Intrinsic Explanation and Field's Dispensabilist Strategy
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2013 Vol. 21, No. 2, 163–183, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2012.727011 Intrinsic Explanation and Field’s Dispensabilist Strategy Russell Marcus Abstract Hartry Field defended the importance of his nominalist reformulation of Newtonian Gravitational Theory, as a response to the indispensability argument, on the basis of a general principle of intrinsic explanation. In this paper, I argue that this principle is not sufficiently defensible, and can not do the work for which Field uses it. I argue first that the model for Field’s reformulation, Hilbert’s axiomatization of Euclidean geometry, can be understood without appealing to the principle. Second, I argue that our desires to unify our theories and explanations undermines Field’s principle. Third, the claim that extrinsic theories seem like magic is, in this case, really just a demand for an account of the applications of mathematics in science. Finally, even if we were to accept the principle, it would not favor the fictionalism that motivates Field’s argument, since the indispensabilist’s mathematical objects are actually intrinsic to scientific theory. Keywords: philosophy of mathematics; indispensability argument; Hartry Field; intrinsic explanation 1. Overview Quine argued that we should believe that mathematical objects exist because of their indispensable uses in scientific theory. Hartry Field rejects Quine’s argument, arguing that we can reformulate science with- out referring to mathematical objects. Field provided a precedental reformulation of Newtonian Gravitational Theory (NGT) which has been refined, improved, and extended in the years since his original monograph. In this paper, I argue that Field’s impressive construction and its extension do not impugn Quine’s argument in the way that Field alleges that they do. I do not defend the indispensability argument. I merely attempt to undermine Field’s influential line of criticism. Field’s reformulation of NGT is simply a formal construction. Field argues for its relevance in a defense of nominalism on the basis of a principle of intrinsic explanation. I argue that this principle is not suffi- ciently motivated or defensible, and that it can not do the work for which Field uses it. I start with the relevant background, in x2, and a Ó 2013 Taylor & Francis INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES discussion of Field’s principle, in x3. In x4–x6, I present and reject Field’s arguments for that principle. In x7, I show that even accepting Field’s principle would not lead to his nominalist, or fictionalist, conclusion. 2. Quine’s Indispensability Argument and the Dispensabilist Response Quine never presented a detailed indispensability argument, though he alluded to one in many places. I interpret Quine’s argument, QI, as fol- lows. QI1. We should believe the single, holistic theory which best accounts for our sense experience. QI2. If we believe a theory, we must believe in its ontological com- mitments. QI3. The ontological commitments of any theory are the objects over which that theory first-order quantifies. QI4. The theory which best accounts for our sense experience first- order quantifies over mathematical objects. QIC. We should believe that mathematical objects exist.1 An instrumentalist who believes that our uses of mathematics in sci- ence do not commit us to the existence of mathematical objects, may deny either QI1 or QI2, or both.2 Regarding QI1, there is some debate over whether we should believe our best theories. Regarding QI2, one might interpret some of a theory’s references fictionally. I return briefly to instrumentalist responses to QI in x7 of this paper. Quine’s procedure for determining the ontological commitments of theories, QI3, is less controversial than QI1–2, and may be taken as defi- nitional. Still, instrumentalists who dismiss QI should be prepared to defend alternative criteria for determining their ontological commit- ments. One alternative to QI3 would be to adopt an eleatic principle on which the ontological commitments of any theory are, approximately, those objects in the causal realm.3 Debate over QI has focused mostly on QI4. To oppose QI4, Field pro- vided two synthetic reformulations of NGT, replacing the standard ana- lytic version of the theory, which relies on real numbers and their relations, with theories based on physical geometry. A second-order reformulation replaced quantification over mathematical objects with quantification over space-time points. A first-order reformulation referred instead to space-time regions. There are technical questions about whether Field’s reformulations are adequate for NGT. Field mostly ceded the second-order reformulation, due to problems involving 164 INTRINSIC EXPLANATION AND FIELD’S DISPENSABILIST STRATEGY incompleteness.4 The first-order version, using Quine’s canonical language, is a more appropriate response to QI anyway. There are also questions about whether analogous strategies are available for other cur- rent and future theories.5 I put these questions aside, for this paper, and suppose that reformulations in the spirit of Field’s construction are avail- able for our best theories. My concern in this paper is whether such reformulations are better theories than standard ones, for the purposes of QI. The superiority of dispensabilist reformulations is important because the indispensability argument relies on the claim, at QI1–2, that we find our ontological com- mitments in our best theory. Field defends his reformulation on the basis of a principle of intrinsic explanation. I argue that this principle is false, and that the standard theory is preferable to its dispensabilist counter- part. Thus, I reject Field’s claim that QI4 is false, not because reference to mathematical objects is ineliminable from science, but because the reformulated theories which eliminate quantification over mathematical objects are not our best theories. The value of dispensabilist reformulations has been questioned before. Pincock (2007) argues that the standard theory is better confirmed. To construct representation theorems which demonstrate that a reformula- tion is adequate, the dispensabilist adopts axioms about the physical world and its properties. For example, to measure mass or temperature, Field assumes the existence of spatio-temporal regions or points, and orderings among them, to do the work that connected sets of real num- bers do in the standard theory.6 But, Pincock argues, those assumptions about the physical world are not as well confirmed as the corresponding mathematical axioms and mappings between physical and mathematical structures. Against Pincock’s claim, even if the dispensabilist’s axioms are less well confirmed than the mathematical axioms they replace, they may derive some measure of confirmation from their adequacy. Furthermore, the dispensabilist reformulation, eschewing mathematical objects, makes fewer commitments. It is not clear how to balance the virtue of having fewer commitments with the benefit of having a greater degree of confir- mation. Burgess and Rosen (1997) argue that a better theory should be pub- lishable in scientific journals, and adopted by working scientists; since dispensabilist reformulations are not preferred by practicing scientists, they are no better. This is a wrong way to measure the value of a theory. The practicing scientist wants a useful theory to produce and replicate empirical results. The scientist is mainly unconcerned with ontological commitments. While scientists do seek parsimony among the concrete elements of their theories, an alternative formulation of a given theory whose only advantage is the removal of abstract objects is unlikely to be 165 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES of interest to the readers of a scientific journal. Field’s defense of his reformulation correctly emphasizes concerns about ontological commit- ments. Field shows that it is reasonable, even preferable, to continue using our standard theories, even if we do not really believe that the mathematical objects to which they refer exist. Dismissing concerns about the ontological commitments of our theories, as Burgess and Rosen do, ignores the questions raised by QI about whether scientific theories must quantify over mathematical objects.7 Much of the debate over whether dispensabilist reformulations are better than their standard counterparts has focused on their attractive- ness. Field uses attractiveness as a criterion for acceptable reformula- tions in his original work.8 But, attractiveness is a vague and malleable criterion. One might find a theory attractive based on its strength, simplicity, or explanatory power. It is unclear how to balance such considerations. ‘Of course, it is a deep and difficult question how the various attributes that contribute towards a theory’s attractiveness ought to be spelled out, and how these attributes are to be independently measured and weighed against each other’ (Melia 2000: p. 472). Mark Colyvan, arguing that the standard theory is more attractive than Field’s reformulation, mentions the unification achieved by the standard theory, and its boldness, simplicity, and predictive powers.9 I believe that Colyvan’s argument can be made more precise. This paper pursues and extends Colyvan’s argument, criticizing Field’s own criterion for attractiveness, his principle of intrinsic explanation. I present a spe- cific explanation of why Field’s reformulation is not a better or more attractive theory than the standard one. 3.