Theory and Reality : Metaphysics As Second Science Angere, Staffan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theory and Reality : Metaphysics As Second Science Angere, Staffan Theory and Reality : Metaphysics as Second Science Angere, Staffan 2010 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Angere, S. (2010). Theory and Reality : Metaphysics as Second Science. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Theory and Reality | Metaphysics As Second Science Staffan Angere Department of Philosophy Lund University ©. 2010 by Staffan Angere ISBN 978-91-628-8207-5 Printed in Lund, Sweden by Media-Tryck in October 2010 For Lucius and Portia, who were lost along the way. Preface This is the day for doubting axioms. With mathematicians, the question is settled; there is no reason to believe that the geometrical axioms are exactly true. Metaphysics is an imitation of geometry, and with the geometrical axioms the metaphysical axioms must go too. |C. S. Peirce, \One, Two, Three: Kantian Categories" This book grew out of my curiosity about what the world is like in its most fundamental aspects. That curiosity got me interested in physics, and later in metaphysics. At first, I was intoxicated by the contempo- rary metaphysics movement and its aims to free metaphysical reasoning from the shackles of epistemology and language. But, gradually, I be- came more and more disillusioned. It seemed to me that standpoints were generally accepted or rejected purely for psychological or social reasons, and the naturalist in me felt that such reasons simply were not relevant to questions of what the world is like. In fact, as I discovered, much of contemporary philosophy is an internal affair: a debate is set up on certain premisses, and these are seldom questioned by the debating parties. As the debate proceeds, it takes on a life of its own, and defines its own norms for evaluating what is a good or a bad argument. Intuitions drive argument, and social groups form intuitions. In the end, the debate can move any distance Preface from the|often quite concrete|questions that motivated it. Perhaps the most well-known philosophical school in which this is said to have occurred was Scholasticism; I suspect that much of what goes on in contemporary analytic and continental philosophy will be described in similar terms in the future. The sciences|both deductive and empirical|are not similarly sus- ceptible. They are generally constrained by fairly stable intersubjective methods of evaluation. These change slower than those of philosophy, so even if much science of the past has been given up, much of it also remains valid. Although purely social factors such as intellectual fash- ion do influence both the sciences and philosophy, the sciences are far less at their mercy. The greater subjectivity of traditional philosophy deprives it of its power to find out what the world is like, and the only way to regain that power, insofar as it is attainable at all, is to limit that subjectivity. I have here tried to sketch an image of what an approach to meta- physics, as far as possible free of these defects, might be like. Ideas are gathered both from the sciences and the arts. On the one hand, this book is intended as a work of scientific naturalism, in that the proper methodology of philosophy is taken to be very similar to that of the sciences. On the other hand, the arts also have a large measure of ob- jectivity by their role as image-providers, detached from questions of truth. An image is, in itself, not anything subjective, even if an inter- pretation of said image may be, and I believe the process of imaging to be crucial both to the sciences and to philosophy. Within philosophy, I have mostly been inspired by the works of the giants of the 20th century: Carnap, Quine, Tarski and Wittgenstein among the dead ones, and Michael Dummett and Bas van Fraassen among those still living. Closer to me, I have received much inspira- tion and support from my supervisor Bengt Hansson, and also from professors Erik J. Olsson and Wlodek Rabinowicz of the Lund philoso- phy department. Furthermore, I would like to thank various attendants at seminars where parts of the book have been discussed, and my co- workers at the department, who were always ready to discuss my ideas, no matter how little sense they made: Robin Stenwall, Martin J¨onsson, Stefan Schubert, Carlo Proietti, and many others. vi An immense thanks goes to Sebastian Enqvist for meticulously read- ing through and commenting on the manuscript, for many enlightening discussions on the nature of philosophy and logic, and for support and friendship. But most of all, I owe infinite and unending gratitude to my wife Saga, and our cats Cassius, Ophelia, Hamlet and Othello, for keeping me sane enough to do philosophy, and for always being there for me. This book could not have been written without you. vii Contents Preface v Introduction xi 1 What Metaphysics Can and Cannot Be 1 . The Last Great Metaphysician . 2 . The Perilous Seas of Language . 9 . What's Wrong with Intuition? . 13 . Naturalistic Metaphysics . 18 . Metaphysics as Model Theory . 25 2 Theories 33 . Logic and Theory . 34 . Truths and Theories as Claims . 42 . Theory Transformations . 48 . Variations on the Theory Theme . 51 .. Formal Theories . 51 .. Many-valued theories . 55 .. Probabilistic theories . 58 . Necessity and Possibility . 63 CONTENTS 3 General Metaphysics 70 . Classical Models . 71 . Abstract Nonsense . 78 . Model Space Mappings . 91 . The Diversity of Model Spaces . 97 .. Theory Space Models . 97 .. Matrix Models . 99 .. Coherence Models . 100 .. Concrete Models . 102 .. Physical Models . 104 . Models and Theories . 106 4 Necessitarian Metaphysics 111 . Necessitation Relations and Possible Worlds . 112 . The Model Space N . 123 . Metaphysical Interpretations . 129 . Probabilistic Necessitation . 138 5 Semantics 147 . Tying Theory to Reality . 148 . Probabilistic and Many-valued Semantics . 155 . Varieties of Semantics . 161 . Necessitarian Semantics . 167 . Truthmaker Theories . 175 . Necessitarian Interpretations . 185 6 The Theory{World Connection 193 . Hertz's Principle . 194 . Necessitarian Semantics are Hertzian . 200 . Algebraic and Probabilistic Theories . 208 . Ontological Commitments . 214 . Commitment in a Necessitarian Semantics . 223 7 Applications 229 . Sentential Logics . 229 . Classical First-order Logic, from Above . 235 . Classical First-order Logic, from Below . 242 ix CONTENTS . Set Theory and Mathematics . 252 . Quantum Mechanics . 259 . Mind and Metaethics . 267 Epilogue: Models and Metaphysics 273 Bibliography 280 Index 293 x Introduction Metaphysics, despite being philosophy's most venerable strain, also re- mains one of its most questioned and criticised. For most part, this criticism is well motivated. Metaphysics was supposed to tell us about the fundamental constitution of reality, but since at least the 17th cen- tury, that has been the work of theoretical physics, and not philosophy. While physics has gone from success to success, metaphysics has seen very little actual progress since Plato: modern metaphysicians still con- cern themselves with problems of universals, instantiation, substance, essences, and the rift between appearance and reality. It is easy to draw the conclusion that metaphysics, as a research programme, has gone into regression, and that the parts of it that were once viable have been taken over by the sciences. Why did this happen? The seeds of the collapse were sown already in the battle between the British empiricists and the continental ratio- nalists during the 17th and 18th centuries. It is safe to say that the progress of science granted victory to the empiricists. Certainly, there was the Kantian programme of trying to show that empirical knowledge was confined to the world of appearances, and that a transcendental metaphysics was necessary to grasp reality as it really is. But the fact remains that the world of things{for{us is what we are immersed in, and it is this world that most directly piques our curiousity. That there may be another world behind the veil of appearance may be an intrigu- ing thought, but perhaps more so for science fiction and theology than Introduction for science and philosophy. Accepting that metaphysics studies the world of things as they are accessible to us should, however, not be confused with the quite different programme of analysing our \common sense" metaphysical concepts, mostly associated with Strawson's descriptive metaphysics (Strawson, 1959). Metaphysics, as it interests us in this book, is a subject pur- portedly dealing with what the world is like, and not primarily about our concepts. If there is a viable notion of descriptive metaphysics, apart from the psychological (and empirical) investigation into how we represent things mentally, we will not have much to say about it here. Our target is the real world, and what we think about it only serves as a stepping-stone, since these thoughts say something about the world only if what they say happens to be true. The best methods for finding out what about this world is true or false are empirical, so it is easy to see why traditional metaphysics in the vein of the presocratics, Plato, Descartes and Leibniz must fail.
Recommended publications
  • Book Reviews 120 This Volume of Thirty-Eight Essays, by An
    120 Book Reviews John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis, eds. A Companion to Pragmatism. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2006. xii + 431 pp. Cloth ISBN 1-4051- 1621-8 This volume of thirty-eight essays, by an impressive list of contributors, is a resource for anyone wishing to learn about pragmatism in general, its history, as well as the particular philosophies of the classical and more recent pragmatists. There are essays in A Companion to Pragmatism that discuss pragmatic philosophers in the context of the history of philosophy. For instance, Douglas Anderson in “Peirce and Cartesian Rationalism” argues that Peirce’s rejection of Cartesianism “was radical but not wholesale” (161). In other words, what Peirce inherits from modern philosophy is as important to our understanding of his philosophy as the ways he breaks away from the tradition. There are several essays in this collection that stress both the break and the continuity with the tradition of all the classical pragmatist figures. Timothy Sprigge in “James, Empiricism, and Absolute Idealism” shows the historical continuity between James and idealism. The historical and philosophical relations between Hegel and the pragmatist are explored in Kenneth Westphal’s essay “Hegel and Realism.” In “Expressivism and Mead’ Social Self” Mitchell Aboulafia argues that the pragmatists cannot be fully appreciated unless they are understood against the backdrop of the enlighment and expressivism. Thomas Alexander argues in “Dewey, Dualism, and Naturalism” that understanding how Dewey addresses the heritage of dualism (as a common western philosophical habit) provides a better insight into his general position. Other essays in A Companion to Pragmatism facilitate understanding of pragmatism by making connections or drawing similarities/differences with other philosophical traditions, some current issue or philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • A Retrospective on Isaac Levi: June 30, 1930 – December 25, 2018
    A retrospective on Isaac Levi: June 30, 1930 – December 25, 2018 Teddy Seidenfeld Philosophy and Statistics Carnegie Mellon University [email protected] Isaac Levi’s philosophy places him squarely within the Rabbi: Birmingham, Alabama; Auburn, New York; and tradition of American Pragmatism: the noble legacy in 1941 the family moved to Sydney, Australia, prior of Peirce, James, and Dewey, evidently influenced by to the Pearl Harbor attack. In 1942, still in Australia, his teachers and colleagues at Columbia University, Levi’s father joined the US Army, becoming the first e.g., E. Nagel and S. Morgenbesser, and fellow overseas Jewish chaplain. Later in 1942, the rest of graduate student at Columbia University, e.g., H. E. the family – Isaac, with his younger brother and sister, Kyburg, Jr. and F. Schick. Important for understanding and mother – left Australia to stay with their maternal Levi’s original perspective on large scale philosophical grandparents in Ontario, Canada. The family reunited, problems is the theme that decision theory is back in the Southern US, when his father, still a embedded in them all. Typical of his work, Levi’s chaplain, returned from overseas in 1944 to be contributions are grounded on significant stationed in Hot Springs, Arkansas. (Isaac’s lifelong distinctions, many of which are cast with the aid of fondness for the music of Hank Williams traces to this sound decision-theory. In this retrospective I review period.). After the war’s end, the family moved to four salient examples of his interests, spanning Levi’s Detroit, Michigan, where Isaac graduated High School work on (1) belief acceptance, (2) belief revision, 3) in 1947.
    [Show full text]
  • For Immediate Release
    Contact: (212) 854-3065 Alyssa Timin, Managing Editor [email protected] FOR IMMEDIATE RELEASE INNAUGURAL ISAAC LEVI PRIZE AWARDED TO ANDREW BOLLHAGEN UC SAN DIEGO GRADUATE STUDENT RECEIVES $10,000 AND PUBLICATION OF PAPER, “HEMPEL’S RAVEN REVISITED” (New York, NY – 12/2/20): The Journal of Philosophy, Inc., today announced the winner of the Isaac Levi Prize, a new annual competition open to current philosophy graduate students and early career researchers who have received a Ph.D. within the past two years. Through a triple- blind review process, the prize committee selected the paper “Hempel’s Raven Revisited” by Andrew Bollhagen, a fourth-year philosophy student at UC San Diego. Bollhagen will receive $10,000, and his paper will be published in one of the issues of The Journal of Philosophy. The Isaac Levi Prize was created in 2019 to honor and continue the intellectual legacy of philosopher Isaac Levi, who served as a longtime editor for The Journal of Philosophy. The annual award will go to an article submitted to the Journal on the areas and themes that interested Levi. Those themes include decision theory, epistemology, formal epistemology, pragmatism (especially as developed by Peirce), philosophy of science, social choice theory, ethics of controversy, and the relevance of philosophy in these areas to public life. The prize competition was endowed by Levi’s surviving family and is administered by the Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The committee to adjudicate the competition for the prize consists of Carol Rovane, Akeel Bilgrami, Philip Kitcher, Teddy Seidenfeld, Jessica Collins, Haim Gaifman, and Achille C.
    [Show full text]
  • Page 447 a CRITICAL EXPOSITION of ISAAC LEVI's EPISTEMOLOGY
    “10tamminga” i i 2005/1/24 page 447 i i Logique & Analyse 183–184 (2003), 447–478 A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF ISAAC LEVI'S EPISTEMOLOGY ALLARD TAMMINGA Abstract The branch of philosophical logic which has become known as “be- lief change” has, in the course of its development, become alienated from its epistemological origins. However, as formal criteria do not suffice to defend a principled choice between competing systems for belief change, we do need to take their epistemological embedding into account. Here, on the basis of a detailed examination of Isaac Levi's epistemology, we argue for a new direction of belief change research and propose to construct systems for belief change that can do without, but do not rule out, selection functions, in order to en- able an empirical assessment of the relative merits of competing belief change systems. 1. Isaac Levi's Epistemology Isaac Levi, professor at the Columbia University of New York since 1970, puts forward his epistemological tenets in a voluminous series of publica- tions, using a rather uncommon terminology based on logic and probability theory. Levi defends a radical new perspective on a number of traditional epistemological issues, while firmly re-establishing the bond between logic and epistemology, which has been increasingly loosening during the past forty years. Furthermore, Levi is the main pioneer and initiator of contem- porary logical-philosophical research into belief change. Levi places him- self explicitly within the tradition of American pragmatism. Accordingly, some of the keynotes of Levi's epistemology can only be understood prop- erly when placed against the background of American pragmatism.
    [Show full text]
  • A Retrospective on Isaac Levi: June 30, 1930 – December 25, 2018
    Proceedings of Machine Learning Research 103:346–353, 2019 ISIPTA 2019 A Retrospective on Isaac Levi: June 30, 1930 – December 25, 2018 Teddy Seidenfeld [email protected] Philosophy and Statistics, Carnegie Mellon University, United States of America Abstract a Rabbi, who trained at the Jewish Theological Seminary Isaac Levi’s philosophy places him squarely within the in New York City. That is where Isaac was born (June tradition of American Pragmatism: the noble legacy 30, 1930). The family moved frequently, as his father was of Peirce, James, and Dewey, evidently influenced a somewhat the itinerant Rabbi: Birmingham, Alabama; by his teachers and colleagues at Columbia Univer- Auburn, New York; and in 1941 the family moved to Syd- sity, amongst whom E. Nagel and S. Morgenbesser, ney, Australia, prior to the Pearl Harbor attack. In 1942, and fellow graduate students at Columbia University, still in Australia, Levi’s father joined the US Army, be- e.g., H. E. Kyburg, Jr. and F. Schick. Important for coming the first overseas Jewish chaplain. Later in 1942, understanding Levi’s original perspective on large the rest of the family – Isaac, with his younger brother scale philosophical problems is the theme that deci- and sister, and mother – left Australia to stay with their sion theory is embedded in them all. Typical of his work, Levi’s contributions are grounded on significant maternal grandparents in Ontario, Canada. The family re- distinctions, many of which are cast with the aid of united, back in the Southern US, when his father, still a sound decision-theory. In this retrospective I review chaplain, returned from overseas in 1944 to be stationed in four salient examples of his interests, spanning Levi’s Hot Springs, Arkansas.
    [Show full text]
  • 6 X 10 Long.P65
    Cambridge University Press 0521845564 - Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi Edited by Erik J. Olsson Frontmatter More information Knowledge and Inquiry Isaac Levi, John Dewey Professor of Philosophy emeritus at Columbia University, has explored the principles of American pragmatism in greater depth and more consistency than others before him. The result is a sophisticated and powerful philosophical system whose key elements stand in stark opposition not only to current mainstream epistemology, but also to the positions of other contemporary authors writing in the same pragmatist tradition. The essays in this timely volume, written by some of philosophy’s finest scholars, contribute substantially to the understanding and appraisal of Levi’s work. Included in this volume are Levi’s extensive and provocative replies to his critics, which offer unique access to his current thinking on a wide range of topics. The introduc- tion provides a concise, systematic presentation of the cornerstone of Levi’s pragmatism. Suitable for students and scholars who are interested in American pragmatism in general and Isaac Levi’s work in particular, this book is an ideal companion to Levi’s own writings. Erik J. Olsson is senior lecturer in the department of philosophy at Lund University, Sweden. He has published extensively on epistemology, philosophy of science, and logic, and he is the author of Against Coherence. © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521845564 - Knowledge and Inquiry: Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi Edited by Erik J. Olsson Frontmatter More information Cambridge Studies in Probability, Induction, and Decision Theory General editor: Brian Skyrms Advisory editors: Ernest W.
    [Show full text]
  • Uva-DARE (Digital Academic Repository)
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Belief Dynamics: (Epistemo)logical Investigations Tamminga, A.M. Publication date 2001 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Tamminga, A. M. (2001). Belief Dynamics: (Epistemo)logical Investigations. ILLC. General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:02 Oct 2021 Chapterr 3 Isaacc Levi's Epistemology: A Critique 3.11 Isaac Levi's Epistemology Isaacc Levi, professor at the Columbia University of New York since 1970, is first andd foremost a philosopher for technicality buffs: using a rather idiosyncratic terminologyy based on logic and probability theory, he puts forward his episte- mologicall tenets in a voluminous series of publications. Levi defends a radical neww perspective on a number of traditional epistemological issues, while firmly re-establishingg the bond between logic and epistemology, which has been increas- inglyy loosening during the past forty years.
    [Show full text]
  • EBUPT180295.Pdf
    P1: KAE 0521845564pre CUNY239/Olsson 0 521 84556 4 October 21, 2005 13:38 Knowledge and Inquiry Isaac Levi, John Dewey Professor of Philosophy emeritus at Columbia University, has explored the principles of American pragmatism in greater depth and more consistency than others before him. The result is a sophisticated and powerful philosophical system whose key elements stand in stark opposition not only to current mainstream epistemology, but also to the positions of other contemporary authors writing in the same pragmatist tradition. The essays in this timely volume, written by some of philosophy’s finest scholars, contribute substantially to the understanding and appraisal of Levi’s work. Included in this volume are Levi’s extensive and provocative replies to his critics, which offer unique access to his current thinking on a wide range of topics. The introduc- tion provides a concise, systematic presentation of the cornerstone of Levi’s pragmatism. Suitable for students and scholars who are interested in American pragmatism in general and Isaac Levi’s work in particular, this book is an ideal companion to Levi’s own writings. Erik J. Olsson is senior lecturer in the department of philosophy at Lund University, Sweden. He has published extensively on epistemology, philosophy of science, and logic, and he is the author of Against Coherence. i P1: KAE 0521845564pre CUNY239/Olsson 0 521 84556 4 October 21, 2005 13:38 Cambridge Studies in Probability, Induction, and Decision Theory General editor: Brian Skyrms Advisory editors: Ernest W. Adams, Ken Binmore, Jeremy Butterfield, Persi Diaconis, William L. Harper, John Harsanyi, James M.
    [Show full text]
  • Writings of Isaac Levi
    WRITINGS OF ISAAC LEVI 1958 Review of Roy Harrod, Foundations of Inductive Logic, Journal of Philosophy, v.55, pp.209-12. 1959 (a) "Putnam's Three Truth Values," Philosophical Studies v.10, 65-9. (b) Translation of R. Carnap "The Old and the New Logic", in Logical Positivism edited by A.J. Ayer, Free Press. 1960 (a) "Must The Scientist Make Value Judgments?" Journal of Philosophy, v.57, 345-57. (b) Translation (with D..B. Terrell and R.M. Chisholm) of A. Meinong, "The Theory of Objects" in R.M. Chisholm (ed.) Realism and the Background of Phenomenology. Free Press. 1961 (a) "Decision Theory and Confirmation," Journal of Philosophy v.58, pp.614-15. (b) Review of Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, Journal of Philosophy v.58, pp.241-8 (c) Review of Danto and Morgenbesser (eds.), Philosophy of Science and E.H. Madden (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Thought, Journal of Philosophy v.58, 387-90. (d) Review of A. Rapaport, Fights, Games and Debates, Harvard Educational Review v.31, 477-9. 1962 "On the Seriousness of Mistakes," Philosophy of Science v.29, pp.47-65. 1963 (a) "Corroboration and Rules of Acceptance", British Journal for the Philosophy of Science v.13, pp.307-13. (b) Review of H. Leblanc, Statistical and Inductive Probabilities, Journal of Philosophy, v.59, pp.21-5. (c) Contribution to Harper's Encyclopedia of Science. 1 1964 (a) "Belief and Action," The Monist v.48, pp.306-16. (b) "Belief and Disposition," American Philosophical Quarterly 1, pp.221-32 (with Sidney Morgenbesser).
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VI-1 | 2014 Isaac Levi, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy VI-1 | 2014 The Reception of Peirce in the World Isaac LEVI, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012 Gabriele Gava Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/521 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.521 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Gabriele Gava, « Isaac LEVI, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], VI-1 | 2014, Online since 08 July 2014, connection on 23 September 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/521 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.521 This text was automatically generated on 23 September 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Isaac Levi, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays 1 Isaac LEVI, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012 Gabriele Gava REFERENCES Isaac Levi, Pragmatism and Inquiry: Selected Essays, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2012. 1 Isaac Levi is a central figure in contemporary pragmatism, who, drawing extensively on the philosophy of classical pragmatists like Charles S. Peirce and John Dewey, has been able to successfully develop, correct, and implement their views, thus presenting an innovative and significant approach to various issues in contemporary philosophy, including problems in logic, epistemology, decision theory, etc. His books (just to mention a few of them) Gambling with Truth (Knopf 1967), The Enterprise of Knowledge (MIT Press 1980), Hard Choices (Cambridge University Press 1986), and The Fixation of Belief and Its Undoing (Cambridge University Press 1991) propose a solid and elaborate framework to address various issues in epistemology from an original pragmatist perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Brunning-Jacqueline-And-Forster
    The Rule of Reason The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914), the founder of Pragmatism, was an Amer- ican philosopher, logician, physicist, and mathematician. Since the publication of his Collected Papers began in 1931, interest in Peirce has grown dramati- cally. His work has found audiences in such disciplines as philosophy, computer science, logic, film studies, semiotics, and literary criticism. While Peirce scholarship has advanced considerably since its earliest days, many controver- sies of interpretation persist, and several of the more obscure aspects of his work remain poorly understood. The Rule of Reason is a collection of original essays examining Peirce's thought by some of the best-known scholars in the field. The contributors inves- tigate outstanding issues and difficulties in his philosophy and situate his views in both their historical and their contemporary contexts. Some of the essays clarify aspects of Peirce's philosophy, some defend its contemporary signifi- cance, and some do both. The essays explore Peirce's work from various per- spectives, considering the philosophical significance of his contributions to logic; the foundations of his philosophical system; his metaphysics and cosmol- ogy; his theories of inquiry and truth; and his theories of mind, agency, and self- hood. JACQUELINE BRUNNING is an associate professor in the Department of Phi- losophy at the University of Toronto. PAUL FORSTER is an assistant professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Ottawa. This page intentionally left blank The Rule of Reason The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce EDITED BY Jacqueline Brunning and Paul Forster UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO PRESS Toronto Buffalo London www.utppublishing.com © University of Toronto Press Incorporated 1997 Toronto Buffalo London Printed in Canada ISBN 0-8020-0829-1 (cloth) ISBN 0-8020-7819-2 (paper) Printed on acid-free paper Toronto Studies in Philosophy Editors: James R.
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce Edition Project | Newsletters Peirce Project Newsletter Volume 2, No
    Peirce Edition Project | Newsletters Peirce Project Newsletter Volume 2, No. 1, Summer1995 Issue Contents No NEH Funds NO NEH FUNDS FOR PEIRCE for Peirce On 1 March the National Endowment for the For the Humanities informed the Peirce Project that NEH Record had decided not to fund the chronological edition for 1995-97. The negative decision was made even though all of the NEH reviewers for our Max Harold proposal recommended that the edition be Fisch: In funded. It was clear from the letter of notification Memoriam and also from the NEH panelists' comments that there were two principal reasons for the decision In the Works not to fund Peirce. Book Notes One major problem is the cost of producing the chronological edition. The Peirce edition costs more than many other critical editions because Research so much scholarly labor has to be expended on Centers and manuscript reorganization and first-time editing. Resources There is simply little or no previous research to fall back on for many of Peirce's manuscript texts Note on "Pest (many of which have to be reclaimed to begin of Religion" with from the disorganized mass of manuscripts that ended up at Harvard in 1915 and that has brought so many scholars to the point of Probing the despair). To make matters worse, Indiana Communal University support for the edition has been much Mind reduced since 1993 and this has created a greater need for external funding. Editor's Note The second major problem is Peirce's persistent image as a brilliant and interesting failure.
    [Show full text]