Machine Learning Comes up Against Unsolvable Problem Researchers Run Into a Logical Paradox Discovered by Famed Mathematician Kurt Gödel

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Machine Learning Comes up Against Unsolvable Problem Researchers Run Into a Logical Paradox Discovered by Famed Mathematician Kurt Gödel IN FOCUS NEWS MATHEMATICS Machine learning comes up against unsolvable problem Researchers run into a logical paradox discovered by famed mathematician Kurt Gödel. BY DAVIDE CASTELVECCHI considered to be the foundation for all of mathematics. team of researchers has stum- Gödel and Cohen’s work on the con- bled on a question that is tinuum hypothesis implies that there mathematically unanswerable can exist parallel mathematical uni- Abecause it is linked to logical paradoxes verses that are both compatible with discovered by Austrian mathematician standard mathematics — one in which Kurt Gödel in the 1930s. the continuum hypothesis is added to The mathematicians, who were the standard axioms and therefore working on a machine-learning prob- declared to be true, and another in lem, show that the question of ‘learn- which it is declared false. ALFRED EISENSTAEDT/LIFE PICTURE COLL./GETTY PICTURE ALFRED EISENSTAEDT/LIFE ability’ — whether an algorithm can extract a pattern from limited data LEARNABILITY LIMBO — is linked to a paradox known as the In the latest paper, Yehudayoff and his continuum hypothesis. Gödel showed collaborators define learnability as the that this cannot be proved either true ability to make predictions about a large or false using standard mathematical data set by sampling a small number language. The latest result were pub- of data points. The link with Cantor’s lished on 7 January (S. Ben-David et al. problem is that there are infinitely many Nature Mach. Intel. 1, 44–48; 2019). ways of choosing the smaller set, but the “For us, it was a surprise,” says Amir size of that infinity is unknown. Yehudayoff at the Technion–Israel The authors go on to show that if Institute of Technology in Haifa, who the continuum hypothesis is true, a is a co-author on the paper. He says that small sample is sufficient to make the although there are a number of tech- extrapolation. But if it is false, no finite nical maths questions that are known sample can ever be enough. In this way, to be similarly ‘undecidable’, he did they show that the problem of learn- not expect this phenomenon to show ability is equivalent to the continuum up in a seemingly simple problem in hypothesis. Therefore, the learnability machine learning. Austrian mathematician Kurt Gödel. problem, too, is in a state of limbo that John Tucker, a computer scientist can be resolved only by choosing the at Swansea University, UK, says that the as the sets in Venn diagrams. In particular, it axiomatic universe. paper is “a heavyweight result on the limits relates to the different sizes of sets containing The result also helps to give us a broader of our knowledge”, with foundational impli- infinitely many objects. understanding of learnability, Yehudayoff cations for both mathematics and machine Georg Cantor, the founder of set theory, says. “This connection between compression learning. demonstrated in the 1870s that not all infinite and generalization is really fundamental if you sets are created equal: in particular, the set of want to understand learning.” NOT ALL SETS ARE EQUAL integer numbers is ‘smaller’ than the set of all Researchers have discovered a number of Researchers often define learnability in terms real numbers, also known as the continuum. similarly ‘undecidable’ problems, says Peter of whether an algorithm can generalize its (The real numbers include the irrational O’Hearn, a computer scientist at University knowledge. The algorithm is given the answer numbers, as well as rationals and integers.) College London. In particular, following work to a ‘yes or no’ question — such as “Does this Cantor also suggested that there cannot be by Gödel, Alan Turing — who co-founded image show a cat?” — for a limited number of sets of intermediate size — that is, larger than the theory of algorithms — found a class of objects, and then has to guess the answer for the integers but smaller than the continuum. questions that no computer program can be new objects. But he was not able to prove this continuum guaranteed to answer in any finite number Yehudayoff and his collaborators arrived at hypothesis, and nor were many mathemati- of steps. their result while investigating the connection cians and logicians who followed him. But the undecidability in the latest results between learnability and ‘compression’, which Their efforts were in vain. A 1940 result by is “of a rare kind”, and much more surprising, involves finding a way to summarize the salient Gödel (which was completed in the 1960s by O’Hearn adds: it points to what Gödel found features of a large set of data in a smaller set of US mathematician Paul Cohen) showed that to be an intrinsic incompleteness in any math- data. The authors discovered that the infor- the continuum hypothesis cannot be proved ematical language. The findings will probably mation’s ability to be compressed efficiently either true or false starting from the standard be important for the theory of machine learn- boils down to a question in the theory of sets axioms — the statements taken to be true — ing, he adds, although he is “not sure it will — mathematical collections of objects such of the theory of sets, which are commonly have much impact on the practice”. ■ ©2019 Spri nger Nature Li mited. All ri ghts reserved. 17 JANUARY 2019 | VOL 565 | NATURE | 277 .
Recommended publications
  • LINEAR ALGEBRA METHODS in COMBINATORICS László Babai
    LINEAR ALGEBRA METHODS IN COMBINATORICS L´aszl´oBabai and P´eterFrankl Version 2.1∗ March 2020 ||||| ∗ Slight update of Version 2, 1992. ||||||||||||||||||||||| 1 c L´aszl´oBabai and P´eterFrankl. 1988, 1992, 2020. Preface Due perhaps to a recognition of the wide applicability of their elementary concepts and techniques, both combinatorics and linear algebra have gained increased representation in college mathematics curricula in recent decades. The combinatorial nature of the determinant expansion (and the related difficulty in teaching it) may hint at the plausibility of some link between the two areas. A more profound connection, the use of determinants in combinatorial enumeration goes back at least to the work of Kirchhoff in the middle of the 19th century on counting spanning trees in an electrical network. It is much less known, however, that quite apart from the theory of determinants, the elements of the theory of linear spaces has found striking applications to the theory of families of finite sets. With a mere knowledge of the concept of linear independence, unexpected connections can be made between algebra and combinatorics, thus greatly enhancing the impact of each subject on the student's perception of beauty and sense of coherence in mathematics. If these adjectives seem inflated, the reader is kindly invited to open the first chapter of the book, read the first page to the point where the first result is stated (\No more than 32 clubs can be formed in Oddtown"), and try to prove it before reading on. (The effect would, of course, be magnified if the title of this volume did not give away where to look for clues.) What we have said so far may suggest that the best place to present this material is a mathematics enhancement program for motivated high school students.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind
    Cantor on Infinity in Nature, Number, and the Divine Mind Anne Newstead Abstract. The mathematician Georg Cantor strongly believed in the existence of actually infinite numbers and sets. Cantor’s “actualism” went against the Aristote- lian tradition in metaphysics and mathematics. Under the pressures to defend his theory, his metaphysics changed from Spinozistic monism to Leibnizian volunta- rist dualism. The factor motivating this change was two-fold: the desire to avoid antinomies associated with the notion of a universal collection and the desire to avoid the heresy of necessitarian pantheism. We document the changes in Can- tor’s thought with reference to his main philosophical-mathematical treatise, the Grundlagen (1883) as well as with reference to his article, “Über die verschiedenen Standpunkte in bezug auf das aktuelle Unendliche” (“Concerning Various Perspec- tives on the Actual Infinite”) (1885). I. he Philosophical Reception of Cantor’s Ideas. Georg Cantor’s dis- covery of transfinite numbers was revolutionary. Bertrand Russell Tdescribed it thus: The mathematical theory of infinity may almost be said to begin with Cantor. The infinitesimal Calculus, though it cannot wholly dispense with infinity, has as few dealings with it as possible, and contrives to hide it away before facing the world Cantor has abandoned this cowardly policy, and has brought the skeleton out of its cupboard. He has been emboldened on this course by denying that it is a skeleton. Indeed, like many other skeletons, it was wholly dependent on its cupboard, and vanished in the light of day.1 1Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (London: Routledge, 1992 [1903]), 304.
    [Show full text]
  • Perspective the PNAS Way Back Then
    Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA Vol. 94, pp. 5983–5985, June 1997 Perspective The PNAS way back then Saunders Mac Lane, Chairman Proceedings Editorial Board, 1960–1968 Department of Mathematics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637 Contributed by Saunders Mac Lane, March 27, 1997 This essay is to describe my experience with the Proceedings of ings. Bronk knew that the Proceedings then carried lots of math. the National Academy of Sciences up until 1970. Mathemati- The Council met. Detlev was not a man to put off till to cians and other scientists who were National Academy of tomorrow what might be done today. So he looked about the Science (NAS) members encouraged younger colleagues by table in that splendid Board Room, spotted the only mathe- communicating their research announcements to the Proceed- matician there, and proposed to the Council that I be made ings. For example, I can perhaps cite my own experiences. S. Chairman of the Editorial Board. Then and now the Council Eilenberg and I benefited as follows (communicated, I think, did not often disagree with the President. Probably nobody by M. H. Stone): ‘‘Natural isomorphisms in group theory’’ then knew that I had been on the editorial board of the (1942) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 28, 537–543; and “Relations Transactions, then the flagship journal of the American Math- between homology and homotopy groups” (1943) Proc. Natl. ematical Society. Acad. Sci. USA 29, 155–158. Soon after this, the Treasurer of the Academy, concerned The second of these papers was the first introduction of a about costs, requested the introduction of page charges for geometrical object topologists now call an “Eilenberg–Mac papers published in the Proceedings.
    [Show full text]
  • I Want to Start My Story in Germany, in 1877, with a Mathematician Named Georg Cantor
    LISTENING - Ron Eglash is talking about his project http://www.ted.com/talks/ 1) Do you understand these words? iteration mission scale altar mound recursion crinkle 2) Listen and answer the questions. 1. What did Georg Cantor discover? What were the consequences for him? 2. What did von Koch do? 3. What did Benoit Mandelbrot realize? 4. Why should we look at our hand? 5. What did Ron get a scholarship for? 6. In what situation did Ron use the phrase “I am a mathematician and I would like to stand on your roof.” ? 7. What is special about the royal palace? 8. What do the rings in a village in southern Zambia represent? 3)Listen for the second time and decide whether the statements are true or false. 1. Cantor realized that he had a set whose number of elements was equal to infinity. 2. When he was released from a hospital, he lost his faith in God. 3. We can use whatever seed shape we like to start with. 4. Mathematicians of the 19th century did not understand the concept of iteration and infinity. 5. Ron mentions lungs, kidney, ferns, and acacia trees to demonstrate fractals in nature. 6. The chief was very surprised when Ron wanted to see his village. 7. Termites do not create conscious fractals when building their mounds. 8. The tiny village inside the larger village is for very old people. I want to start my story in Germany, in 1877, with a mathematician named Georg Cantor. And Cantor decided he was going to take a line and erase the middle third of the line, and take those two resulting lines and bring them back into the same process, a recursive process.
    [Show full text]
  • Georg Cantor English Version
    GEORG CANTOR (March 3, 1845 – January 6, 1918) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK, Germany There is hardly another mathematician whose reputation among his contemporary colleagues reflected such a wide disparity of opinion: for some, GEORG FERDINAND LUDWIG PHILIPP CANTOR was a corruptor of youth (KRONECKER), while for others, he was an exceptionally gifted mathematical researcher (DAVID HILBERT 1925: Let no one be allowed to drive us from the paradise that CANTOR created for us.) GEORG CANTOR’s father was a successful merchant and stockbroker in St. Petersburg, where he lived with his family, which included six children, in the large German colony until he was forced by ill health to move to the milder climate of Germany. In Russia, GEORG was instructed by private tutors. He then attended secondary schools in Wiesbaden and Darmstadt. After he had completed his schooling with excellent grades, particularly in mathematics, his father acceded to his son’s request to pursue mathematical studies in Zurich. GEORG CANTOR could equally well have chosen a career as a violinist, in which case he would have continued the tradition of his two grandmothers, both of whom were active as respected professional musicians in St. Petersburg. When in 1863 his father died, CANTOR transferred to Berlin, where he attended lectures by KARL WEIERSTRASS, ERNST EDUARD KUMMER, and LEOPOLD KRONECKER. On completing his doctorate in 1867 with a dissertation on a topic in number theory, CANTOR did not obtain a permanent academic position. He taught for a while at a girls’ school and at an institution for training teachers, all the while working on his habilitation thesis, which led to a teaching position at the university in Halle.
    [Show full text]
  • Humanizing Mathematics and Its Philosophy a Review by Joseph Auslander
    BOOK REVIEW Humanizing Mathematics and its Philosophy A Review by Joseph Auslander Communicated by Cesar E. Silva Humanizing Mathematics and its Philosophy: he wrote and coauthored with Philip Davis and Vera John- Essays Celebrating the 90th Birthday of Reuben Hersh Steiner several books and developed what he terms a Bharath Sriraman, editor Humanist philosophy of mathematics. He has also been a Birkhäuser, 2017 frequent book reviewer for Notices.1 Hardcover, 363 pages ISBN: 978-3-319-61230-0 Although he was not trained as a philosopher, Reuben Hersh has emerged as a major figure in the philosophy of mathematics. His Humanist view is probably the most cogent expression contrasting the dominant philosophies of Platonism and Formalism. Hersh has had a remarkable career. He was born in the Bronx, to immigrant working class parents. He graduated from Harvard at age nineteen with a major in English and worked for some time as a journalist, followed by a period of working as a machinist. He then attended the Courant Institute from which he obtained a PhD in 1962, under the supervision of Peter Lax. Hersh settled into a conventional academic career as a professor at The University of New Mexico, pursuing research mostly in partial differential equations. But beginning in the 1970s he wrote a number of expository articles, in Scientific American, Mathematical Reuben Hersh with co-author Vera John-Steiner Intelligencer, and Advances in Mathematics. Subsequently, signing copies of their book Loving and Hating Mathematics: Challenging the Myths of Mathematical Life Joseph Auslander is Professor Emeritus of Mathematics at the at the Princeton University Press Exhibit, JMM 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembering Paul Cohen (1934–2007) Peter Sarnak, Coordinating Editor
    Remembering Paul Cohen (1934–2007) Peter Sarnak, Coordinating Editor Paul Joseph Cohen, one of the stars some classic texts. There he got his first exposure of twentieth-century mathematics, to modern mathematics, and it molded him as a passed away in March 2007 at the mathematician. He tried working with André Weil age of seventy-two. Blessed with a in number theory, but that didn’t pan out, and unique mathematical gift for solving instead he studied with Antoni Zygmund, writing difficult and central problems, he a thesis in Fourier series on the topic of sets of made fundamental breakthroughs uniqueness. In Chicago he formed many long- in a number of fields, the most spec- lasting friendships with some of his fellow stu- tacular being his resolution of Hil- dents (for example, John Thompson, who re- bert’s first problem—the continuum mained a lifelong close friend). hypothesis. The period after he graduated with a Ph.D. Like many of the mathematical gi- was very productive, and he enjoyed a series of Paul Cohen ants of the past, Paul did not restrict successes in his research. He solved a problem his attention to any one specialty. of Walter Rudin in group algebras, and soon To him mathematics was a unified subject that after that he obtained his first breakthrough on one could master broadly. He had a deep under- what was considered to be a very difficult prob- standing of most areas, and he taught advanced lem—the Littlewood conjecture. He gave the first courses in logic, analysis, differential equations, nontrivial lower bound for the L1 norm of trigo- algebra, topology, Lie theory, and number theory nometric polynomials on the circle whose Fourier on a regular basis.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor and Continuity
    Cantor and Continuity Akihiro Kanamori May 1, 2018 Georg Cantor (1845-1919), with his seminal work on sets and number, brought forth a new field of inquiry, set theory, and ushered in a way of proceeding in mathematics, one at base infinitary, topological, and combinatorial. While this was the thrust, his work at the beginning was embedded in issues and concerns of real analysis and contributed fundamentally to its 19th Century rigorization, a development turning on limits and continuity. And a continuing engagement with limits and continuity would be very much part of Cantor's mathematical journey, even as dramatically new conceptualizations emerged. Evolutionary accounts of Cantor's work mostly underscore his progressive ascent through set- theoretic constructs to transfinite number, this as the storied beginnings of set theory. In this article, we consider Cantor's work with a steady focus on con- tinuity, putting it first into the context of rigorization and then pursuing the increasingly set-theoretic constructs leading to its further elucidations. Beyond providing a narrative through the historical record about Cantor's progress, we will bring out three aspectual motifs bearing on the history and na- ture of mathematics. First, with Cantor the first mathematician to be engaged with limits and continuity through progressive activity over many years, one can see how incipiently metaphysical conceptualizations can become systemati- cally transmuted through mathematical formulations and results so that one can chart progress on the understanding of concepts. Second, with counterweight put on Cantor's early career, one can see the drive of mathematical necessity pressing through Cantor's work toward extensional mathematics, the increasing objectification of concepts compelled, and compelled only by, his mathematical investigation of aspects of continuity and culminating in the transfinite numbers and set theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Prepared to Meet You Where You Are Annual Report 2019 Annual Message We Are Delighted to Present Our 2019 Annual Report
    Prepared to Meet You Where You Are Annual Report 2019 Annual Message We are delighted to present our 2019 Annual Report. We must be prepared to meet people where they Finally, our heartfelt thanks go out to our entire Board, Every year, as we “look back,” we are amazed at how are and we’re doing just that. Our short list includes our volunteers and our 500-plus staff members— much CJE offers to the community. It is often hard a focus on the emerging field of digital health and social workers, nurses, care managers, bus drivers, to choose which programs and services to highlight. assistive technology, the highly-anticipated opening cooks, resident care assistants, therapists and a Very few organizations nationwide offer the breadth of of Tamarisk NorthShore, the thoughtful elevation of whole host of hardworking individuals—who provide programs and services that we do to enhance the lives educational programming for the Sandwich Generation services to more than 20,000 older adults and their of older adults in the Jewish and larger community. and the expansion of supportive services to seniors family members each year. With your continued who want to stay in their own homes safely and with support, we can keep moving forward with creativity In this report, we illustrate how CJE’s Continuum dignity. and intention to “meet people” wherever they are on of Care stands without walls—prepared to “meet” CJE’s Continuum of Care. people wherever they might be in life, utilizing any As we move closer to our 50-year milestone, CJE has of our 35-plus programs to address their individual a strong foundation on which to build for the future.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.5. INFINITE SETS Now That We Have Covered the Basics of Elementary
    2.5. INFINITE SETS Now that we have covered the basics of elementary set theory in the previous sections, we are ready to turn to infinite sets and some more advanced concepts in this area. Shortly after Georg Cantor laid out the core principles of his new theory of sets in the late 19th century, his work led him to a trove of controversial and groundbreaking results related to the cardinalities of infinite sets. We will explore some of these extraordinary findings, including Cantor’s eponymous theorem on power sets and his famous diagonal argument, both of which imply that infinite sets come in different “sizes.” We also present one of the grandest problems in all of mathematics – the Continuum Hypothesis, which posits that the cardinality of the continuum (i.e. the set of all points on a line) is equal to that of the power set of the set of natural numbers. Lastly, we conclude this section with a foray into transfinite arithmetic, an extension of the usual arithmetic with finite numbers that includes operations with so-called aleph numbers – the cardinal numbers of infinite sets. If all of this sounds rather outlandish at the moment, don’t be surprised. The properties of infinite sets can be highly counter-intuitive and you may likely be in total disbelief after encountering some of Cantor’s theorems for the first time. Cantor himself said it best: after deducing that there are just as many points on the unit interval (0,1) as there are in n-dimensional space1, he wrote to his friend and colleague Richard Dedekind: “I see it, but I don’t believe it!” The Tricky Nature of Infinity Throughout the ages, human beings have always wondered about infinity and the notion of uncountability.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory: Cantor
    Notes prepared by Stanley Burris March 13, 2001 Set Theory: Cantor As we have seen, the naive use of classes, in particular the connection be- tween concept and extension, led to contradiction. Frege mistakenly thought he had repaired the damage in an appendix to Vol. II. Whitehead & Russell limited the possible collection of formulas one could use by typing. Another, more popular solution would be introduced by Zermelo. But ¯rst let us say a few words about the achievements of Cantor. Georg Cantor (1845{1918) 1872 - On generalizing a theorem from the theory of trigonometric series. 1874 - On a property of the concept of all real algebraic numbers. 1879{1884 - On in¯nite linear manifolds of points. (6 papers) 1890 - On an elementary problem in the study of manifolds. 1895/1897 - Contributions to the foundation to the study of trans¯nite sets. We include Cantor in our historical overview, not because of his direct contribution to logic and the formalization of mathematics, but rather be- cause he initiated the study of in¯nite sets and numbers which have provided such fascinating material, and di±culties, for logicians. After all, a natural foundation for mathematics would need to talk about sets of real numbers, etc., and any reasonably expressive system should be able to cope with one- to-one correspondences and well-orderings. Cantor started his career by working in algebraic and analytic number theory. Indeed his PhD thesis, his Habilitation, and ¯ve papers between 1867 and 1880 were devoted to this area. At Halle, where he was employed after ¯nishing his studies, Heine persuaded him to look at the subject of trigonometric series, leading to eight papers in analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Beautiful Mind Christopher D
    University of the Pacific Scholarly Commons College of the Pacific aF culty Presentations All Faculty Scholarship 4-1-2006 A Beautiful Mind Christopher D. Goff University of the Pacific, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.pacific.edu/cop-facpres Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Goff, C. D. (2006). A Beautiful Mind. Paper presented at Popular Culture Association (PCA) / American Culture Association (ACA) Annual Conference in Atlanta, GA. https://scholarlycommons.pacific.edu/cop-facpres/485 This Conference Presentation is brought to you for free and open access by the All Faculty Scholarship at Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of the Pacific aF culty Presentations by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Beautiful Mind: the queering of mathematics Christopher Goff PCA 2006 Atlanta The 2001 film A Beautiful Mind tells the exciting story of real-life mathematical genius John Nash Jr. According to the DVD liner notes, director Ron Howard points out that while “there is a lot of creativity in the story-telling,…we are presenting a real world. We approached this story as truthfully as possible and tried to let authenticity be our guide.” (emphasis in original) Moreover, lead Russell Crowe not only “immersed himself in … Sylvia Nasar’s acclaimed biography” of Nash, but he also suggested that the film be shot in continuity (scenes in sequential order) to imbue the film with even more authenticity. Howard agreed. The film enjoyed huge box office success, earning over $170 million, and collared four Academy Awards, including the ultimate: Best Picture.
    [Show full text]