Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Gintis, Herbert Working Paper Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality Working Paper, No. 2000-02 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts Suggested Citation: Gintis, Herbert (2000) : Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality, Working Paper, No. 2000-02, University of Massachusetts, Department of Economics, Amherst, MA This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/105717 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality∗ Herbert Gintis Department of Economics University of Massachusetts, Amherst Phone: 413-586-7756 Fax: 413-586-6014 Email: [email protected] Web: http://www-unix.oit.umass.edu/˜gintis Running Head: Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality March 11, 2000 Abstract Human groups maintain a high level of sociality despite a low level of relatedness among group members. The behavioral basis of this sociality remains in doubt. This paper reviews the evidence for an empirically identifi- able form of prosocial behavior in humans, which we call ‘strong reciprocity,’ that may in part explain human sociality. A strong reciprocator is predisposed to cooperate with others and punish non-cooperators, even when this behavior cannot be justified in terms of extended kinship or reciprocal altruism. We present a simple model, stylized but plausible, of the evolutionary emergence of strong reciprocity. 1 Introduction Human groups maintain a high level of sociality despite a low level of relatedness among group members. Three types of explanation have been offered for this phe- nomenon: reciprocal altruism (Trivers 1971, Axelrod and Hamilton 1981), cultural group selection (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman 1981, Boyd and Richerson 1985) and genetically-based altruism (Lumsden and Wilson 1981, Simon 1993, Wilson and Dugatkin 1997). These approaches are of course not incompatible. Reciprocal ∗ I would like to thank Lee Alan Dugatkin, Ernst Fehr, David Sloan Wilson, and the referees of this Journal for helpful comments, Samuel Bowles and Robert Boyd for many extended discussions of these issues, and the MacArthur Foundation for financial support. This paper is dedicated to the memory of W. D. Hamilton. 1 Strong Reciprocity 2 altruism is almost certainly a very important part of human sociality, and if altru- ism has a genetic basis, it would almost necessarily follow that there has been a coevolutionary development of genes and culture. This paper reviews the evidence for an empirically identifiable form of prosocial behavior in humans that fits neither the extended kinship and or reciprocal altruism frameworks, and probably has a significant genetic component. We call this ‘strong reciprocity.’ A strong reciprocator is predisposed to cooperate with others and punish non-cooperators, even when this behavior cannot be justified in terms of self-interest or extended kinship. We present a simple yet plausible model of the evolutionary emergence of strong reciprocity. 2 The Conditions for Sustaining Cooperation A group of n individuals faces in each time period a ‘public goods game’ in which each member, by sacrificing an amount c>0, contributes an amount b>cshared equally by the other members of the group (all costs and benefits are in fitness units).1 If all members cooperate, each receives a net payoff of b − c>0. However the only Nash equilibrium in this game is universal defection, in which no member contributes, and all members have baseline fitness zero (an arbitrary constant can be added to all fitnesses to account for the growth rate of the overall population). We also assume an individual not in a cooperating group has baseline fitness zero. While cooperation is not an equilibrium outcome in a single play of this public goods game, it can be sustained under appropriate conditions if the game is repeated. Specifically, suppose a members’s contribution is publicly observable, and in any period a player who fails to contribute c is ostracized from the group. Suppose also that group disbands spontaneously at the end of a given period (due to war, pestilence, climate change, and the like) with probability 1−δ. Let π be a member’s total expected fitness when contributing, assuming all other members contribute. Then π can be determined by noting that the current period net fitness gain is b − c, plus with probability δ the game is continued and again has value π in the next 1For a review of the evidence concerning cooperation in nonhuman species see Dugatkin (1997). For a review of cooperation in the two-player public goods game (usually called the iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma), see Dugatkin (1998). Following Axelrod and Hamilton (1981), most models deal with repeated two-person interactions, although Boyd and Richerson (1988,1992) and a few others deal with larger groups. Sethi and Somanathan (1996) is close to this paper in modeling endogenous punishment in a public goods game, but their model predicts a zero level of strong reciprocators in equilibrium. March 11, 2000 Strong Reciprocity 3 period. Therefore we have π = b − c + δπ, which gives 2 b − c π = . (1) 1 − δ A player will contribute, then, as long as (b − c)/(1 − δ)>b, since by not con- tributing, the member earns b during the current period, but is ostracized at the end of the period. Rearranging terms in this inequality, we get Theorem 1. Suppose c be the fitness cost to a group member of cooperating, b is the fitness gain to others in the group when a member cooperates, and δ is a discount factor representing the probability that the group will remain constituted for at least one more period.3 Then cooperation can be sustained in the repeated public goods game if and only if c ≤ δ. b Theorem 1 is of course a completely standard result. With n = 2 is analo- gous to William Hamilton’s (1964) inclusive fitness criterion (where δ represents the degree of relatedness), Robert Triver’s (1971) reciprocal altruism mechanism (where δ = 1), and Robert Axelrod’s (1984) condition for cooperation in the re- peated prisoner’s dilemma. However, the explicit presence of the discount factor δ in Theorem 1 makes it clear that however great the net benefits of cooperation, if groups disband with high probability, then cooperation among self-interested agents cannot be sustained.4 Moreover, periodic social crises are not implausible, since population contractions were likely common in the evolutionary history of Homo sapiens (Boone and Kessler 1999). The very low rate of growth of the human pop- ulation over the whole prehistoric period, plus the high rate of human population growth in even poor contemporary foraging societies in good times (Keckler 1997), suggests periodic crises occurred in the past. Moreover, flattened mortality profiles of prehistoric skeletal populations indicate population crashes ranging from 10% to n 2Equation (1) can also be derived by noting that (b − c)δ is the expected return in period n,so π = (b − c)(1 + δ + δ2 + ...)= (b − c)/(1 − δ). 3In general the discount factor δ is the ratio of the contribution to fitness of a unit payoff in the next period to a unit payoff in the current period. In addition to the probability of group dissolution, this ratio generally depends, among other things, on an individual’s age and health. We abstract from these factors in this paper. 4To my knowledge, endogenous variation in the discount factor δ, central to explaining a high frequency of strong reciprocators in this paper, has not previously been modeled. Nor has the rela- tionship between group longevity and the prevalence of reciprocal altruism in nonhuman species been subjected to systematic empirical investigation. See however Dugatkin and Alfieri (1992). March 11, 2000 Strong Reciprocity 4 54% at a mean rate of once per thirty years (Keckler 1997). Finally, optimal forag- ing models of hunter-gatherer societies often predict stable limit cycles (Belovsky 1988). In contrast to the self-interested agents assumed in Theorem 1, a strong recip- rocator cooperates and punishes noncooperators without considering the value of δ; i.e., even when the probability of future interactions is low. As we shall see, when δ is low, the presence of strong reciprocators can allow the group to secure the benefits of cooperation. However strong reciprocators are altruists, since they bear surveillance and punishment costs not borne by self-interested group members, so they can
Recommended publications
  • Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality∗
    Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality∗ Herbert Gintis Department of Economics University of Massachusetts, Amherst Phone: 413-586-7756 Fax: 413-586-6014 Email: [email protected] Web: http://www-unix.oit.umass.edu/˜gintis Running Head: Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality March 11, 2000 Abstract Human groups maintain a high level of sociality despite a low level of relatedness among group members. The behavioral basis of this sociality remains in doubt. This paper reviews the evidence for an empirically identifi- able form of prosocial behavior in humans, which we call ‘strong reciprocity,’ that may in part explain human sociality. A strong reciprocator is predisposed to cooperate with others and punish non-cooperators, even when this behavior cannot be justified in terms of extended kinship or reciprocal altruism. We present a simple model, stylized but plausible, of the evolutionary emergence of strong reciprocity. 1 Introduction Human groups maintain a high level of sociality despite a low level of relatedness among group members. Three types of explanation have been offered for this phe- nomenon: reciprocal altruism (Trivers 1971, Axelrod and Hamilton 1981), cultural group selection (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman 1981, Boyd and Richerson 1985) and genetically-based altruism (Lumsden and Wilson 1981, Simon 1993, Wilson and Dugatkin 1997). These approaches are of course not incompatible. Reciprocal ∗ I would like to thank Lee Alan Dugatkin, Ernst Fehr, David Sloan Wilson, and the referees of this Journal for helpful comments, Samuel Bowles and Robert Boyd for many extended discussions of these issues, and the MacArthur Foundation for financial support. This paper is dedicated to the memory of W.
    [Show full text]
  • Walrasian Economics in Retrospect
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Bowles, Samuel; Gintis, Herbert Working Paper Walrasian Economics in Retrospect Working Paper, No. 2000-04 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts Suggested Citation: Bowles, Samuel; Gintis, Herbert (2000) : Walrasian Economics in Retrospect, Working Paper, No. 2000-04, University of Massachusetts, Department of Economics, Amherst, MA This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/105719 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu WALRASIAN ECONOMICS IN RETROSPECT∗ Department of Economics University of Massachusetts Amherst, Massachusetts, 01003 Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis February 4, 2000 Abstract Two basic tenets of the Walrasian model, behavior based on self-interested exogenous preferences and complete and costless contracting have recently come under critical scrutiny.
    [Show full text]
  • Reciprocity and Overoptimism in Public Goods Games
    Biased Beliefs and Reciprocal Behavior in Social Dilemmas Von der Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Technischen Hochschule Aachen zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktors der Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaften genehmigte Dissertation vorgelegt von Dipl.-Ing. Anselm Hüwe Berichter: Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Wolfgang Breuer Univ.-Prof. Dr. rer. pol. Christine Harbring Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 21.04.2015 Diese Dissertation ist auf den Internetseiten der Hochschulbibliothek online verfügbar. Table of Contents 1 Introduction ............................................................................................................................. 1 2 Economic Experiments ........................................................................................................... 3 3 Game Theory and (Common) Belief in Rationality ................................................................ 8 3.1 Boundedly Rational Behavior ........................................................................................ 11 3.2 Biased Beliefs ................................................................................................................. 14 4 Social Preferences ................................................................................................................. 15 4.1 When Social Preferences Should Be Assumed, and When Not ..................................... 16 4.2 Evolutionary Analysis ...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Reciprocity: Weak Or Strong? What Punishment Experiments Do (And Do Not) Demonstrate
    BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2012) 35,1–59 doi:10.1017/S0140525X11000069 Reciprocity: Weak or strong? What punishment experiments do (and do not) demonstrate Francesco Guala Department of Economics, University of Milan, 20122 Milan, Italy [email protected] http://users.unimi.it/guala/index.htm Abstract: Economists and biologists have proposed a distinction between two mechanisms – “strong” and “weak” reciprocity – that may explain the evolution of human sociality. Weak reciprocity theorists emphasize the benefits of long-term cooperation and the use of low-cost strategies to deter free-riders. Strong reciprocity theorists, in contrast, claim that cooperation in social dilemma games can be sustained by costly punishment mechanisms, even in one-shot and finitely repeated games. To support this claim, they have generated a large body of evidence concerning the willingness of experimental subjects to punish uncooperative free- riders at a cost to themselves. In this article, I distinguish between a “narrow” and a “wide” reading of the experimental evidence. Under the narrow reading, punishment experiments are just useful devices to measure psychological propensities in controlled laboratory conditions. Under the wide reading, they replicate a mechanism that supports cooperation also in “real-world” situations outside the laboratory. I argue that the wide interpretation must be tested using a combination of laboratory data and evidence about cooperation “in the wild.” In spite of some often-repeated claims, there is no evidence that cooperation in the small egalitarian societies studied by anthropologists is enforced by means of costly punishment. Moreover, studies by economic and social historians show that social dilemmas in the wild are typically solved by institutions that coordinate punishment, reduce its cost, and extend the horizon of cooperation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic and Location of Strong Reciprocity: Anthropological and Philosophical Considerations
    Chapter 7 The Logic and Location of Strong Reciprocity: Anthropological and Philosophical Considerations Jordan Kiper and Richard Sosis Introduction Many behavioral economists and evolutionary anthropologists claim that a cornerstone of human cooperation is the willingness to pay the costs of helping cooperators or punishing cheaters, which is known as strong reciprocity (e.g., Bowles, Boyd, Matthew, & Richerson, 2012; Boyd & Richerson, 2009; Diekmann, Jann, Przepiorka, & Wehrl, 2014; Gintis, Henrich, Bowles, Boyd, & Fehr, 2008; Gintis & Fehr, 2012). Yet critics have put forth several reasons purporting to challenge the very idea of strong reciprocity (e.g., Burnham & Johnson, 2005; Guala, 2012; Hagen & Hammerstein, 2006; Price, 2008; Yamagishi et al., 2012). In this chapter, we exam- ine some of these criticisms and related challenges through anthropological and philosophical lenses, and provide a few ethnographic examples of wartime altruism to illustrate the difficulties of isolating strong reciprocity in the real world. Semantic issues should be acknowledged here at the outset, including the fact that the term strong reciprocity is not a straightforward one. Hearing the words strong and reciprocity together, one would assume that what was being discussed was the robust exchange of something for mutual benefit—but that is not entirely the case. The term strong reciprocity designates one of two things that both entail a cost for an agent: rewarding cooperators when it would be more advantageous to exploit them or pun- ishing defectors when it would be more advantageous to ignore them (Gintis, 2000a, p. 177). In either case, the key is that an agent pays a high price for enforcing reci- procity among others, but does so without any personal benefit for himself or herself, which defies traditional models of self-interested maximization in economics and biology (Gintis et al., 2008, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Reciprocity: Weak Or Strong? What Punishment Experiments Do (And Do Not) Demonstrate
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2012) 35,1–59 provided by RERO DOC Digital Library doi:10.1017/S0140525X11000069 Reciprocity: Weak or strong? What punishment experiments do (and do not) demonstrate Francesco Guala Department of Economics, University of Milan, 20122 Milan, Italy [email protected] http://users.unimi.it/guala/index.htm Abstract: Economists and biologists have proposed a distinction between two mechanisms – “strong” and “weak” reciprocity – that may explain the evolution of human sociality. Weak reciprocity theorists emphasize the benefits of long-term cooperation and the use of low-cost strategies to deter free-riders. Strong reciprocity theorists, in contrast, claim that cooperation in social dilemma games can be sustained by costly punishment mechanisms, even in one-shot and finitely repeated games. To support this claim, they have generated a large body of evidence concerning the willingness of experimental subjects to punish uncooperative free- riders at a cost to themselves. In this article, I distinguish between a “narrow” and a “wide” reading of the experimental evidence. Under the narrow reading, punishment experiments are just useful devices to measure psychological propensities in controlled laboratory conditions. Under the wide reading, they replicate a mechanism that supports cooperation also in “real-world” situations outside the laboratory. I argue that the wide interpretation must be tested using a combination of laboratory data and evidence about cooperation “in the wild.” In spite of some often-repeated claims, there is no evidence that cooperation in the small egalitarian societies studied by anthropologists is enforced by means of costly punishment.
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Reciprocity and Team Production: Theory and Evidence
    G Model JEBO-2349; No. of Pages 12 ARTICLE IN PRESS Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization xxx (2009) xxx–xxx Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jebo Strong reciprocity and team production: Theory and evidence Jeffrey Carpenter a,∗, Samuel Bowles b,c, Herbert Gintis b,d, Sung-Ha Hwang e a Middlebury College and IZA, Munroe Hall, Middlebury, VT 05753, United States b Santa Fe Institute, United States c University of Siena, Italy d Central European University, Hungary e University of Massachusetts, Amherst, United States article info abstract Article history: Punishment of shirkers is often an effective means of attenuating incentive problems and Received 25 April 2006 sustaining coordination in work teams. Explanations of the motivation to punish generally Received in revised form 12 March 2009 rely either on small group size or on a Folk theorem that requires coordinated punishment Accepted 12 March 2009 and, hence, highly accurate information concerning the behavior of each player. We pro- Available online xxx vide a model of team production in which the punishment of shirkers depends on strong reciprocity: the willingness of some team members to contribute altruistically to a joint JEL classification: C72 project and also to bear costs in order to discipline fellow members who do not con- C92 tribute. This alternative does not require small group size, complex coordinated punishing H41 activities, or implausible informational assumptions. An experimental public goods game provides evidence for the behavioral relevance of strong reciprocity and how it differs from Keywords: unconditional altruism. Public good © 2009 Elsevier B.V.
    [Show full text]
  • Poster of His Research on Cultural Evolution
    A bibliometric analysis of the interdisciplinary field of cultural evolution Mason Youngblood1 & David Lahti1,2 1The Graduate Center, City University of New York 2Queens College, City University of New York Introduction Phylogenetics, dual Results 2 inheritance theory, etc… The interdisciplinary study of cultural evolution, or change in socially Overall collaboration in the field is increasing, as shown by the learned traits over time, has historically been approached from a increased ratio of authors to articles (Fig. 1). Network analysis based variety of fields, such as: on co-authorship showed five distinct clusters of collaboration in the • Evolutionary biology literature (Fig. 2), approximately corresponding to: • Anthropology Comparative psychology, Evolutionary psychology, • 1 - comparative psychology, evolutionary biology, etc. evolutionary biology, etc… linguistics, etc… • Psychology • 2 - phylogenetics, dual inheritance theory, etc. • Archaeology 1 3 • 3 - evolutionary psychology, linguistics, etc. • Sociology • 4 - theoretical biology, animal behavior, etc. • 5 - evolutionary archaeology, anthropology, etc. In the last decade efforts have been made to bridge the historical Based on the degree in citation overlap (Fig. 3), groups 4 and 5 are the divisions between these approaches to develop a unified field of most intellectually isolated from the rest of the field. cultural evolution (Mesoudi, 2015), but much of this has been based upon subjective perceptions of how the field is structured in terms of 4 community effects collectivism
    [Show full text]
  • Strong Reciprocity and the Roots of Human Morality
    Soc Just Res DOI 10.1007/s11211-008-0067-y Strong Reciprocity and the Roots of Human Morality Herbert Gintis Æ Joseph Henrich Æ Samuel Bowles Æ Robert Boyd Æ Ernst Fehr Ó Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2008 Abstract Human morality is a key evolutionary adaptation on which human social behavior has been based since the Pleistocene era. Ethical behavior is constitutive of human nature, we argue, and human morality is as important an adaptation as human cognition and speech. Ethical behavior, we assert, need not be a means toward personal gain. Because of our nature as moral beings, humans take pleasure in acting ethically and are pained when acting unethically. From an evolutionary viewpoint, we argue that ethical behavior was fitness-enhancing in the years marking the emergence of Homo sapiens because human groups with many altruists fared better than groups of selfish individuals, and the fitness losses sustained by altruists were more than compensated by the superior performance of the groups in which they congregated. Keywords Morality Á Human nature Á Evolution Á Reciprocity Á Sociobiology Á Altruism H. Gintis (&) Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, New Mexico and, The Central European University, Budapest, Hungary e-mail: [email protected] J. Henrich University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada S. Bowles Santa Fe Institute, Santa Fe, NM, USA R. Boyd University of California, Los Angeles, CA, USA E. Fehr University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland 123 Soc Just Res The Nature of Human Morality The two volumes under review summarize a body of research suggesting that human morality is a key evolutionary adaptation on which human social behavior has been based since the Pleistocene era.
    [Show full text]
  • Ultimate and Proximate Explanations of Strong Reciprocity
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Erasmus University Digital Repository HPLS (2017) 39:25 DOI 10.1007/s40656-017-0151-4 ORIGINAL PAPER Ultimate and proximate explanations of strong reciprocity Jack Vromen1 Received: 8 December 2016 / Accepted: 9 August 2017 Ó The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication Abstract Strong reciprocity (SR) has recently been subject to heated debate. In this debate, the ‘‘West camp’’ (West et al. in Evol Hum Behav 32(4):231–262, 2011), which is critical of the case for SR, and the ‘‘Laland camp’’ (Laland et al. in Science, 334(6062):1512–1516, 2011, Biol Philos 28(5):719–745, 2013), which is sympathetic to the case of SR, seem to take diametrically opposed positions. The West camp criticizes advocates of SR for conflating proximate and ultimate cau- sation. SR is said to be a proximate mechanism that is put forward by its advocates as an ultimate explanation of human cooperation. The West camp thus accuses advocates of SR for not heeding Mayr’s original distinction between ultimate and proximate causation. The Laland camp praises advocates of SR for revising Mayr’s distinction. Advocates of SR are said to replace Mayr’s uni-directional view on the relation between ultimate and proximate causes by the bi-directional one of recip- rocal causation. The paper argues that both the West camp and the Laland camp misrepresent what advocates of SR are up to. The West camp is right that SR is a proximate cause of human cooperation.
    [Show full text]
  • Identity, Kinship, and the Evolution of Cooperation Burton Voorhees1
    Identity, Kinship, and the Evolution of Cooperation Burton Voorhees1*, Dwight Read2, and Liane Gabora3 1 Center for Science, Athabasca University, 1 University Drive, Athabasca, AB, T9S 3A3; [email protected], http://science.athabascau.ca/staff-pages/burtv/ 2 Department of Anthropology, UCLA, 375 Portola Plaza, 341 Haines Hall, Box 951553, Los Angeles, CA 90095; [email protected], http://www.anthro.ucla.edu/faculty/dwight-read 3 Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Okanagan Campus, Kelowna, BC Canada V1V 1V7; [email protected], https://people.ok.ubc.ca/lgabora/ * Please address correspondence to Burton Voorhees, [email protected] To appear in Current Anthropology. This draft may not be identical to the final version that was accepted for publication. Running Head: Identity, Kinship, and the Evolution of Cooperation Abstract Extensive cooperation among biologically unrelated individuals is uniquely human and much current research attempts to explain this fact. We draw upon social, cultural, and psychological aspects of human uniqueness to present an integrated theory of human cooperation that explains aspects of human cooperation that are problematic for other theories (e.g., defector invasion avoidance, preferential assortment to exclude free riders, and the second order free rider problem). We propose that the evolution of human cooperative behavior required (1) a capacity for self-sustained, self-referential thought manifested as an integrated worldview, including a sense of identity and point of view, and (2) the cultural formation of kinship-based social organizational systems within which social identities can be established and transmitted through enculturation. Human cooperative behavior arose, we argue, through the acquisition of a culturally grounded social identity that included the expectation of cooperation among kin.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Direct Reciprocity Under Uncertainty Can Explain Human Generosity in One-Shot Encounters
    Evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty can explain human generosity in one-shot encounters Andrew W. Deltona,b,1,2, Max M. Krasnowa,b,1,2, Leda Cosmidesa,b, and John Toobya,c aCenter for Evolutionary Psychology and Departments of bPsychology and cAnthropology, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106 Edited by Kenneth Binmore, University College London, London WC1E 6BT, United Kingdom and accepted by the Editorial Board May 27, 2011 (received for review February 9, 2011) Are humans too generous? The discovery that subjects choose to proven equally challenging to biologists, because they seem to incur costs to allocate benefits to others in anonymous, one-shot violate the expectations of widely accepted models of fitness economic games has posed an unsolved challenge to models of maximization that predict selfishness in the absence of either economic and evolutionary rationality. Using agent-based simu- (i) genetic relatedness, (ii) conditions favoring reciprocity, or lations, we show that such generosity is the necessary byproduct (iii) reputation enhancement (22). of selection on decision systems for regulating dyadic reciprocity The most glaring anomaly stems from the fact that, according to under conditions of uncertainty. In deciding whether to engage in both evolutionary and economic theories of cooperation, whether dyadic reciprocity, these systems must balance (i) the costs of mis- an interaction is repeated or one-shot should make a crucial dif- taking a one-shot interaction for a repeated interaction (hence, ference in how agents act. The chance of repeated interactions risking a single chance of being exploited) with (ii) the far greater offers the only possibility of repayment for forgoing immediate costs of mistaking a repeated interaction for a one-shot interaction selfish gains when the interactants are not relatives and the situ- (thereby precluding benefits from multiple future cooperative ation precludes reputation enhancement in the eyes of third par- interactions).
    [Show full text]