Gene-Culture Coinheritance of a Behavioral Trait

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gene-Culture Coinheritance of a Behavioral Trait vol. 192, no. 3 the american naturalist september 2018 Gene-Culture Coinheritance of a Behavioral Trait Elliot G. Aguilar* and Erol Akçay University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104 Submitted October 5, 2017; Accepted April 5, 2018; Electronically published July 16, 2018 Online enhancements: appendix. abstract: Many physical and behavioral traits in animals, including havior (Pérusse et al. 1994), handedness (Laland 2008), fer- humans, are inherited both genetically and culturally. The presence of tility (Kosova et al. 2010; Alvergne et al. 2011; Colleran and different inheritance systems affecting the same trait can result in com- Mace2015;Colleran2016),andAlzheimer’sdiseasebiomark- plex evolutionary dynamics. Here, we present a general model that elu- ers (Levy et al. 2016) in humans as well as song form in pas- cidates the distinct roles of cultural and genetic inheritance systems and serine birds (Freeberg 2000; Feher et al. 2009), mate choice their interaction in driving the evolution of complex phenotypes. In par- in Trinidadian guppies (Dugatkin 1992), and foraging be- ticular, we derive a Price equation that incorporates both cultural and havior in bottlenose dolphins (Krŭtzen et al. 2005). In each genetic inheritance of a phenotype where the effects of genes and cul- fi ture are additive. We then use this equation to investigate whether a of these cases, an important tness-related trait or behavior genetically maladaptive phenotype can evolve under dual transmission. is determined by not only genetic inheritance but also cul- We examine the special case of altruism using an illustrative model and tural transmission from individuals that may not have con- show that cultural selection can overcome genetic selection when the tributedanygeneticmaterial.Giventheimportanceofgenetic variance in culture is sufficiently high with respect to genes. We also and nongenetic inheritance in determining so many behav- show that the presence of cultural transmission can modify genetic se- ioral traits, it is imperative to develop a better theoretical un- lection itself, making genetic selection more favorable to a trait than derstanding of how such coinheritance affects the evolution under purely genetic inheritance. Last, we consider the effect of differ- ent timescales of genetic and cultural transmission. We discuss the im- of behavioral traits. plications of our results for understanding the evolution of important In recent years, evolutionary theorists have begun to in- coinherited behaviors, including how our framework can be used to vestigate the consequences of multiple inheritance systems generate quantitative estimates of selection pressures required for a ge- (Otto et al. 1995; Bonduriansky and Day 2009; Day and Bon- netically maladaptive trait to evolve. duriansky 2011). In a pair of articles, Day and Bondurianski Keywords: gene-culture coevolution, altruism, multiple inheritance, used the Price equation to construct a general framework for Price equation. modeling genetic and nongenetic traits that jointly deter- mined phenotype. However, their approach was limited to vertical transmission of the nongenetic trait and thus kept Introduction track of only the reproductive fitness consequences of both systems of inheritance. While this approach gives a mathe- Behavioral traits are among the most complex phenotypes matically valid description of evolutionary change in a trait, under study in evolutionary biology. At the heart of that com- it obscures the separate roles of genetic and nongenetic in- plexity is the interaction between genetic inheritance and the heritance and selection in causing that change. In another environment (Turkheimer 2000). In organisms with social recent article, El Mouden et al. (2014) developed a Price equa- learning, a significant component of the environment can tion for cultural evolution and addressed the question of how be conspecific individuals who serve as models for socially potential conflicts between cultural and genetic selection might learned behaviors, leading to cultural transmission. Differ- be resolved. However, their work considered cultural and ge- ential cultural transmission of behaviors or traits can lead netic transmission of (and selection on) a trait as mutually ex- to an evolutionary process that operates in tandem with ge- clusive alternatives and did not attempt to model the cotrans- netic evolution. Examples of behaviors that are influenced by mission of a single trait through both culture and genetics both genetic and cultural transmission span a wide range, (for more on this point, see “Discussion”). such as antisocial behavior (Maes et al. 2007), parental be- To account for the distinct causal roles of cultural and ge- netic selection, one needs to consider fitness measures in both * Corresponding author; email: [email protected]. ORCIDs: Akçay, http://orcid.org/0000-0001-8149-7124. systems of inheritance simultaneously. This is ultimately be- – q cause ancestors in one system may not be identical to the Am. Nat. 2018. Vol. 192, pp. 000 000. 2018 by The University of Chicago. fi 0003-0147/2018/19203-57995$15.00. All rights reserved. ancestors in another. A tness measure implies a mapping DOI: 10.1086/698872 from ancestral to descendant individuals: ancestors who map This content downloaded from 165.123.034.086 on August 14, 2018 21:07:50 PM All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c). 000 The American Naturalist (i.e., contribute hereditary material) to more descendants ple forms of inheritance are present. This point was high- have higher fitness. Multiple inheritance systems mean the lighted nearly 40 years ago by Richerson and Boyd (1978), possibilityofmultiplemappings.Forexample,imagineapop- who remarked that when both genes and culture determine ulation of asexual organisms (as in fig. 1) with a phenotype a single phenotype, the value of the phenotype that maximizes fi p determined by genetic and cultural inheritance. Let pa be genetic tness may differ from the value that maximizes cul- fi fl the phenotype of an ancestor and pd the phenotype of her ge- tural tness, leading to con icts between the two inheritance netic descendant. If both genes and culture are inherited from systems. Modeling phenotype as the outcome of a nonzero the same ancestor and we assume no flaws in transmission sum game between cultural and genetic inheritance, they p and identical environmental effects, then pa pd. However, showed the conditions under which the Nash equilibrium if one’s genetic parent and cultural role model are not the phenotype would be the cultural fitness optimum and not ( fi same individual, then it is possible that pa pd.Ifwecon- the optimum value for genetic tness. In the ensuing de- sider the mapping solely from genetic parents to offspring, cades, cultural evolution theory has largely focused on the this discrepancy will appear simply to be an unexplained de- case when the genetic trait encodes a learning rule that de- viation between parents and offspring. However, also keep- termines how a cultural trait is acquired (Cavalli-Sforza and ing track of the mapping between cultural role models and Feldman 1981; Boyd and Richerson 1988; Boyd et al. 2003; pupils, we might find that certain individuals map to more Guzmán et al. 2007; Lehmann et al. 2008). By contrast, the cultural descendants as a result of their phenotype because problem of conflict between inheritance systems that affect of selection in the cultural domain. Thus, what appears un- the same trait has received surprisingly little attention, with der one mapping to be an unexplained deviation between the notable exception of the model of Findlay (1992), which parent and offspring is revealed under another mapping to treated only vertical cultural transmission. This dearth of at- be a force of selection in its own right. tention is particularly surprising, given the anthropological The argument above underscores the importance of con- evidence for behavioral and social practices in humans that sidering fitness in each domain of inheritance when multi- reduce reproductive fitness (Glanville 1987; Logan and Qirko a A1 A2 A3 D1 D2 D3 b gcPhenotypes Reproductive fitness Cultural fitness 10 = 1 = 1 = 0 A1 pa1 w1 s1 10 = 1 = 2 = 0 A2 pa2 w2 s2 11 = 2 = 0 = 3 A3 pa3 w3 s3 11 = 2 D1 pd1 11 = 2 D2 pd2 11 = 2 D3 pd3 Figure 1: a, Diagram shows the hereditary relationships between ancestors (A1, A2, A3) and descendants (D1, D2, D3). Solid lines indicate reproductive relationships, while dashed lines show cultural learning. While A3 sired no offspring, he is the cultural learning model for all descendants. b, Genotype, culture type, phenotypic, and fitness values for each ancestor and descendant (excepting fitness values). Each p descendant has only one genetic and cultural ancestor; thus, each solid edge corresponds to vij 1, and each dashed edge corresponds to p gij 1. This content downloaded from 165.123.034.086 on August 14, 2018 21:07:50 PM All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c). Gene-Culture Coinheritance of a Trait 000 1996). Examples include clubbing pregnant women to in- ness, conscientiousness; Goldberg 1993), or a morphological duce birth in Colombia (Reichel-Dolmatoff and Reichel- one such as body size. We assume that the effects of genetic Dolmatoff 2013), unhygienic neonatal care practices in Ban- and cultural inheritance are additive; that is, we express an gladesh
Recommended publications
  • The Mirror of Physics: on How the Price Equation Can Unify Evolutionary Biology
    Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03339-6 ORIGINAL RESEARCH The mirror of physics: on how the Price equation can unify evolutionary biology Victor J. Luque1 · Lorenzo Baravalle2 Received: 30 September 2020 / Accepted: 26 July 2021 © The Author(s) 2021 Abstract Due to its high degree of complexity and its historical nature, evolutionary biol‑ ogy has been traditionally portrayed as a messy science. According to the supporters of such a view, evolutionary biology would be unable to formulate laws and robust theories, instead just delivering coherent narratives and local models. In this article, our aim is to challenge this view by showing how the Price equation can work as the core of a general theoretical framework for evolutionary phenomena. To support this claim, we outline some unnoticed structural similarities between physical theo‑ ries (in particular, classical mechanics) and evolutionary biology. More specifcally, we shall argue that the Price equation, in the same way as fundamental formalisms in physics, can serve as a heuristic principle to formulate and systematise diferent theories and models in evolutionary biology. Keywords Evolutionary biology · Price equation · Complexity · Metatheoretical structuralism · Guiding principle · Classical mechanics This article belongs to the topical collection “Simplicity out of Complexity? Physics and the Aims of Science,” Edited by Florian J. Boge, Martin King, Paul Grünke and Miguel Ángel Carretero Sahuquillo. * Victor J. Luque [email protected] Lorenzo Baravalle [email protected]
    [Show full text]
  • The 'Algebra of Evolution': the Robertson–Price Identity and Viability Selection for Body Mass in a Wild Bird Population
    Edinburgh Research Explorer The ‘algebra of evolution’: the Robertson–Price identity and viability selection for body mass in a wild bird population Citation for published version: Hajduk, GK, Walling, CA, Cockburn, A & Kruuk, LEB 2020, 'The ‘algebra of evolution’: the Robertson–Price identity and viability selection for body mass in a wild bird population', Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, vol. 375, no. 1797, 20190359. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0359 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1098/rstb.2019.0359 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 The ‘algebra of evolution’: the Robertson–Price identity and royalsocietypublishing.org/journal/rstb viability selection for body mass in a wild bird population Research G. K. Hajduk1, C. A. Walling1, A. Cockburn2 and L. E. B. Kruuk2 1 Cite this article: Hajduk GK, Walling CA, Institute of Evolutionary Biology, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh EH9 3FL, UK 2Research School of Biology, Australian National University, Canberra, ACT 2601, Australia Cockburn A, Kruuk LEB.
    [Show full text]
  • Multilevel Selection and Population Genetics in Structured
    Multilevel Selection, Population Genetics and Cooperation in Structured Populations NIMBioS Tutorial: Game Theoretical Modeling of Evolution in Structured Populations Jeremy Van Cleve University of Kentucky 26 April 2016 Multilevel selection, pop gen and games in structured pops UNIVERSITY OF KENTUCKY How do cooperative behaviors evolve? Cooperation occurs when: focal: cost to improve state of its partner partner: beneft from improved state Food improves state ⟶ higher ftness Multilevel selection, pop gen and games in structured pops UNIVERSITY OF KENTUCKY trate into a tightWhen form they known cease as moving,and the a when cells Mexican there ofenvironment hat. is the lacks Then, either slug electrolytes, concen- directional when light it orimmune is system, no before they very are light. shed at moist, thefunctioning rear of simultaneously the slug. asthe liver, slug from kidney, front and toered back innate class picking up of toxins cells and calledand bacteria, ultimately sentinel become cells the stalk. that There is sweep athe through recently discov- constituent cells. Those atthe slug the lacks a front nervous system, direct there are movement differencesmove: among an important advantage to themore quickly social and farther stage. than Though any individual amoebaeffectively could recovering the solitaryrear, stage. and these The cells slug can feed moves sheath on any largely bacteria made they discover, upfrom of it cellulose, it in drops some cells important at ways. the Astoward light and heat it and away from ammonia crawls ( throughwhich a then elongatesAfter slightly a few and hours, beginsa this center to center concentrates into crawl in aconcentrate around a mound, in great process streams of calledhighest dicty cells, aggregation concentration.
    [Show full text]
  • The Purpose of Adaptation
    Downloaded from http://rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org/ on February 1, 2018 The purpose of adaptation Andy Gardner rsfs.royalsocietypublishing.org School of Biology, University of St Andrews, Dyers Brae, St Andrews KY16 9TH, UK AG, 0000-0002-1304-3734 A central feature of Darwin’s theory of natural selection is that it explains the purpose of biological adaptation. Here, I: emphasize the scientific impor- tance of understanding what adaptations are for, in terms of facilitating Research the derivation of empirically testable predictions; discuss the population genetical basis for Darwin’s theory of the purpose of adaptation, with refer- Cite this article: Gardner A. 2017 The ence to Fisher’s ‘fundamental theorem of natural selection’; and show that a purpose of adaptation. Interface Focus 7: deeper understanding of the purpose of adaptation is achieved in the context 20170005. of social evolution, with reference to inclusive fitness and superorganisms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2017.0005 One contribution of 20 to a theme issue ‘New 1. The purpose of adaptation trends in evolutionary biology: biological, Darwinism is a theory of the process of adaptation, i.e. the appearance of design philosophical and social science perspectives’. in the biological world. The problem of how to explain adaptation is an ancient one, and it famously provided the basis for William Paley’s [1] argument for Subject Areas: the existence of an intelligent, divine designer. This problem was decisively solved by Charles Darwin [2], whose theory of evolution by natural selec- biomathematics tion—in which heritable variations associated with greater survival and reproductive success are identified as being more likely to accumulate in natural Keywords: populations—explained the adaptation of organisms in purely naturalistic, natural selection, fundamental theorem, mechanical terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Struggle for Existence: the Models for Darwinian and Non-Darwinian Selection
    Struggle for Existence: the models for Darwinian and non-Darwinian selection G. Karev1, F. Berezovskaya2 1National Center for Biotechnology Information, Bethesda, MD 20894, USA. Email: [email protected] 2 Howard University, Washington, DC 20059, USA e-mail: [email protected] Abstract Classical understanding of the outcome of the struggle for existence results in the Darwinian “survival of the fittest”. Here we show that the situation may be different, more complex and arguably more interesting. Specifically, we show that different versions of inhomogeneous logistic-like models with a distributed Malthusian parameter imply non-Darwinian “survival of everybody”. In contrast, the inhomogeneous logistic equation with distributed carrying capacity shows Darwinian “survival of the fittest”. We also consider an inhomogeneous birth-and-death equation and give a simple proof that this equation results in the “survival of the fittest”. In addition to this known result, we find an exact limit distribution of the parameters of this equation. We also consider “frequency-dependent” inhomogeneous models and show that although some of these models show Darwinian “survival of the fittest”, there is not enough time for selection of the fittest species. We discuss the well-known Gauze’s Competitive exclusion principle that states that “Complete competitors cannot coexist”. While this principle is often considered as a direct consequence of the Darwinian “survival of the fittest”, we show that from the point of view of developed mathematical theory complete competitors can in fact coexist indefinitely. 1. Introduction. Darwinian evolution and Competitive Exclusion principle In his 1934 book, G.F. Gause described his experiments where he cultivated two types of yeast, S.
    [Show full text]
  • George Price's Contributions to Evolutionary Genetics
    J. theor. Biol. (1995) 175, 373–388 George Price’s Contributions to Evolutionary Genetics S A. F Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of California, Irvine, CA 92717, U.S.A. (Received on 9 November 1994, Accepted in revised form on 14 February 1995) George Price studied evolutionary genetics for approximately seven years between 1967 and 1974. During that brief period Price made three lasting contributions to evolutionary theory; these were: (i) the Price Equation, a profound insight into the nature of selection and the basis for the modern theories of kin and group selection; (ii) the theory of games and animal behavior, based on the concept of the evolutionarily stable strategy; and (iii) the modern interpretation of Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection, Fisher’s theorem being perhaps the most cited and least understood idea in the history of evolutionary genetics. This paper summarizes Price’s contributions and briefly outlines why, toward the end of his painful intellectual journey, he chose to focus his deep humanistic feelings and sharp, analytical mind on abstract problems in evolutionary theory. 7 1995 Academic Press Limited Introduction (iii) Price (1972b) was the first to crack the most obscure and misunderstood of R. A. Fisher’s many At the age of 44, George Price quit his engineering job oracles: the fundamental theorem of natural selection. at IBM and took up evolutionary genetics. Price This theorem is perhaps the most widely quoted result moved to the Galton Laboratories at London in 1967, in evolutionary theory, yet Price demonstrated where C. A. B. Smith, Weldon Professor of Biometry, convincingly that the consensus interpretation of the provided him with space and encouragement.
    [Show full text]
  • The Place of Development in Mathematical Evolutionary Theory SEAN H
    COMMENTARY AND PERSPECTIVE The Place of Development in Mathematical Evolutionary Theory SEAN H. RICEÃ Department of Biological Sciences, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, Texas ABSTRACT Development plays a critical role in structuring the joint offspring–parent phenotype distribution. It thus must be part of any truly general evolutionary theory. Historically, the offspring–parent distribution has often been treated in such a way as to bury the contribution of development, by distilling from it a single term, either heritability or additive genetic variance, and then working only with this term. I discuss two reasons why this approach is no longer satisfactory. First, the regression of expected offspring phenotype on parent phenotype can easily be nonlinear, and this nonlinearity can have a pronounced impact on the response to selection. Second, even when the offspring–parent regression is linear, it is nearly always a function of the environment, and the precise way that heritability covaries with the environment can have a substantial effect on adaptive evolution. Understanding these complexities of the offspring–parent distribution will require understanding of the developmental processes underlying the traits of interest. I briefly discuss how we can incorporate such complexity into formal evolutionary theory, and why it is likely to be important even for traits that are not traditionally the focus of evo–devo research. Finally, I briefly discuss a topic that is widely seen as being squarely in the domain of evo–devo: novelty. I argue that the same conceptual and mathematical framework that allows us to incorporate developmental complexity into simple models of trait evolution also yields insight into the evolution of novel traits.
    [Show full text]
  • The Price Equation, Fisher's Fundamental Theorem, Kin Selection, and Causal Analysis
    Evolution, 51(6), 1997, pp. 1712-1729 THE PRICE EQUATION, FISHER'S FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM, KIN SELECTION, AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS STEVEN A. FRANK Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of California, Irvine, California 92697-2525 E-mail: [email protected] Abstract.--A general framework is presented to unify diverse models of natural selection. This framework is based on the Price Equation, with two additional steps. First, characters are described by their multiple regression on a set of predictor variables. The most common predictors in genetics are alleles and their interactions, but any predictor may be used. The second step is to describe fitness by multiple regression on characters. Once again, characters may be chosen arbitrarily. This expanded Price Equation provides an exact description of total evolutionary change under all conditions, and for all systems of inheritance and selection. The model is first used for a new proof of Fisher's fundamental theorem of natural selection. The relations are then made clear among Fisher's theorem, Robertson's covariance theorem for quantitative genetics, the Lande-Arnold model for the causal analysis of natural selection, and Hamilton's rule for kin selection. Each of these models is a partial analysis of total evolutionary change. The Price Equation extends each model to an exact, total analysis of evolutionary change for any system of inheritance and selection. This exact analysis is used to develop an expanded Hamilton's rule for total change. The expanded rule clarifies the distinction between two types of kin selection coefficients. The first measures components of selection caused by correlated phenotypes of social partners.
    [Show full text]
  • Joint Phenotypes, Evolutionary Conflict and the Fundamental Theorem of Natural Selection David C
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations Biology 5-19-2014 Joint phenotypes, evolutionary conflict and the fundamental theorem of natural selection David C. Queller Washington University in St Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/bio_facpubs Part of the Biology Commons, Evolution Commons, and the Population Biology Commons Recommended Citation Queller, David C., "Joint phenotypes, evolutionary conflict and the fundamental theorem of natural selection" (2014). Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations. 57. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/bio_facpubs/57 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Biology at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Joint phenotypes, evolutionary conflict, and the fundamental theorem of natural selection David C. Queller Department of Biology Washington University in St. Louis St. Louis, MO 63130 USA Email: [email protected] Prepublication version. Pulbished in Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. B 369:20130423 doi:10.1098/rstb.2013.0423. 1 Abstract Multiple organisms can sometimes affect a common phenotype. For example the portion of a leaf eaten by an insect is a joint phenotype of the plant and the insect and the amount of food obtained by an offspring can be joint trait with its mother. Here I describe the evolution of joint phenotypes in quantitative genetic terms. A joint phenotype for multiple species evolves as the sum of additive genetic variances in each species, weighted by the selection on each species.
    [Show full text]
  • One Equation to Rule Them All
    One Equation To Rule Them All: A philosophical analysis of the Price equation Victor J. Luque ABSTRACT This paper provides a philosophical analysis of the Price equation and its role in evolutionary theory. Traditional models in population genetics postulate simplifying assumptions in order to make the models mathematically tractable. On the contrary, the Price equation implies a very specific way of theorizing, starting with assumptions that we think are true and then deriving from them the mathematical rules of the system. I argue that the Price equation is a generalization-sketch, whose main purpose is to provide a unifying framework for researchers, helping them to develop specific models. The Price equation plays this role because, like other scientific principles, shows features as abstractness, unification and invariance. By underwriting this special role for the Price equation some recent disputes about it and other evolutionary equations could be diverted. This move also links Price’s equation with Newton’s second law of motion, and therefore vindicates the Newtonian analogy. KEYWORDS: Price equation, generalization-sketch, abstractness, unification, Newtonian analogy. 1. INTRODUCTION The Price equation, first presented by George Price at the beginning of the 1970s, is one of the key equations in evolutionary theory. Price believed that he had found an equation so special that it could describe any evolutionary situation and any evolutionary problem –in other words, Price developed an abstract way of theorizing and thinking about evolution. Nevertheless, this equation has been involved in a great dispute the last decade due to its special nature, after a long period of oblivion when it was used by very few researchers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Price Equation and the Mathematics of Selection∗
    GENERAL ARTICLE The Price Equation and the Mathematics of Selection∗ Amitabh Joshi Fifty years ago, a small one and a half page paper without a single reference was published in the leading journal Na- ture. The paper laid out the most general mathematical for- mulation of natural selection that would work for all kinds of selection processes and under any form of inheritance (not just biological evolution and Mendelian genes), although the paper discussed the issue in a genetical framework. Writ- ten by a maverick American expatriate in England, with no prior background of studying evolution or genetics, the paper Amitabh Joshi studies and had initially been turned down by the editor of Nature as too teaches evolutionary biology and population ecology at ffi di cult to understand. Largely ignored by the evolutionary JNCASR, Bengaluru. He also biology community till the 1990s, the Price Equation is now has serious interests in poetry, widely recognized as an extremely useful conceptualization, history and philosophy, permitting the incorporation of non-genetic inheritance into especially the history and philosophy of genetics and evolutionary models, serving to clarify the relationship be- evolution. tween kin-selection and group-selection, unifying varied ap- proaches used in the past to model evolutionary change, and forming the foundation of multi-level selection theory. Background: Charles Darwin, Natural Selection, and Popu- lation Genetics To fully understand the significance of the Price Equation, we need to step back over a century and a half to Charles Darwin and the principle of natural selection. Darwin derived his concept of natural selection by analogy to plant and animal breeding, in which varieties of domesticated organisms with desired charac- teristics could be developed merely by choosing individuals with Keywords certain desired traits to breed from, generation after generation.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1808.05643V1 [Q-Bio.PE] 16 Aug 2018 Subject to Surprisingly Little Conceptual Or Theoretical Challenge to Its Underlying Premises and Methods
    Not even wrong: The spurious link between biodiversity and ecosystem functioning Pradeep Pillaia1 , Tarik C. Gouhier1 1Marine Science Center, Northeastern University, 30 Nahant Rd, Nahant, MA 01908 a To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: [email protected] Abstract Resolving the relationship between biodiversity and ecosystem functioning has been one of the central goals of modern ecology. Early debates about the relationship were finally resolved with the advent of a statistical partitioning scheme that decomposed the biodiversity effect into a \selection" effect and a \complementarity" effect. We prove that both the biodiversity effect and its statistical decomposition into selection and complementarity are fundamentally flawed because these methods use a na¨ıve null expectation based on neutrality, likely leading to an overestimate of the net biodiver- sity effect, and they fail to account for the nonlinear abundance-ecosystem functioning relationships observed in nature. Furthermore, under such nonlinearity no statistical scheme can be devised to partition the biodiversity effects. We also present an alter- native metric providing a more reasonable estimate of biodiversity effect. Our results suggest that all studies conducted since the early 1990s likely overestimated the positive effects of biodiversity on ecosystem functioning. Keywords: biodiversity; ecosystem functioning; complementarity effect; selection effect; Jensen's inequality; Price equation; species coexistence Introduction The notion that increasing biodiversity
    [Show full text]