the meaning of a singular term and the all possible worlds. Picturesqueness aside, entity named, we must distinguish equally between the meaning he truths of reason are those which could not of a general term and its extension. The general terms 'creature 1 the same vein we hear analytic statements with a heart' and 'creature with kidneys', for example, are its whose denials are self-contradictory. But perhaps alike in extension but unlike in meaning. small explanatory value; for the notion of Confusion of meaning with extension, in the case of general ss, in the quite broad sense needed for this terms, is less common than confusion of meaning with naming ticity, stands in exactly the same need of in the case of singular terms. It is indeed a commonplace in 8 the notion of analyticity itself. The two philosophy to oppose intension (or meaning) to extension, or, , sides of a single dubious coin. in a variant vocabulary, connotation to denotation. of an analytic statement as one that attrib- I See above, p. 9. ) more than is already conceptually contained Bee above, p. 10, and below, pp. 107-115. 20 volved in the meaning of the word 'man' The characteristic of such a statement is that it can be turned ; is not; but two-leggedness may at the into a logical truth by putting synonyms for synonyms; thus d as involved in the meaning of 'biped' (2) can be turned into (I) by putting 'unmarried man' for its not. Thus from the point of view of the synonym 'bachelor'. We still lack a proper characterization of it makes no sense to say of the actual this second class of analytic statements, and therewith of ana- mice a man and a biped, that his rationality lyticity generally, inasmuch as we have had in the above descrip- two-leggedness accidental or vice versa. tion to lean on a notion of "synonymy" which is no less in need , for Aristotle, but only linguistic forms of clarification than analyticity itself. ning is what essence becomes when it is In recent years Carnap has tended to explain analyticity ject of reference and wedded to the word. by appeal to what he calls state-descriptions.' A state-descrip- f meaning a conspicuous question is the tion is any exhaustive assignment of truth values to the atomic, what sort of things are meanings? A felt or noncompound, statements of the language. All other state- ,ies may derive from an earlier failure to ments of the language are, Carnap assumes, built up of their ling and reference are distinct. Once the component clauses by means of the familiar logical devices, in s sharply separated from the theory of such a way that the truth value of any complex statement is step to recognizing as the primary business fixed for each state-description by specifiable logical laws. A aning simply the synonymy of linguistic statement is then explained as analytic when it comes out true icity of statements; meanings themselves, under every state description. This account is an adaptation of 6ry entities, may well be abandoned.' Leibniz's "true in all possible worlds." But note that this version nalyticity then confronts us anew. State- of analyticity serves its purpose only if the atomic statements of 13rtic by general philosophical acclaim are the language are, unlike 'John is a bachelor' and 'John is mar- tk. They fall into two classes. Those of the ried', mutually independent Otherwise there would be a state- be called logically true, are typified by: description which assigned truth to 'John is a bachelor' and to nmarried man is married, 'John is married', and consequently 'No bachelors are married' would turn out synthetic rather than analytic under the pro- of this example is that it not merely is posed criterion. Thus the criterion of analyticity in terms of remains true under any and all reinterpre- state-descriptions serves only for languages devoid of extra- married'. If we suppose a prior inventory logical synonym-pairs, such as 'bachelor' and 'unmarried man'— nprising 'no', 'un-', 'not', 'if', 'then', 'and', synonym-pairs of the type which give rise to the "second class" logical truth is a statement which is true of analytic statements. The criterion in terms of state-descrip- Lnd below, pp. 48f. Carnap [3], pp. Off; 141, pp. 70ff. i. Our problem, however, is analyticity; which does not limit itself to the reporting of preexisting fficulty lies not in the first class of analytic synonymies. I have in mind what Carnap calls explication—an al truths, but rather in the second class, activity to which philosophers are given, and scientists also in notion of synonymy. their more philosophical moments. In explication the purpose is not merely to paraphrase the definiendum into an outright 2. Definition synonym, but actually to improve upon the definiendum by ho find it soothing to say that the analytic refining or supplementing its meaning. But even explication, mid class reduce to those of the first class, though not merely reporting a preexisting synonymy between lefinition; 'bachelor', for example, is defined definiendum and definiens, does rest nevertheless on other pre- But how de we find that 'bachelor' is existing synonymies. The matter may be viewed as follows. I man'? Who defined it thus, and when? Any word worth explicating has some contexts which, as wholes, , the nearest dictionary, and accept the are clear and precise enough to be useful; and the purpose of dation as law? Clearly this would be to explication is to preserve the usage of these favored contexts e horse. The lexicographer is an empirical while sharpening the usage of other contexts. In order that less is the recording of antecedent facts; a given definition be suitable for purposes of explication, there- Lielor' as 'unmarried man' it is because of fore, what is required is not that the definiendum in its ante- is a relation of synonymy between those cedent usage be synonymous with the definiens, but just that ieral or preferred usage prior to his own each of these favored contexts of the definiendum, taken as a ynonymy presupposed here has still to be whole in its antecedent usage, be synonymous with the corres- in terms relating to linguistic behavior. ponding context of the definiens. bion" which is the lexicographer's report Two alternative definientia may be equally appropriate for iymy cannot be taken as the ground of the purposes of a given task of explication and yet not be synony- mous with each other; for they may serve interchangeably within indeed, an activity exclusively of philolo- the favored contexts but diverge elsewhere. By cleaving to one id scientists frequently have occasion to of these definientia rather than the other, a definition of expli- term by paraphrasing it into terms of a cative kind generates, by fiat, a relation of synonymy between ary. But ordinarily such a definition, like definiendum and definiens which did not hold before. But such tire lexicography, affirming a relation of a definition still owes its explicative function, as seen, to pre- to the exposition in hand. existing synonymies. s to affirm synonymy, just what the inter- There does, however, remain still an extreme sort of defini- Dy GanttMan; Walla that all species ot between two languages, the one a part of the other. Riligible. For the rest, definition rests on But these correlations are not arbitrary. They are supposed explaining it. to show how the primitive notations can accomplish all purposes, m' has come to have a dangerously refo- save brevity and convenience, of the redundant language. Hence rm doubt to its frequent occurrence in the definiendum and its definiens may be expected, in each case, ical writings. We shall do well to digress to be related in one or another of the three ways lately noted.
Recommended publications
  • Defense of Reductionism About Testimonial Justification of Beliefs
    Page 1 Forthcoming in Noûs A Defense of Reductionism about Testimonial Justification of Beliefs TOMOJI SHOGENJI Rhode Island College Abstract This paper defends reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs against two influential arguments. One is the empirical argument to the effect that the reductionist justification of our trust in testimony is either circular since it relies on testimonial evidence or else there is scarce evidence in support of our trust in testimony. The other is the transcendental argument to the effect that trust in testimony is a prerequisite for the very existence of testimonial evidence since without the presumption of people’s truthfulness we cannot interpret their utterances as testimony with propositional contents. This paper contends that the epistemic subject can interpret utterances as testimony with propositional contents without presupposing the credibility of testimony, and that evidence available to the normal epistemic subject can justify her trust in testimony. I. Introduction There has recently been a considerable interest in anti-reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs, according to which we cannot justify our trust in testimony by perceptual and memorial evidence.1 The reason for the interest is not the enticement of skepticism. Recent anti-reductionists hold that we are prima facie justified in trusting testimony simply because it is testimony. This means that there is a presumption in favor of testimony that it is credible unless contrary evidence is available. I will use the term “anti-reductionism” to refer to this non-skeptical version of anti-reductionism about testimonial justification. The more traditional position is reductionism, of which the most prominent advocate is David Hume.
    [Show full text]
  • You Are Not Your Brain: Against Teaching to the Brain
    You Are Not Your Brain: Against Teaching to the Brain Gregory M. Nixon Gregory Nixon is an Assistant Professor in the School of Education at the University of Northern British Columbia in Prince George. He took his doctorate with William F. Pinar at Louisiana State University and taught at various universities in the USA for 12 years before returning home to Canada. He publishes widely on learning theory and philosophy of mind. He is editor-at-large for the Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research. Abstract Since educators are always looking for ways to improve their practice, and since empirical science is now accepted in our worldview as the final arbiter of truth, it is no surprise they have been lured toward cognitive neuroscience in hopes that discovering how the brain learns will provide a nutshell explanation for student learning in general. I argue that identifying the person with the brain is scientism (not science), that the brain is not the person, and that it is the person who learns. In fact the brain only responds to the learning of embodied experience within the extra-neural network of intersubjective communications. Learning is a dynamic, cultural activity, not a neural program. Brain-based learning is unnecessary for educators and may be dangerous in that a culturally narrow ontology is taken for granted, thus restricting our creativity and imagination, and narrowing the human community. [keywords: selfhood, neuroscience, cognitive science, brain-based learning, intersubjectivity, consciousness, philosophy of mind, explanatory gap, cultural construction, reductionism, scientism, education, learning theory, curriculum theory] Brain-Based Scientism 2 Introduction Human experience is a dance that unfolds in the world and with others.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell on Sensations and Images Abdul Latif Mondal Aligarh Muslim University SUMMARY INTRODUCTION
    Bertrand Russell on Sensations and Images Abdul Latif Mondal Aligarh Muslim University SUMMARY In his Theory of Mind, Russell tries to explain the mind in positive terms of sensations and images. All the mental phenomena like imagination, belief, memory, emotion, desire, will, even consciousness etc. are attempted to be established as entities, subjects, or acts by Russell. In his works The Analysis of Mind and An Outline of Philosophy, Russell offers the explanations of each mental phenomena with reference to neutrality of sensations and images, Russell does not treat them as neutral in his book The Analysis of Mind. However, in his later work, he treats them to be neutral. Russell relates especially the images to ―mnemic‖ causation. Firstly, he declares them as concerned with action in time. Subsequently, he explains them as permanent modification of the structure of the brain. He also explains sensations and images as stuff of our brain. In his book The Analysis of Mind, Russell tries to explain various mental phenomena. Firstly, he contends that all types of mental phenomena is a mix up of sensations and images and does not imply a special entity designated as ‗consciousness.‘ Secondly, Russell considers how combinations of sensations and images do, in a sense, imply consciousness in the sense of awareness. For Russell, a single sensation and image cannot in itself be deemed to be cognitive. When we try to explain a conscious mental occurrence, we do analyse it into non-cognitive constituents. We also need to show what constitutes consciousness or awareness in it. In this paper, our contention is that Russell‘s explanation of mental phenomena is especially related to these two claims.
    [Show full text]
  • What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(S): Hans Halvorson Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol
    What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(s): Hans Halvorson Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 79, No. 2 (April 2012), pp. 183-206 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/664745 . Accessed: 03/12/2012 10:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.67 on Mon, 3 Dec 2012 10:32:52 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions What Scientific Theories Could Not Be* Hans Halvorson†‡ According to the semantic view of scientific theories, theories are classes of models. I show that this view—if taken literally—leads to absurdities. In particular, this view equates theories that are distinct, and it distinguishes theories that are equivalent. Furthermore, the semantic view lacks the resources to explicate interesting theoretical relations, such as embeddability of one theory into another.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Education R.T
    Reductionism in Education R.T. Alien, Loughborough Leicestershire, England 1. Reductionism as a Metaphysical Issue In an earlier article, I demonstrated the necessary ingredients of metaphysics in education1• I propose now to show how Reductionism, some­ times called 'Reductivism', is a metaphysical issue, has serious consequences for human life, and can gravely affect educational practice and theory.2 Firstly, we need to distinguish Reductionism from the reduction of one set of laws to another within the same science, whereby the former set are shown to be special cases of the latter. Such reductions are legitimate simplifications. Reductionism, in contrast, is to be understood as the claim that one whole set of things is or can be wholly explained in terms of another set. It is, therefore, a reduction in the number of types of entity or the regions of the world. In particular, Reductionism today operates with a stratified conception of the universe--for example, mind, life, matter or energy--and claims to be able to eliminate the higher levels or to explain them completely in terms of the lower. Familiar examples are the claims that mind is observable behaviour and that people's beliefs and attitudes can be entirely explained in terms of their upbring­ ing or social class. Reductionism, therefore, is to be understood as the claim that a given set of things are either illusory or epiphenomenal: they have either no reality or no independent power. Three types of Reductionism have been distinguished3: a. Methodological--breaking down presently unintelligible wholes into their component parts, which can be managed, fmding their structures and func­ tions, and working thence back to an understanding of the whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Reductionism in Ethics
    Socratic Reductionism in Ethics Nicholas Smyth, Fordham University Genealogy is the study of the ways in which concepts, ideas, values and norms have emerged, persisted, and developed over time. Recently, philosophers have begun to argue that the method is of great importance for analytic philosophy, which has traditionally shown some resistance to historical inquiry.i Arguably, genealogy can be particularly fruitful in ethics, where there is notably wide cultural and historical variation across conceptual schemes. To understand where our ethical concepts come from is to gain insight into their social function(s), as well as to envision ways in which they might be improved, revised, or perhaps even eliminated. One of the more striking claims in the genre was made by Bernard Williams, and I shall take it as my point of departure in this paper. Williams argued that modern life in certain Western countries was characterized by the increasing prominence of certain forms of reflection, and that this reflectiveness has actually resulted in the declining influence of thick ethical concepts (such as courage and honesty), which, he claimed were de-prioritized in favor of the use of thin concepts (such as good and right). Williams suggested that the growing influence of reductionist moral theories was a sign that thinner concepts were acquiring more and more currency (Williams, 1986, p. 163). While these claims can certainly seem both puzzling and ambitious, in what follows, I’ll argue that Plato’s ‘Socratic’ dialogues actually contain a genealogical key to the nature and origin of the process Williams describes. In attempting to explain why we use the concepts we do, there is no more profitable figure than that of Socrates, who has exerted enormous influence over the methodological self-image of Western philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • "Reductionism in Ethics" In
    1 Reductionism in Ethics Chris Heathwood What Is Reductionism in Ethics? Ethical reductionism is a doctrine in metaethics, the area of ethics in which we ask not what the facts are concerning our moral obligations, or concerning what things in life are worth pursuing, but, among other things, questions about the nature (or even the very existence) of such facts. One such question is whether moral facts are, to put it roughly, identical to facts of another kind. Reductionism in ethics is the view that they are. That is, reductionists hold that moral facts, or moral properties, are identical to facts or properties that can be expressed using nonmoral vocabulary. Moral reductionism (i) demystifies moral properties – it tells us what they are. It promises further advantages in (ii) explaining how we can come to know moral facts (see epistemology, moral), (iii) explaining why moral facts necessarily depend upon nonmoral facts (see supervenience, moral), and (iv) rebutting charges of the explanatory idleness of moral facts (see explanations, moral). Critics complain, however, that explaining the moral in other terms leaves out what is essential to and important about it: its evaluative or normative nature (see normativity). Two simple examples of reductionist views are the following: the property of being morally wrong just is the property of being generally disapproved of; and the fact that some life is a good life is the very same fact as the fact that that life is an enjoyable life. These theses are said to reduce a moral or evaluative property or fact to a nonmoral, nonevaluative property or fact, in the way that a reductive thesis in the philosophy of mind might reduce psychological facts to neurological facts.
    [Show full text]
  • To Be a Reductionist in a Complex Universe
    How (not) to be a reductionist in a complex universe Karola Stotz Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, A14, Sydney NSW 2006, Australia. Email: [email protected] Word count: 3000 1. Introduction In the last 10 years the reductionism debate has shifted to the idea of reduction as a relation not between theories, but between explanations. A reductionist explains a system’s phenomenon by the properties and interactions of its components. Through this move Sahotra Sarkar attempted to shift attention from a discussion of the logical form of scientific theories to questions regarding the interpretation of scientific explanations (Sarkar 1998). During this time there has been a spate of publications on what has variously been termed 'causal', 'proximal', or 'experimental' biology, including Sahotra Sarkar’s Molecular Models of Life, Marcel Weber’s Philosophy of Experimental Biology, William Bechtel’s Discovering Cell Mechanisms and Alexander Rosenberg’s Darwinian Reductionism (Sarkar 2005; Weber 2005; Bechtel 2006; Rosenberg 2006). Among the emergent themes in the recent literature on proximal biology are: 1. Does proximal biology discover 'mechanisms' rather than laws or theories? 2. What is the relationship between physicalism and antireductionism? 3. How does proximal biology deal with levels of organization, complexity and non-trivial emergence? In the light of these and other themes this paper discusses to what extent should we expect biological phenomena to be reduced to the molecular level. While most philosophers of biology, and arguably biologists as well, subscribe to some kind of physicalism they also belief that biological phenomena in principle cannot be reduced to physical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendence of the Ego: the Non-Existent
    © Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2004, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Ratio (new series) XVII 4 December 2004 0034–0006 TRANSCENDENCE OF THE EGO (THE NON-EXISTENT KNIGHT) Bas C. van Fraassen Abstract I exist, but I am not a thing among things; X exists if and only if there is something such that it = X. This is consistent, and it is a view that can be supported. Calvino’s novel The Non-Existent Knight can be read so as to illustrate this view. But what is my relation to the things there are if I am not identical with any of them – things such as my arms, my garden, the city I live in? I name this the Gur- duloo problem, after the Knight’s page. This relation must be one that admits of degrees; I suggest that we say that I manifest myself through the things thus associated with me. Several pseudo- problems, pertaining to volitional action, supervenience, observ- ability, and the emergence of consciousness, dissolve upon inspection.1 I am as inseparable from the world as light, and yet exiled as light is, gliding over the surface of stones and water, never gripped nor held.2 I exist, but I am not a thing among things. I am neither a physi- cal object nor a mental substance or abstract entity, nor a com- pound thereof. I am not animal, mineral, or vegetable. Nor am I a thing constituted by or composed of things of that sort taken together. I am not some piece of furniture of the universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructive Empiricism in the Social Sciences
    Constructive empiricism in the social sciences Abstract ‘What problems face the aspirant empiricist today?’ is the question Bas C. van Fraassen asks in his seminal work The Scientific Image (1980). In this thesis, I interpret this question as a challenge to develop constructive empiricism [CE] in a field of scientific inquiry other than the context of physics in which it was conceived. The first part of the thesis expounds CE with reference to classical empiricism, discloses some of its fundamental assumptions, and spells out in detail its account of science. In the second part of the thesis, CE is extended to social science. Since CE was developed in the context of natural science, I take an articulation of the alleged fundamental differences between natural and social science as indicating challenges a CE-outlook on social science must address. I also provide a brief history of the gap between the sciences. Then, in the bulk of this thesis, I argue that CE’s model view accommodates social science, that description, prediction and explanation in the light of CE are proper fruits of inquiry in social science, and that CE is able to make sense of the differences in the concepts used in natural and social science. In the discussion of the feasibility of CE for social science, I show concurrently that contemporary articulations of the differences between the natural and the social sciences pose no insuperable problems for the constructive empiricist. Bram van Dijk | 3691454 History & Philosophy of Science | Utrecht University Daily supervisors | dr. Guido Bacciagaluppi & dr. Ruud Abma Third examiner | dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Dogmas of Reductionism: on the Irreducibility of Self-Consciousness and the Impossibility of Neurophilosophy
    Athens Journal of Humanities & Arts - Volume 1, Issue 2 – Pages 135-146 Two Dogmas of Reductionism: On the Irreducibility of Self-Consciousness and the Impossibility of Neurophilosophy By Joseph Thompson Two fundamental assumptions have become dogma in contemporary Anglo-American philosophy of consciousness: that everything about consciousness can be explained in physical terms, and that neuroscience provides the uniquely authoritative methodology for approaching the essential questions. But there has never yet been a successful physical explanation of subjective first-person experience, and reductionism fails to account adequately for thought, reason, and a full range of objects proper to philosophy. Tracking the deep divide within the analytic tradition, I bring a ‘continental’ (German) perspective to bear on recent work from Nagel and Chalmers which shows the reductionist neuroscientific agenda to be incapable of completion, for systematic reasons. Physicalism can explain only structure, function, and mechanism; but self-consciousness is always already embodied and embedded in multiple contexts beyond the structures and functions of brain activity. Consciousness needs to account for itself, to itself, on the terms in which it experiences itself. No explanation of the form provided by ‘neurophilosophy’ is adequate to the most fundamental and essential phenomena of self- consciousness, and neurophilosophy can never philosophically explain or justify itself on its own terms and by its own methodology. These are insuperable limitations for any explanation aspiring to be comprehensive, and such problems have brought contemporary antireductionists in the English-speaking world back around to positions which strongly resemble the ontology and phenomenology of German-language philosophers, particularly Kant, Hegel, and Heidegger.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume's Reductionist Epistemology of Testimony
    DAVID HUME’S REDUCTIONIST EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY Paul Faulkner –––––––––– ABSTRACT David Hume advances a reductionist epistemology of testimony: testimonial beliefs are justified on the basis of beliefs formed from other sources. This reduction, however, has been misunderstood. Testimonial beliefs are not justified in a manner identical to ordinary empirical beliefs; it is true, they are justified by observation of the conjunction between testimony and its truth, it is the nature of the conjunctions that has been misunderstood. The observation of these conjunctions provides us with our knowledge of human nature and it is this knowledge which justifies our testimonial beliefs. Hume gives a naturalistic rather than sceptical account of testimony. –––––––––– Testimony is a unique source of belief. It is unique in the sense that many of our beliefs have been formed only through accepting testimony. Examples are easy to enumerate; my belief that a major ocean current flows from the Gulf of Mexico to North-West Europe and my belief that there have been two World Wars this century both depend on testimony. I have not seen the entire passage of the North Atlantic Drift. Nor do I remember the 1 Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, December 1998, vol. 79, no. 4, pp. 302-313. __________________________________________________________________ catastrophic events that were World War One and Two. It is equally clear that testimony is a unique source of knowledge. Again, unique in the sense that much of our knowledge has been acquired only through accepting testimony. Unless one is to propose a revisionary account of what it is to know, I do not merely believe that there is a major ocean current flowing from the Gulf of Mexico to North-West Europe but I know that there is.
    [Show full text]