The Role of Irony in Kierkegaard's Philosophical Fragments

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Role of Irony in Kierkegaard's Philosophical Fragments The Role of Irony in Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments By C. Stephen Evans Abstract Recent authors have suggested that Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous writings are funda- mentally ironical, and that it is mistaken to see them as containing philosophical and theological claims. Rather, the point of these writings is to show that the really impor- tant theological and philosophical truths cannot be expressed. I argue that such inter- preters are correct to see pervasive irony in Kierkegaard’s writings, but wrong about how this irony works from a literary perspective. Philosophical Fragments is analyzed as a test case to see how Kierkegaard uses irony, and to show that this use of irony is con- sistent with the advancement of substantive philosophical and theological claims. Many authors, beginning with Kierkegaard himself, have seen the writings attributed by Kierkegaard to the Johannes Climacus pseud- onym as having a central place in the Kierkegaardian authorship. In The Point of View for My Work as an Author Kierkegaard says that Concluding Unscientific Postscript is “the turning point in the whole authorship.”1 To signal its special place in the authorship, as a book that is, strictly speaking, neither esthetic nor religious, Kierkegaard says that it had to be attributed to a pseudonym, “although I did place my name as editor, which I have not done with any purely esthetic production – a hint, at least for someone who is concerned with or has a sense for such things.”2 Of course, Postscript is a postscript to Philo- sophical Fragments, albeit a rather long-winded one, and since Kier- kegaard had already placed his name on that earlier volume as “edi- tor,” we are probably safe in assuming that the same kind of “hint” is being offered in the case of Fragments as with Postscript. 1 SFV, SV1 XIII, 542. 2 SFV, SV1 XIII, 523. 64 C. Stephen Evans But what kind of hint is being offered? There is a long tradition of reading Fragments and Postscript as Kierkegaard’s definitive treat- ments of theological and philosophical topics. This tradition has re- cently been criticized by literary-minded commentators, who argue that to read Kierkegaard “straight” as a philosopher/theologian is to misunderstand him. Roger Poole, for example, criticizes what he calls the tradition of “blunt reading” of Kierkegaard in North America.3 Poole attempts to explain this “blunt reading” as due to the fact that the first two prominent interpreters of Kierkegaard in North America were Walter Lowrie and David Swenson. Lowrie, according to Poole, was a retired minister with a “plain, honest mind,” and Poole misiden- tifies David Swenson as a “professor of religion at the University of Minnesota.”4 Thus, Kierkegaard was initially seen in North America through religious eyes, and this “emplacement within theology is the reason why Kierkegaard was translated as he was, and also translated as an orthodox Christian believer…in a manner that paid extraordi- narily little attention to the contours of what Kierkegaard obsessively used to refer to as his ‘indirect communication.’”5 In reality Swenson was a philosopher in one of the most secular de- partments and secular universities in the United States; there was no department of religion at the University of Minnesota at that time or even today.6 However, this mistake on the part of Poole is probably not important, since he sees most philosophers as equally “blunt” in their readings of Kierkegaard as the theologians.7 The real problem 3 Roger Poole “The Unknown Kierkegaard: Twentieth-Century Receptions” in The Cambridge Companion to Kierkegaard, ed. by Alastair Hannay and Gordon D. Marino, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998, pp. 48-75 (abbreviated “The Unknown Kierkegaard”). See particularly pp. 57-66. 4 “The Unknown Kierkegaard,” pp. 59-60. 5 “The Unknown Kierkegaard,” p. 59. 6 There is, however, currently a program of “Religious Studies” that is housed in the Department of Classical and Near Eastern Studies. 7 Poole singles out my own work as an especially bad example of “blunt reading,” tak- ing special exception to the subtitle of my book Passionate Reason, which is “Making Sense of Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments.” (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press 1992.) Poole apparently takes the subtitle to imply that Kierke- gaard’s book is confused and needs to be “rescued.” However, my book is a sustained argument that Fragments is philosophically clear and coherent, though the philosoph- ical content is packaged in a humorous and ironical form; some contemporary readers may need help but that is more a comment on today’s educational system than a cri- tique of Kierkegaard. Curiously, Poole praises Robert Roberts’ Faith, Reason, and History to the skies, as a great contrast to my work. If he had read both my book and The Role of Irony in Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments 65 seems to be that philosophers and theologians have taken Kierke- gaard to be offering claims or views on various issues, and even as sup- porting such claims with arguments. Poole claims that such an ap- proach is doomed to failure, because “Kierkegaard’s text does not of- fer itself to be the object of the question, ‘What does it mean?’ It of- fers itself as the proponent of the question ‘What do you think?’”8 Now one might reasonably think that a false dilemma is here as- sumed and ask whether or not Kierkegaard’s texts could inspire new thinking if they have no meaning of their own that we could under- stand and respond to. However, Poole claims that such a question be- trays a failure to understand that the Kierkegaardian texts “demon- strate to a nicety the Lacanian perception that all we are ever offered in a text is an endless succession of signifiers.”9 If we read Kierkegaard in this Lacanian way, we will see that “Kierkegaard writes text after text whose aim is not to state a truth, not to clarify an issue, not to pro- pose a definite doctrine, not to offer some meaning that could be di- rectly appropriated.”10 To avoid blunt reading, commentators such as Poole stress that one must pay special attention to Kierkegaard’s use of pseudonyms and the role irony plays in the authorship. And quite a few writers have done so. James Conant, for example, has written a series of articles in which he compares Kierkegaard to Wittgenstein, arguing that the “Revocation” attached to Concluding Unscientific Postscript is for- mally analogous to the famous ending of the Tractatus Logico-Philo- sophicus, in which Wittgenstein affirms that the content of the book is nonsense: “My propositions serve as elucidations in the following way: anyone who understands me eventually recognizes them as non- sensical, when he has used them – as steps – to climb up beyond them. (He must, so to speak, throw away the latter after he has climbed up it.)”11 Conant argues that the “Revocation” attached to Postscript by Johannes Climacus functions in the same way as Wittgenstein’s oracu- lar “conclusion,” identifying what has gone before in the book as 8 Roberts’ book carefully, he would have learned that Roberts and myself are close friends and shared many ideas in the writing of both books. While Roberts and I cer- tainly disagree on some points, the two books are in basic and broad agreement. 8 “The Unknown Kierkegaard,” p. 62. 9 Roger Poole Kierkegaard: The Indirect Communication, Charlottesville, Virginia: University of Virginia Press 1993, p. 9. 10 Kierkegaard: The Indirect Communication, p. 7. 11 Ludwig Wittgenstein Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1961, p. 151. 66 C. Stephen Evans “nonsense.”12 If irony as a rhetorical form consists in part in saying something entirely different from and even opposite of the surface meaning of the text, then on Conant’s reading the Climacus writings are ironical through and through; the irony consists in the fact that the texts apparently express what is in fact inexpressible.13 The real point of Kierkegaard according to Conant is that religious truth cannot be expressed but only lived, and the attempts on the part of Climacus to express this truth cannot help but be nonsensical. That generations of philosophers and theologians have read the works without perceiving the nonsense is itself what one might call a deep situational irony. The tradition of taking Kierkegaard seriously as a philosopher and theologian is certainly not confined to North America, however, and Lowrie and Swenson hardly deserve all the blame (or credit) for this tradition. The late Niels Thulstrup surely provides an excellent exam- ple in his “Commentary” on Fragments. Consider, for example, Thul- strup’s judgment on the question of the pseudonymity of Fragments: “The work is both thought and written in Kierkegaard’s own name and therefore cannot be considered a truly pseudonymous work.”14 Since the work is not truly pseudonymous, Thulstrup feels free to regard the book as the one in which Kierkegaard gives “the outline of his dogmat- ics.”15 Fragments is seen as a book in which “Kierkegaard raises philo- sophical and Christian problems one after the other and gives his solu- tions, which open one’s eyes to ever-widening perspectives.”16 Poole would surely judge this account of Fragments as an “outline of dogmat- ics” replete with “problems and solutions” to be blunt reading indeed. In this paper I want to argue that the literary scholars are quite right to call attention to the ironical character of Kierkegaard’s pseudony- mous literature, including the writings attributed to Johannes Clima- 12 Probably the clearest of these articles of Conant’s is “Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein, and Nonsense” in Pursuits of Reason, ed.
Recommended publications
  • Robert R. Cook S~Ren Kierkegaard
    EQ 87:4 (1987), 311-327 Robert R. Cook S~ren Kierkegaard: Missionary to Christendom It was, we understand, Professor Gordon Rupp who coined the usejUl word 'rebunk' to denote a more positive activity than the much more common practice of 'debunking' ideas and people. Mr Cook, a teapher at the Scott Theological College in Kenya, offers an essay which falls into this helpful category of showing us what we may learn from a figure who has not always been appreciated by evangelical Christians. I. A Reappraisal Evangelicals have tended to be very wary of Kierkegaard. His profound influence on the early Barth is well known and the consequent Neo-Orthodox obsessions with God as utterly trans­ cendent and revelation as irrational and non-propositional have been profoundly regretted. Similarly Bultmann's lamentable disinterest in the Jesus of history can clearly be traced back to Kierkegaard,1 In fact a wide variety of modernist themes are embryonically present in lesser known strands of his thought. For example, does not the following sound like an extract from a Tillich sermon?: '.. while the jesting phrase winds its way drolly through the rest of the conversation, the speaker may privately have a rendezvous with the deity, who is present as soon as the uncertainty of all things is thought infinitely.'2 Or when Kierkegaard asserts that the sincere idol worshipper is enjoying a relationship with the living God for ' ... if only the mode of this relationshp is in the truth, the individual is in the truth even if it should happen to be thus related to what is not true',3 he is surely an unwitting precursor of such religious pluralists asJ.
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard on Selfhood and Our Need for Others
    Kierkegaard on Selfhood and Our Need for Others 1. Kierkegaard in a Secular Age Scholars have devoted much attention lately to Kierkegaard’s views on personal identity and, in particular, to his account of selfhood.1 Central to this account is the idea that a self is not something we automatically are. It is rather something we must become. Thus, selfhood is a goal to realize or a project to undertake.2 To put the point another way, while we may already be selves in some sense, we have to work to become real, true, or “authentic” selves.3 The idea that authentic selfhood is a project is not unique to Kierkegaard. It is common fare in modern philosophy. Yet Kierkegaard distances himself from popular ways of thinking about the matter. He denies the view inherited from Rousseau that we can discover our true selves by consulting our innermost feelings, beliefs, and desires. He also rejects the idea developed by the German Romantics that we can invent our true selves in a burst of artistic or poetic creativity. In fact, according to Kierkegaard, becom- ing an authentic self is not something we can do on our own. If we are to succeed at the project, we must look beyond ourselves for assistance. In particular, Kierkegaard thinks, we must rely on God. For God alone can provide us with the content of our real identi- ties.4 A longstanding concern about Kierkegaard arises at this point. His account of au- thentic selfhood, like his accounts of so many concepts, is religious.
    [Show full text]
  • Construing the Elaborate Discourse of Thomas More's Utopia
    California State University, San Bernardino CSUSB ScholarWorks Theses Digitization Project John M. Pfau Library 2006 Irony, rhetoric, and the portrayal of "no place": Construing the elaborate discourse of Thomas More's Utopia Davina Sun Padgett Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/etd-project Part of the English Language and Literature Commons, and the Rhetoric Commons Recommended Citation Padgett, Davina Sun, "Irony, rhetoric, and the portrayal of "no place": Construing the elaborate discourse of Thomas More's Utopia" (2006). Theses Digitization Project. 2879. https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/etd-project/2879 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the John M. Pfau Library at CSUSB ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses Digitization Project by an authorized administrator of CSUSB ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IRONY, RHETORIC, AND THE PORTRAYAL OF "NO PLACE" CONSTRUING THE ELABORATE DISCOURSE OF THOMAS MORE'S UTOPIA A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of California State University, San Bernardino In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts in English Composition by Davina Sun Padgett June 2006 IRONY,'RHETORIC, AND THE PORTRAYAL OF "NO PLACE": CONSTRUING THE ELABORATE DISCOURSE OF THOMAS MORE'S UTOPIA A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of California State University, San Bernardino by Davina Sun Padgett June 2006 Approved by: Copyright 2006 Davina Sun Padgett ABSTRACT Since its publication in 1516, Thomas More's Utopia has provoked considerable discussion and debate. Readers have long grappled with the implications of this text in order to determine the extent to which More's imaginary island-nation is intended to be seen as a description of the ideal commonwealth.
    [Show full text]
  • The Limits of Irony: the Chronillogical World Of
    THELIMITS OF IRONY The Chronillogical World of Martin Arnis' Time's Arrow s a work of Holocaust fiction, Martin Arnis' Time'sArrm is as A, oving and disturbing as it is ingenious; indeed, it is Amis' narrative ingenuity that is responsible for the work's moral and emotional impact. What moves and disturbs the reader is the multitude of ironies that result from the reversal of time- the "narrative conceitn (Diedrick 164) that structures and drives the novel.' In Time'sArrow the normal present-to-future progression becomes the movement from present to past and the normative convention of realistic fiction-the inability to foresee the future- becomes the inability to recall the past. A narrator in Amis' Einstein's Monsters describes the 20th-century as "the age when irony really came into its own" (37) and Time'sAwow is an ironic tour-de-force if ever there was one. The minor and major ironies generated by the time- reversal all follow from the most important effect of the trope- the reversal of all normal cause-effect relations. (The minor become major as the reverse becomes increasinglypmerse.) The irony is structural-formal when the reader recognizes that the novel is an inverted Bihhngsromn- detailing the devolution of the protagonist- and an autobiography told by an amnesiac; but as might be expected, the trope results in an array of more locally comic, and then, grimly dark ironies. Indeed, the work's most disturbing effects are the epistemological and, ultimately, onto- logical uncertainties which are the cumulative impact of the narrative method.
    [Show full text]
  • Søren Kierkegaard's View of Faith Found in Fear And
    SØREN KIERKEGAARD’S VIEW OF FAITH FOUND IN FEAR AND TREMBLING AND PRACTICE IN CHRISTIANITY David Pulliam Submitted to the faculty of the University Graduate School in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in the Department of Philosophy Indiana University September 2016 ii Accepted by the Graduate Faculty, Indiana University, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts. Master’s Thesis Committee __________________________________ Dr. Samuel J.M. Khan, PhD __________________________________ Dr. Cornelis de Waal, PhD __________________________________ Dr. David Pfeifer, PhD iii David Pulliam Søren Kierkegaard’s view of Faith found in Fear and Trembling and Practice in Christianity In this paper I discuss two key works written by Søren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling and Practice in Christianity, under the pseudonyms Johannes de Silentio and Anti-Climacus respectively. I focus on three questions: what is Johannes view of faith, what is Anti-Climacus’ view of faith and how are these Kierkegaard’s conclusions? I argue that stemming from Johannes’ and Anti-Climacus’ points of view, Kierkegaard’s view of faith is the aligning of the self in a trusting relationship with the God-man. One outside of faith can perceive faith to be a paradox or find faith offensive; one must have faith to avoid offense and overcome the paradox. Chapter 1 focuses on the connection between Kierkegaard and his pseudonyms using his work The Point of View. In this chapter I map out Kierkegaard’s method of communication and the purpose for his use of pseudonyms. Chapter 2 focuses on Johannes’ view of faith in Fear and Trembling.
    [Show full text]
  • Søren Kierkegaard Newsletter
    Søren Kierkegaard Newsletter A Publication of the Howard and Edna Hong Kierkegaard Library NUMBER 66: December 2016 Contents ‘ ANNOUNCEMENTS AND NEWS 2 BOOK REVIEWS The Isolated Self: Irony as Truth and Untruth in Søren Kierkegaard's On the Concept of Irony by Brian Söderquist 2 Reviewed by Will Williams Kierkegaard and the Refusal of Transcendence by Steven Shakespeare Reviewed by Lucas Piccinin Lazzaretti 5 Unto the Abyss of Despair—Kierkegaard’s Aesthetic Sphere of Existence (走向绝望的深渊——克尔凯郭尔的美学生活境界) by Wang Qi (王齐) 6 Reviewed by Chingshun J. Sheu ARTICLES Philosophical Fragments: The Infinite Comic Drama Anthony Eagan 8 Tribute to David Kangas Martin Kavka 16 Tribute to Per Lønning Rune Engebretsen 18 Editor: Gordon D. Marino Editorial Intern: Lucas Shurson Assistant Editorial Intern: Emily Shimota Managing Editor: Eileen Shimota Assistant Editor: Begonya Saez Tajafuerce Assistant Editor: Rafael García Pavón Assistant Editor: Catalina Elena Dobre Assistant Editor: Leo Stan Assistant Editor: Christina Danko 1 ANNOUNCEMENTS AND NEWS Professor Anthony Rudd will deliver the lecture in spring 2017. International Kierkegaard Conference Though an exact date has not been established yet, the Library will host the Eighth International Kierkegaard Conference in the summer of 2018. Dr. Richard Purkarthofer will give the plenary lecture. In addition, for more information from the Hong Kierkegaard Library and other news from Kierkegaard scholars and related groups around the world, please see the website of the Hong Kierkegaard Library at http://wp.stolaf.edu/kierkegaard/. K. Brian Söderquist. The Isolated Self: Irony as Truth and Untruth in Søren Kierkegaard's On the Concept of Irony Copenhagen: Søren Kierkegaard Research Centre and C.
    [Show full text]
  • Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript – Excerpts1 PHIL101 Prof
    Søren Kierkegaard Philosophical Fragments, Concluding Scientific Postscript – excerpts1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 3/18/13 10:24 AM Section III: How do I know? Reading III.5 Søren Kierkegaard (1813-1855) was a Danish philosopher who is best known for his interpretation of Christian faith and for his contributions to what would become known as ‘existentialism’. In both cases, a primary focus of Kierkegaard’s work is the immediate quality of our lived experience. What, exactly, is it like to be a human? What constitutes the best form of human life? As we will see, both in the following excerpts and in those in our Ethics section (Section IV), Kierkegaard thinks that our conceptual thought poses a significant potential obstacle to living well – or, more precisely, an obstacle to our living at all, in a sense. Not that Kierkegaard is anti-intellectual in either the theological or ethical context: conceptual thought plays a crucial role in proper human life, he maintains. But we can become “lost” in our concepts, he thinks, and thus fail to live the vital, vivid lives that are otherwise possible for us. In the following passages, Kierkegaard calls attention to this dualism in our relationship with God, the dualism of our objective, conceptual form of thought, on the one hand, and a subjective, “inner” state, on the other. Conceptual thought is the province of reason, and so Kierkegaard first considers belief in God in terms of what reason and the conceptual mind can tell us. Finding this approach unsatisfactory, Kierkegaard then considers belief in God in subjective terms.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Irony in Ian Mcewan's Selected Literary Works
    Univerzita Palackého v Olomouci Filozofická fakulta Katedra anglistiky a amerikanistiky Bc. Eva Mádrová Concept of Irony in Ian McEwan’s Selected Literary Works Diplomová práce PhDr. Libor Práger, Ph.D. Olomouc 2013 Prohlašuji, že jsem tuto diplomovou práci na téma “Concept of Irony in Ian McEwan’s Selected Literary Works” vypracovala samostatně pod odborným dohledem vedoucího práce a uvedla jsem všechny použité podklady a literaturu. V Olomouci dne Podpis I would like to thank my supervisor PhDr. Libor Práger, Ph.D. for his assistance during the elaboration of my diploma thesis, especially for his valuable advice and willingness. Table of contents Introduction 6 1. Ian McEwan 7 2. Methodology: Analysing irony 8 2.1 Interpreter, ironist and text 8 2.2 Context and textual markers 10 2.3 Function of irony 11 2.4 Postmodern perspective 12 3. Fiction analyses 13 3.1 Atonement 13 3.1.1 Family reunion ending as a trial of trust 13 3.1.2 The complexity of the narrative: unreliable narrator and metanarrative 14 3.1.3 Growing up towards irony 17 3.1.4 Dramatic encounters and situations in a different light 25 3.2 The Child in Time 27 3.2.1 Loss of a child and life afterwards 27 3.2.2 The world through Stephen Lewis’s eyes 27 3.2.3 Man versus Universe 28 3.2.4 Contemplation of tragedy and tragicomedy 37 3.3 The Innocent 38 3.3.1 The unexpected adventures of the innocent 38 3.3.2 The single point of view 38 3.3.3 The versions of innocence and virginity 40 3.3.4 Innocence in question 48 3.4 Amsterdam 50 3.4.1 The suicidal contract 50 3.4.2 The multitude
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard on the Transformative Power of Art Antony Aumann Northern Michigan University [email protected]
    Kierkegaard on the Transformative Power of Art Antony Aumann Northern Michigan University [email protected] 1 Kierkegaard’s Therapeutic Project Kierkegaard’s project is first and foremost a therapeutic one. Although he makes theological points and defends philosophical theses, he is not primarily a theologian or philosopher. Instead, he is a “physician of the soul.”1 He aims to help us get better, existentially speaking—to cure us of our spiritual ills. And what he thinks we need to overcome our anxiety and despair is a transformation. In particular, we have to turn our backs on the goal of self-gratification. We must devote our lives to God or the Good rather than ourselves. In sum, Kierkegaard’s prescription for our existential ailments is that we leave behind “the aesthetic life” and head in an ethical or religious direction.2 The central question facing Kierkegaard is thus a practical one. How can he inspire such transformations? How can he get his readers to change who they are at a fundamental level? Following Ryan Kemp and others, I will argue that reason is not the proper tool for the task.3 No mere argument, even if cogent or sound, can move people in the way Kierkegaard wants to move them. Yet, I will maintain that where reason fails, art can succeed. Indeed, to the degree that Kierkegaard ever inspires transformations, it is in virtue of the beauty of his words and the aesthetic appeal of his stories rather than the force of his logic.4 2 Transformational Change To appreciate the challenge facing Kierkegaard, we need to understand the kind of change he wants to effect.
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard's Top Ten Hits #1 Fear and Trembling Do You Remember
    Kierkegaard’s Top Ten Hits #1 Fear and Trembling Do you remember the Biblical story of Abraham taking his son Isaac to be sacrificed to God? Isn’t it shocking to think that God commanded his most faithful servant to commit filicide? And have you ever wondered why Abraham never let Sarah in on his intention to kill their son or why he even obeyed God in the first place? According to Johannes de silentio (John of Silence), the pseudonym under which the book was published, Abraham can be seen either as a delusional murderer or the father of faith. This text extrapolates on the ethical issues of the story, tackling whether Abraham’s actions can be justified and whether there is an Absolute Duty to God. #2 Concept of Anxiety Every human being has experienced what is commonly referred to as anxiety. The word anxiety ​ acts as an umbrella term, referring to a certain state of being. Whether one is experiencing PTSD, a panic attack, or insomnia, these are all anxious states. In this book, Kierkegaard does not go into the specific forms of anxiety, but rather tackles the concept as a whole. He defines it as the actualization of freedom as the possibility for possibility. Although it is treated as a mental illness in modern medicine, the Danish philosopher believed that “pills and powders” cannot erase this fundamental aspect of the human condition. “Anxiety is the dizziness of freedom,” he writes. “Whoever has learned to be anxious in the right way has learned the ultimate.” #3 The Sickness Unto Death Death can be defined, in biological terms, as the moment in which the electrical activity of the brain ceases.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Fragments by Sören Kierkegaard Preface
    Philosophical Fragments by Sören Kierkegaard Preface Propositio: The question is asked in ignorance, by one who does not even know what can have led him to ask it. The present offering is merely a piece, proprio Marte, propriis auspiciis, proprio stipendio. It does not make the slightest pretension to share in the philosophical movement of the day, or to fill any of the various roles customarily assigned in this connection: transitional, intermediary, final, preparatory, participating, collaborating, volunteer follower, hero, or at any rate relative hero, or at the very least absolute trumpeter. The offering is a piece and such it will remain, even if like Holberg’s magister I were volente Deo to write a sequel in seventeen pieces, just as half-hour literature is half-hour literature even in folio quantities. Such as it is, however, the offering is commensurate with my talents, since I cannot excuse my failure to serve the System after the manner of the noble Roman, merito magis quam ignavia; I am an idler from love of ease, ex animi sententia, and for good and sufficient reasons. Nevertheless, I am unwilling to incur the reproach of , at all times an offense against the State, and especially so in a period of ferment; in ancient times it was made punishable by death. But suppose my intervention served merely to increase the prevailing confusion, thus making me guilty of a still greater crime, would it not have been better had I kept to my own concerns? It is not given to everyone to have his private tasks of meditation and reflection so happily coincident with the public interest that it becomes difficult to judge how far he serves merely himself and how far the public good.
    [Show full text]
  • Gristwold on Platonic Irony
    84 Philosophy and Literature Charles L. Griswold, Jr. IRONY IN THE PLATONIC DIALOGUES I nterpreters of Plato have arrived at a general consensus to the Ieffect that there exists a problem of interpretation when we read Plato, and that the solution to the problem must in some way incorporate what has tendentiously been called the “literary” and the “philosophi- cal” sides of Plato’s writing. The problem is created by the fact that Plato wrote in dialogue form, indeed a specific type of dialogue form. The solution must somehow combine into a coherent theory of the “meaning” of the dialogues, the ways in which these texts work (such as the use of imagery, metaphor, myth, allusion, irony, as well as argu- ment). At the same time, there exists enormous disagreement about how one ought to move from these general observations to interpreta- tion of a particular text.1 The problem of interpretation lies not merely in the fact that Plato wrote dialogues. That alone would not necessarily present any herme- neutical issues of unusual difficulty. Plato’s distinctive use of the dialogue form creates the difficulties. The genre that we might call “the Platonic dialogue” is distinguished by several relevant characteristics. First, there is no character called “Plato” who speaks in any of the dialogues; indeed, “Plato” is mentioned twice in the entire corpus, once as being absent (Pho. 59b10), and once as being present (Apol. 38b6). Authorial anonymity is thus an important feature of the dialogues.2 At least ab initio, we are not justified in identifying Plato with any one of his characters.
    [Show full text]