Perspectivism and the Philosophical Rhetoric of the Dialogue Form

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Perspectivism and the Philosophical Rhetoric of the Dialogue Form MARINA MCCOY | 49 In reading a Platonic dialogue, we know the Perspectivism and old saying: quot lectores, tot Platones. the Philosophical There are probably as many Platos as there are readers of him. Perhaps it will be a surprise, Rhetoric of the then, for a commentator to begin by saying that Dialogue Form I share a basic agreement with Gonzalez’s per- spectivist approach to the Platonic dialogues. This kind of an approach to the dialogues has guided much of my own teaching and writ- ing about them. The dialogues presuppose an objective truth toward which we are meant to strive, and yet acknowledge that we as seek- ers of this truth are always partial in what we Marina McCoy grasp of its nature. I find this perspectivist ap- Boston College proach warranted by the sorts of examples that [email protected] Gonzalez offers on how topics such as the soul or the forms are treated across dialogues. To this, I would add that perspectivism fits well with the way that the dialogues often treat the ABSTRACT human person as “in between”. The Sympo- sium presents a vision of the human being as In this paper, I support the perspectivist read- “in between” poverty and plenty (Symp. 203 ing of the Platonic dialogues. The dialogues b-204 a). In the Apology, Socrates claims a deep assert an objective truth toward which we are commitment to seeking the truth, coupled with meant to strive, and yet acknowledge that we an equally strong belief that his wisdom is a as seekers of this truth are always partial in human wisdom, one that is better than other what we grasp of its nature. They are written claims to wisdom insofar as he knows that he in a way to encourage the development of does not know (Apol. 20 d; 21 d). The Meno philosophical practice in their readers, where and Phaedrus alike claim that we are both be- “philosophical” means not only having an epis- ings of forgetting and of learning, of ascent temic state in between the total possession of and descent (Men. 81 b-e; Phaedr. 246 c-e). The truth and its absence, but also growing in self- Phaedrus describes souls on the philosophi- knowledge as being that kind of a being. I take cal path, the best of all possible paths that can up three particular qualities of the dialogue: be taken, as those who can have only a faint they are multilayered, multivocal, and mimetic. recollection of the forms that they pursue, but Devices such as Platonic irony, multiple char- who nonetheless are in a state of ascent to- acters’ voices, and a reformulated notion of wards those same objects of our deepest desires mimesis that encourages the development of (Phaedr. 247 b-248 d). Perspectivism captures rationality and autonomy are central to Platonic the multiple ways in which Plato describes the rhetoric and philosophy. human soul, as that which is neither divine nor animal, but always en route, in a state of Keywords: Plato, dialogue, rhetoric, mimesis, becoming. Moreover, a perspectivist approach irony, self-knowledge, perspectivism, image. https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_16_4 50 | Perspectivism and the Philosophical Rhetoric of the Dialogue Form to how to read the dialogues in relationship to Socrates, recognizes the partial and perspec- one another also fits well with what I under- tival nature of her own knowledge. stand to be the relationship between language In contrast with many other forms of and Platonic ontology. If the forms of justice, rhetoric and poetry among his contemporar- beauty, and so on are not reducible to verbal ies, Plato’s dialogues engage in a rhetoric of definitions of justice, beauty, and the like, activity rather than passivity.3 It is not a form then all statements that we make about them of philosophy that simply transmits knowledge will be limited. Although I cannot argue this to an otherwise passive audience but rather point here, I would argue that Platonic argu- one that asks its audience to become seekers ment frequently proceeds by way of images, and along with Socrates and other seekers of truth that such imagery is appropriate when there in the dialogues. In the Republic, Socrates says is a gap between the nature of being itself and that education is not a process of pouring true language as a tool for talking about being. If knowledge into an empty soul, or putting sight the forms exceed what we can say about them, into blind eyes, but rather a turning around then various images of the forms both capture of the soul in order to make an ascent (Rep. something of that which they describe and are 518 c). In the Symposium, Socrates says that it limited in their vision.1 would be a wonderful thing if wisdom could In my response today, I will take up the flow between two people the way that water can topic of the rhetoric and poetic form of the flow from one cup to another, through a piece Platonic dialogue as a development of perspec- of yarn, but (alas for poor Agathon) this is not tivism. The dialogues do not simply present the case (Symp. 175 d). Socrates never claims to a view, or even many views, to their readers. teach anyone through the direct transmission Instead, they are written in a way to encourage of knowledge. It would be surprising, then, if the development of philosophical practice in Plato as author of these words understood his their readers. Although others have argued for own practice differently, as a process of writing a pedagogical value of one dialogue for another that he undertook in order simply to transmit (as is the case with Kahn’s proleptic reading),2 I his ideas to us, the readers. Instead, I want to want to argue that the very construction of each argue, that the perspectivism of the dialogues is single dialogue as a dramatic work encourages accompanied by a dialogical, rhetorical practice the development of the notion of philosophy as that actively encourages us as readers to be- an ascent, as erotic, as perspectival, through come philosophical— where “philosophical” is its very dialogical construction. The reader’s understood to be not only having an epistemic philosophical development is not merely ac- state in between the total possession of truth complished through the development of spe- and its absence, but also becoming increasingly cific content that Plato hopes for the reader to self-consciously aware of oneself as being that hold as his own belief by the time that the dia- kind of a being. The forms exceed what can be logue is read. Rather, the dialogue form engages fully grasped through language; beauty itself in a form of poetics that leads its readers on is always more than anything that we can say the perspectival journey. Plato as author asks about the beautiful or about beautiful things.4 his reader to undertake particular practices in To practice philosophy, then, always requires the course of reading or listening to a dialogue that I seek with the virtues of courage and that form her into a lover of wisdom who, like humility: where humility is an awareness of MARINA MCCOY | 51 both what I know and what I do not know, Protagoras, where the question of whether vir- and where courage leads me to continue the tue can be taught is not resolved, we as readers pursuit without fear despite my own limits of still have learned a great deal about what the knowledge. How does the construction of the relevant issues are; for example, we might leave dialogues encourage this to take place? the dialogue with a sense that knowledge is cen- If Socrates is a torpedo fish that numbs tral to the practice of virtue, but that the kind (Men. 80 a-b), or a midwife who tests our ideas of knowledge that is requisite to virtue is not to see if they are only wind eggs (Theaet. 149 taught in the same way that either traditional a-151 d), then the Platonic dialogue can be un- poets or sophists taught their students. In the derstood as a text that invites us into our own Theaetetus, the role of judgment in relation to process of philosophical midwifery, whereby knowledge ought to be clearer than before we the dialogue and reader engage in a mutual read the dialogue. The dialogues problematize process of exploring its central philosophical philosophical problems in a way that empha- questions. The Platonic dialogues are read most sizes the lack of finality and comprehensive- fruitfully when we read them not as texts that ness to the problem at hand, whether in an report a Platonic truth to us, for us to absorb, aporetic or non-aporetic dialogue. There is no accept, or reject, but rather as texts that take finality because the process of inquiry always us through an ongoing dialectical movement continues, both in other Platonic works, and in between making claims and then problematiz- our conversations as communities of readers.6 ing the claims made. Within each dialogue, we I propose that three elements of a dialogue frequently find that Socrates makes a claim ought especially to be attended to as we seek and then shows why the claim that he is made fruitful approaches to interpret them: the dia- is problematic. For example, the Protagoras logues are multilayered, multivocal, and mimetic. features Socrates and Protagoras who begin Let me take up each of these qualities in turn. with certain views as to whether virtue can be On the multi-layered nature of the dialogue: taught, and find at the end of their conversation in reading any Platonic dialogue, there are po- that their positions seem to have been reversed tentially as many as four layers to each dialogue (Prot.
Recommended publications
  • Marathon 2,500 Years Edited by Christopher Carey & Michael Edwards
    MARATHON 2,500 YEARS EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS BULLETIN OF THE INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SUPPLEMENT 124 DIRECTOR & GENERAL EDITOR: JOHN NORTH DIRECTOR OF PUBLICATIONS: RICHARD SIMPSON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS PROCEEDINGS OF THE MARATHON CONFERENCE 2010 EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON 2013 The cover image shows Persian warriors at Ishtar Gate, from before the fourth century BC. Pergamon Museum/Vorderasiatisches Museum, Berlin. Photo Mohammed Shamma (2003). Used under CC‐BY terms. All rights reserved. This PDF edition published in 2019 First published in print in 2013 This book is published under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives (CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0) license. More information regarding CC licenses is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Available to download free at http://www.humanities-digital-library.org ISBN: 978-1-905670-81-9 (2019 PDF edition) DOI: 10.14296/1019.9781905670819 ISBN: 978-1-905670-52-9 (2013 paperback edition) ©2013 Institute of Classical Studies, University of London The right of contributors to be identified as the authors of the work published here has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Designed and typeset at the Institute of Classical Studies TABLE OF CONTENTS Introductory note 1 P. J. Rhodes The battle of Marathon and modern scholarship 3 Christopher Pelling Herodotus’ Marathon 23 Peter Krentz Marathon and the development of the exclusive hoplite phalanx 35 Andrej Petrovic The battle of Marathon in pre-Herodotean sources: on Marathon verse-inscriptions (IG I3 503/504; Seg Lvi 430) 45 V.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche for Physicists
    Nietzsche for physicists Juliano C. S. Neves∗ Universidade Estadual de Campinas (UNICAMP), Instituto de Matemática, Estatística e Computação Científica, CEP. 13083-859, Campinas, SP, Brazil Abstract One of the most important philosophers in history, the German Friedrich Nietzsche, is almost ignored by physicists. This author who declared the death of God in the 19th century was a science enthusiast, especially in the second period of his work. With the aid of the physical concept of force, Nietzsche created his concept of will to power. After thinking about energy conservation, the German philosopher had some inspiration for creating his concept of eternal recurrence. In this article, some influences of physics on Nietzsche are pointed out, and the topicality of his epistemological position—the perspectivism—is discussed. Considering the concept of will to power, I propose that the perspectivism leads to an interpretation where physics and science in general are viewed as a game. Keywords: Perspectivism, Nietzsche, Eternal Recurrence, Physics 1 Introduction: an obscure philosopher? The man who said “God is dead” (GS §108)1 is a popular philosopher well-regarded world- wide. Nietzsche is a strong reference in philosophy, psychology, sociology and the arts. But did Nietzsche have any influence on natural sciences, especially on physics? Among physi- cists and scientists in general, the thinker who created a philosophy that argues against the Platonism is known as an obscure or irrationalist philosopher. However, contrary to common arXiv:1611.08193v3 [physics.hist-ph] 15 May 2018 ideas, although Nietzsche was critical about absolute rationalism, he was not an irrationalist. Nietzsche criticized the hubris of reason (the Socratic rationalism2): the belief that mankind ∗[email protected] 1Nietzsche’s works are indicated by the initials, with the correspondent sections or aphorisms, established by the critical edition of the complete works edited by Colli and Montinari [Nietzsche, 1978].
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Perspectivism
    This impressive collection is essential reading for appreciating the inevi- table contextualities of scientific knowledge. It explores how notions of “perspective” can illuminate the epistemic upshot of the sciences and how they are situated in their history, practices, representations, and sometimes competing aims, provocatively advancing debates about realism, pragma- tism, explanation, and modeling in the process, all through a wealth of cases from physics, biology, neuroscience, and medical science . —Anjan Chakravartty, University of Miami An excellent collection of essays on a topic rapidly establishing itself as an important interpretive programme in philosophy of science. One of the volume’s many merits consists in showing the diversity and versatil- ity of perspectivism while illustrating common features among its differ- ent varieties. The reader is thus provided an enormously rich foundation for evaluating the role of perspectivism in understanding science and its practices . —Margaret Morrison, University of Toronto Perspectivism is a fruitful metaphor for imagining alternatives to tradi- tional realism in philosophy of science. Massimi and McCoy have gath- ered ten essays which show how perspectivism is illuminating in areas such as molecular biology and measurement theory, and also explore the relationships between perspectivism and other recent accounts including pragmatism, structural realism, pluralism, and scientific modelling. There is an excellent balance of established and emerging scholars in the field. This volume is a superb, cutting-edge text to use in an advanced graduate seminar . —Miriam Solomon, Temple University Understanding Perspectivism This edited collection is the first of its kind to explore the view called perspectivism in the philosophy of science. The book brings together an array of essays that reflect on the methodological promises and scientific challenges of perspectivism in a variety of fields such as physics, biology, cognitive neuroscience, and cancer research, just for a few examples.
    [Show full text]
  • Mercenaries, Poleis, and Empires in the Fourth Century Bce
    The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts ALL THE KING’S GREEKS: MERCENARIES, POLEIS, AND EMPIRES IN THE FOURTH CENTURY BCE A Dissertation in History and Classics and Ancient Mediterranean Studies by Jeffrey Rop © 2013 Jeffrey Rop Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2013 ii The dissertation of Jeffrey Rop was reviewed and approved* by the following: Mark Munn Professor of Ancient Greek History and Greek Archaeology, Classics and Ancient Mediterranean Studies Dissertation Advisor Chair of Committee Gary N. Knoppers Edwin Erle Sparks Professor of Classics and Ancient Mediterranean Studies, Religious Studies, and Jewish Studies Garrett G. Fagan Professor of Ancient History and Classics and Ancient Mediterranean Studies Kenneth Hirth Professor of Anthropology Carol Reardon George Winfree Professor of American History David Atwill Associate Professor of History and Asian Studies Graduate Program Director for the Department of History *Signatures are on file in the Graduate School iii ABSTRACT This dissertation examines Greek mercenary service in the Near East from 401- 330 BCE. Traditionally, the employment of Greek soldiers by the Persian Achaemenid Empire and the Kingdom of Egypt during this period has been understood to indicate the military weakness of these polities and the superiority of Greek hoplites over their Near Eastern counterparts. I demonstrate that the purported superiority of Greek heavy infantry has been exaggerated by Greco-Roman authors. Furthermore, close examination of Greek mercenary service reveals that the recruitment of Greek soldiers was not the purpose of Achaemenid foreign policy in Greece and the Aegean, but was instead an indication of the political subordination of prominent Greek citizens and poleis, conducted through the social institution of xenia, to Persian satraps and kings.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Meno: Knowledge Is Justified True Belief
    Plato’s Meno: Knowledge is Justified True Belief: This Socratic dialogue introduces two dominate themes in Western philosophy: 402 BC What counts as virtue and what counts as knowledge. Part 1: 70-86c: Part 2: 86d-end: Can Virtue Be Taught? Knowledge Search for a definition of “arete.” MENO’S CHALLENGE: “Opinion” vs. “Knowledge” WHAT IS “ARETE”? 70-79b STRATEGY: : 80d-e 1. may be useful as knowledge, Socrates asks Meno for a formal definition of If you don’t know what “arete” is Socrates proposes that we first determine if virtue is a but often fails to stay in their “arete” for how can we know if arete can be already, you can’t even look for it, kind of knowledge. If it is, it can be taught. If virtue taught we don’t have a clear idea what it is. because if you don’t know what it place; must be tethered by All the examples of “arete” have something in is already, then even if you look, isn’t knowledge, then it can’t be taught (86d-e) anamnesis: certain common: The “essence” or “form” of “arete.” you will not know when you’ve [recognize that virtue is used interchangeably found it. Argument # 1: Virtue can be taught: (87-89c); knowledge is innate & recollected by the soul through with “the good”]. Argument # 2: Virtue is not knowledge (89c): KNOWLEDGE IS proper inquiry. RECOLLECTION: 70a: Can virtue be taught? 71b; Must know what virtue is before Everyone agrees that there are teachers for certain knowing its qualities. What is virtue? Meno responds: (71e-72a).
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge, Truth and the Life-Affirming Ideal in Nietzsche's Perspectivism
    Knowledge, truth and the life-affirming ideal in Nietzsche’s perspectivism Joakim Olsson Department of Philosophy Level C (third year) 15 ECTS Supervisor: Elinor Hållén Examiner: Pauliina Remes Bachelor Thesis in Theoretical Philosophy Semester: Autumn 2017 Contents INTRODUCTION 1 Notes on bibliography and delimitation of scope 4 Abbreviations 5 CHAPTER I: NIETZSCHE AND TRUTH—A BACKGROUND 6 CHAPTER II: NIETZSCHE’S PERSPECTIVISM—AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL EXTROSPECTIVE READING 14 CHAPTER III: NIETZSCHE’S PERSPECTIVISM—A THERAPEUTIC INTROSPECTIVE READING 29 CHAPTER IV: REFLECTION—A CALL FOR A SYNTHESIS OF PERSPECTIVES 35 CONCLUSION 41 BIBLIOGRAPHY 43 Introduction In this thesis, I am going to explore the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche’s (1844-1900) epistemology through his concept of perspectivism. From being regarded to have had a main influence on the Nazis with his strongly opinionated views on humanity he has since the 1960s generally been considered “a certain sort of philosophical sceptic about truth, knowledge and meaning” (Leiter 2002, 291). When reading quotes like “’nothing is true, everything is permitted’” (Nietzsche 1998, 109) together with his repetitive reference to interpretation and perspective, one could perhaps see why. As ‘The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy’ indeed writes: [Nietzsche] bluntly rejects the idea, dominant in philosophy at least since Plato, that knowledge essentially involves a form of objectivity that penetrates behind all subjective appearances to reveal the way things really are, independently of any point of view whatsoever (Anderson, 2017). This quote is stated specifically about Nietzsche’s perspectivism, which argues that all knowing is perspectival—that just as in visual matters, we all know the world from our very limited personal perspective (Nietzsche 1998, 85).
    [Show full text]
  • Persian-Thessalian Relations in the Late Fifth Century BC
    The Prince and the Pancratiast: Persian-Thessalian Relations in the Late Fifth Century B.C. John O. Hyland EAR THE END of the fifth century B.C. the famous Thes- salian pancratiast Poulydamas of Skotoussa traveled to Nthe Achaemenid court at the invitation of Darius II. Scholars have noted the visit as an instance of cultural inter- action, but Persia’s simultaneous involvement in the Pelopon- nesian War suggests the possibility of diplomatic overtones. A political purpose for Poulydamas’ travel would be especially at- tractive given the subsequent cooperation between Darius’ son, Cyrus the Younger, and a cabal of Thessalian guest-friends. These episodes may be linked as successive steps in the restora- tion of the old xenia between Xerxes and Thessalian leaders, dormant since 479. By examining what Persian and Thessalian elites stood to gain from renewing their old partnership, we can shed new light on an under-appreciated dimension of Graeco- Persian political relations. The pancratiast’s visit: Poulydamas, Darius II, and Cyrus Poulydamas’ victory at the Olympic games of 408 made him a living legend in Greece, a strongman comparable to Herakles (Paus. 6.5.1–9).1 Plato’s Republic testifies to his fame outside of Thessaly in the first half of the fourth century, citing him as the 1 For the date see Luigi Moretti, Olympionikai: i vincitori negli antichi agoni Olympici (Rome 1957), no. 348. For Poulydamas’ emulation of Herakles, and similar associations for Milo and other Olympic victors see David Lunt, “The Heroic Athlete in Ancient Greece,” Journal of Sport History 36 (2009) 380–383.
    [Show full text]
  • Any 37 Anytus of Euonymon, Son of Anthemion I Pl
    Any 37 Anytus of Euonymon, son of Anthemion I Pl. Meno 90a speaker [PA/APF 1324 LGPN2 4 PAA 139460 DPhA Pl. Ap. 18b, 23e, & 227 RE 3 OCD3 PP !Aνυτ%ς 'Aνθεµι+ων%ς schol. present (Eυ' ωνυµευ+ ς)] Xen. Apol. 29–31 ≤443–>396 Xen. Hell. 2.3.42, 44 father of an unnamed son Andoc. 1.150 prosecutor of Socrates Lys. 13.78–9, 22.8 Isocr. 18.23–4 D. S. 13.64–6, 14.37.7 Hell. Oxy. 6.2 Aristoph. Thesm. 809, unnamed Arch. Fishes fr. 31 (K 30) Theo. Strat. fr. 58 (K 57) [Aristot.] Ath. Pol. 27.5, 34.3 Life. Anytus was the son of a self-made man who was highly praised in Plato’s Meno (90a): Anthemion, son of Diphilus, a thete who became a hippeus ([Aristot.] Ath. Pol. 7.4; Poll. 8.131) “through his own wisdom and effort” (Meno 90a). His demotic is virtually certain (Raubitschek 1949). If Anytus was in fact a lover of Alcibiades III (Pl. Ap. schol.), his date of birth should be earlier than 451, and nothing that is known about his career makes that early date implausible. If this datum falls away, however, as suggested in detail in APF, Anytus’ birth would be no later than 443, if he served on the Council in 413/2, and no later than ±440 in any case. Anytus inherited a successful tannery from his father (Xen. Apol. 29; Pl. Ap. schol.), but the comic playwrights reduced his occupation to one rather more common for slaves, “shoemaker” (Theo.; Arch.).
    [Show full text]
  • Klearchos in Xenophon's Anabasis
    Klearchos in Xenophon’s Anabasis Joseph Roisman Having brought the history of Kyros’ expedition to the point where Tissa­ phernes seized the generals of the Greek mercenaries, Xenophon breaks the narrative of the Anabasis to draw the portrait of three of them, namely of Klearchos, Proxenos, and Meno/ The portraits deal, by and large, with the strategoi’s character and ambitions. Thus the sketch of Klearchos the Spartan is dominated by three themes: his being aner philopolemos, polemikos, and archikos (2.6Ἰ-15). Although Xenophon thinks well of Klearchos the war­ rior and his ability to turn his troops into an efficient war machine (2.6. 7-8, 11, 14), the scale is clearly tipped towards criticism when he describes him as almost obsessed with a love of war, enforcing discipline by fear and punish­ ment, and gaining command because of his rank and his followers’ difficult circumstances (2.6.2-6, 9-10, 12-15). The characterisation of Klearchos is brief, occupying about 63 lines in the Teubner edition of Xenophon’s Anaba­ sis? Yet its impact on students of Xenophon who evaluated Klearchos’ role in the expedition seems to have been out of proportion to its size. Two examples may illustrate the phenomenon: a) After their arrival at Tarsos the mercenar­ ies refused to follow Kyros to the Euphrates. Klearchos persuaded them to change their minds by using manipulative tactics which would have made a veteran demagogue green with envy.1 23 However, due to the impact of Klear­ chos’ portrait in 2.6.1-5, it has been concluded that on this occasion Klear- 1 Xenophon, Anabasis 2.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche, Unconscious Processes, and Non-Linear Individuation" (2011)
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2011 Nietzsche, Unconscious Processes, and Non- Linear Individuation Damon Paul McGregor Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation McGregor, Damon Paul, "Nietzsche, Unconscious Processes, and Non-Linear Individuation" (2011). LSU Master's Theses. 265. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/265 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NIETZSCHE, UNCONSCIOUS PROCESSES, AND NON-LINEAR INDIVIDUATION A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy by Damon Paul McGregor B.A. Philosophy, University of Louisiana at Lafayette, 2007 B.S. Psychology, University of Louisiana at Lafayette, 2007 December, 2011 To the love of my life, Rosalind, and To my son, Slade ii “You must live in the present, launch yourself on every wave, find eternity in every moment.” –Thoreau iii Table of Contents Dedication………………………………………………………………….ii Foreword…………………………………………………………………...iii Key Terms………………………………………………………………….v Abstract…………………………………………………………………….vi Introduction…………………………………………………………..….... 1 Chapter 1 Schopenhauer’s The World as Will and Idea…………..…....7 Chapter 2 Nietzsche’s The Birth of Tragedy………….………………... 15 Chapter 3 Unconscious Processes as Will-to-Power Forces...………… 25 Chapter 4 Causality, The Self, and Non-linear Individuation…...…… 35 Conclusion………………………………………………………………… 50 References………………………………………………………………….
    [Show full text]
  • The Perspectival Nature of Knowledge
    Raff 1 The Perspectival Nature of Knowledge Exploring Different Accounts of the Theory of Perspectivism William Raff Philosophy Senior Seminar PHIL399 Professor Macbeth Professor Sommerville April, 2018 Raff 2 Abstract: Perspectivism of knowledge, in conjunction with common epistemic assumptions, entails that perspectives are an inherently distortionary force in the knowledge relation. Often reduced to the thought that “there are no facts, only interpretations,” perspectivism can seem to lead to a skeptical or relativist theory of truth and knowledge. When interpreted as an extension of the Kantian notion of the thing-in-itself and the Correspondence Theory of Truth, it is assumed that a view from nowhere, or a non-perspectival knowledge, would be preferable. This thesis explores the basis of these different assumptions about knowledge, and the aspects of perspectivism that make them untenable. Different versions of perspectivism arises in the works of Arthur Danto, Alexander Nehamas, and Maudemarie Clark, who each argue for a characterization of the theory which in various ways misconstrue the role of the cognitive perspective in knowledge. Perspective always impels access to knowledge, and sometimes impedes it – knowledge originates from an approach to the world which is always taken through a perspective. In some cases, the perspective adopted can confuse our understanding, but that understanding is always made initially possible by the perspective. Rather than making knowledge meaningless through distorting the interpretations made by cognizing subjects, perspectives enable the cognitive relation to occur, and has a structural role in the relation between a cognizing subject and objects of their cognition. Raff 3 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my thesis advisors, Professors Danielle Macbeth and Brooks Sommerville, for helping guide me through the research and writing of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meno by Plato
    MENO By Plato Translated by Lee Perlman The bold numbers and letters are universal ‘stephanus’ page numbers, which provide a common reference between different translations PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE: Meno, Socrates, A Slave of Meno (Boy), Anytus. 70 MENO: Can you tell me1, Socrates, whether aretê is something that can be taught; or if not through teaching, through practice, or if neither by practice nor through learning, does it accrue to humans by nature, or in some other way? SOCRATES: Meno, the Thessalians used to be held in high repute and marveled B at among the Greeks for their horsemanship and their riches, but now, it seems to me, also for wisdom, not least the citizens of Larissa, the city of your companion Aristippus. The cause of this is Gorgias. For he came to the city and made the foremost of the Aleuadae lovers of his wisdom, among them your lover2 Aristippus, as well as the other Thessalians. And he accustomed you to the habit C of answering any question asked of you fearlessly and magnificently, exactly like those who know; just as he himself stands ready for any question a Greek wishes to ask, and never fails to answer. But in this region, dear Meno, the opposite has come to pass. There 1 Exeis moi epein means literally ‘Do you have it to tell me?” There is some reason to think that Plato played with the conventions of the epic tradition, in which the first word set the theme for the entire poem. Here, this would suggest that the question of whether knowledge is a kind of ‘having’ or possession is central to the Meno.
    [Show full text]