Bell's Theorem and Experimental Tests

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bell's Theorem and Experimental Tests BACHELORARBEIT Titel der Bachelorarbeit Bell's theorem and experimental tests Verfasser Cheng Xiaxi Matrikelnummer: a0800812 Institut für Experimentalphysik der Universität Wien angestrebter akademischer Grad Bachelor of Science (B. Sc.) Wien, im Juli 2011 Studienkennzahl lt. Studienblatt: 033676 Betreuer: Ao. Univ. -Prof. Dr. Reinhold A. Bertlmann Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Basic concepts of quantum mechanics 5 2.1 The density operator . .7 2.2 The entangled state . .8 3 Part I: Bell's Theorem 9 3.1 Bell's Theorem . .9 3.2 The general argument (1964) . 11 3.3 CHSH { The non-idealized case (1971) . 13 3.4 CH { more experiment related (1974) . 15 3.5 Wigner { a combinatorial analysis . 17 3.6 Relations between Bell's inequality and entanglement witness 18 4 Part II: Experimental Tests 20 4.1 Requirement for general experimental tests . 20 4.2 The \First" Generation . 22 4.3 The \Second" Generation . 24 4.4 The \Third" Generation - G. Weihs, A. Zeilinger 1998 . 27 4.5 Lab report . 29 4.5.1 Experimental requirements . 29 4.5.2 Setup and execution . 29 4.5.3 Results . 33 4.5.4 Discussion . 36 5 Conclusion 37 6 Acknowledgement 38 2 Chapter 1 Introduction We can say that one of the greatest philosophical and physical discussions was caused by a single paper written by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen[1] (EPR) in 19351. In the paper, EPR assume reasonably the non-existence of the action-at-distance and define the criteria for a complete physical theory, which include the concepts of local causality and physical reality. By demon- strating mathematically their ideas within a though experiment, which was modified by Bohm[26] later on, they concluded that the description of quan- tum mechanics may be incomplete. This conclusion is formulated because this real, deterministic property isn't contained in the formalism of quan- tum theory. And that is also the birth of the term of the \spooky action at the distance[1]." The observation on one system immediately influences the observation on the second one. Few months later, Bohr[2] replied to EPR and defended quantum mechanics with his principle of complementarity. He denoted that the realistic view- point is inapplicable under the macroscopic level. In the following decades, in order to fulfill the desire of understanding na- ture, not only was the validation of contextuality in nature questioned, but also the suggestions of extending quantum physics with a model of unknown \hidden" variable theory (HVT) for the completion were proposed. Many great physicists, e.g. Von Neumann, Gleason, Jauch and Piron, made some attempts to deny the theoretical extension. Apparently, all the proofs con- tain some leakages in their axioms or failed at the point of determinism and congruence with quantum mechanics[3]. Finally, both possible explanations were fully eliminated by the two follow- ing \no-go" theorems: the Kochen-Specker theorem and Bell's theorem. The present work covers Bell's theorem, published in 1964[4] by John Bell. He formulates a contradiction between the HVT and quantum mechanical 1Interestingly, the EPR paper became cited with a delay of 30 years, i.e., after Bell published his inequality and nowadays in the age of quantum information, there is an exponential increase of citations. 3 measurement. Besides the brief summaries of a few interesting proofs of Bell's theorem, the most significant historical experimental tests of Bell's theorem, during the last decades, are hereby also described and analysed. 4 Chapter 2 Basic concepts of quantum mechanics In this chapter, a short introduction into quantum mechanics will be ex- plained and all necessary mathematical notations for understanding the present work will also be mentioned. According to the fundamental law of quantum mechanics, a quantum state φ of a given system is described by a complex function, called the wave func- tion, which contains the complete knowledge of the state and allows one to determine the probabilities of obtaining certain measurement results made in the state. Suppose φ(~x;t) is a function of the space ~x and time t, then the probability of finding the system in the coordinate interval [~x;~x + d~x] or shortly d3x at time t is given by jφ(~x;t)j2d3x (2.1) And due to the normalization condition, the total probability is: Z jjφjj2 = jφ(~x;t)j2d3x = 1 = hφjφi (2.2) where jj · jj = ph · j · i and the right side of the equation is expressed by the Dirac notation. To gain a deeper understanding of the quantum states, let us consider the space underlying our physical objects, which is also called the Hilbert space. Definition: A Hilbert space H is a finite- or infinite-dimensional, linear vector space with the scalar product in C (Complex field). The inner product of the elements of the space, hφj i = R φ∗ d3x, with φ, 2 H, satisfies the following properties, where φ∗ is the complex conjugate of φ: hφj i is complexly conjugated: hφj i = h jφi where the term with overline denotes the complex conjugation. 5 hφj i is linear in its second argument. For all complex number a and b: hφja 1 + b 2i = ahφj 1i + bhφj 2i The inner product is positive definite: hφjφi ≥ 0 where the case of equality holds for φ = 0. The norm, a real-value function, is also defined by the inner product: jjφjj = phφjφi Physical states expressed by wave functions obey the superposition princi- ples. If fjφiig are all possible states of H, then any linear combination jφi of them also belongs to H: jφi = c1jφ1i + c2jφ2i + ::: + cN jφN i (2.3) 2 where fcig are complex numbers and i = 1; 2;:::N. jcij gives the proba- PN 2 bility of obtaining φi with i=1 jcij = 1: 2 2 jcij = jhφij ij (2.4) If fjφiig are orthonormal, they are called the orthonormal bases. Therefore a quantum state can be generally written as: N X jφi = cijφii (2.5) i=1 The observables are operators which act on the wave function, if certain physical quantities need to be measured. The measurement results are given by the eigenstates of the corresponding observable with their eigenvalues. Imagine an operator A acting on any arbitrary eigenstate jφii, then: Ajφii = λijφii where λi is the eigenvalue and denotes the measurement probability. The most important analysis of this work is based on the expectation value of an observable. Since a statistical average value for the given observable acted on a large number of the identically prepared systems is required, this mean value is defined by the expectation value: Z N ∗ 3 X y hAiφ = φ Aφd x = hφjAjφi = cncpAn;p (2.6) n;p=0 where An;p = hφnjAjφpi is the matrix element of the observable A. 6 2.1 The density operator Usually, we often deal with states of systems, which are not perfectly de- termined. In order to make the maximal use of this partial information we possess about the state of the system, the density matrix formalism is introduced. The density operator ρ is therefore defined as: ρ = jφihφj (2.7) Analogously, the expectation value is given by: hAiφ = tr(ρ · A) = tr(A · ρ) (2.8) And tr(ρ) = 1 (2.9) For a given pure state jφi whose information is perfectly known, the density operator has to fulfil the following properties: ρ2 = ρ ρy = ρ tr(ρ2) = 1 For the completeness, a mixed state is present when there is a statistical distribution of pure states. Since there is no interference effects between the pure states, a mixed state can therefore only be given by the density operator: X X ρ = pijφiihφij = piρi (2.10) i i P where i pi = 1 and fpig are the probabilities of detecting fjφiihφijg. The following properties will be satisfied: X tr(ρ) = pitr(ρi) i tr(ρ) = 1 hAiφ = tr(ρ · A) ρ2 6= ρ tr(ρ2) ≤ 1 Here the last inequality can be seen as a measure of the mixedness of a given state. 7 2.2 The entangled state Before starting with Bell's theorem, let us first take a brief look at the entangled state. We consider the following quantum state vector: · · −iφ · jΦi = a jxi1 jyi2 + b e jyi1 jxi2 (2.11) which is a general form of an entangled state for two subsystems. Here, jaj2 2 and jbj are the probabilities of the corresponding product states jxi1⊗jyi2 = 2 2 −iφ jxi1 jyi2 and jyi1 ⊗jxi2 = jyi1 jxi2 with jaj +jbj = 1, the term e denotes a phase difference. The peculiar property of this kind of states is that they can't be factorized into a product of two states of individual subsystems. In other words, a state vector jΨi in biparticle system describing, e.g., two subsystems of photons can generally be written in the form: X jΨi = cm;n jmi1 jni2 (2.12) m;n · where cm;n = am bn are the probability coefficients of jmi1 jni2, am is the P m-th probability coefficient of the single photon state jΨ1i = am jmi, the m analogous notation bn for the other single photon. A state which can be written in Eq. (2.12) is called separable. Otherwise, the state is said to be entangled, which means: cm;n 6= am · bn (2.13) In conclusion, an entangled state can only be totally examined as a whole system. Therefore we define an entangled state as such a state with two or more subsystems, separated by a certain distance, that the whole system, but not the individual subsystems, is well defined. The most remarkable entangled states are called Bell states, which have maximal entanglement and are given for photons with horizontal and vertical polarizations by: + 1 Ψ = p (jHi jV i + jV i jHi ) (2.14) 2 1 2 1 2 − 1 Ψ = p (jHi jV i − jV i jHi ) (2.15) 2 1 2 1 2 + 1 Φ = p (jHi jHi + jV i jV i ) (2.16) 2 1 2 1 2 − 1 Φ = p (jHi jHi − jV i jV i ) (2.17) 2 1 2 1 2 8 Chapter 3 Part I: Bell's Theorem 3.1 Bell's Theorem Let us consider the following thought experiment made by Bohm[26] (EPRB).
Recommended publications
  • Bell Inequalities Made Simple(R): Linear Functions, Enhanced Quantum Violations, Post- Selection Loopholes (And How to Avoid Them)
    Bell inequalities made simple(r): Linear functions, enhanced quantum violations, post- selection loopholes (and how to avoid them) Dan Browne: joint work with Matty Hoban University College London Arxiv: Next week (after Matty gets back from his holiday in Bali). In this talk MBQC Bell Inequalities random random setting setting vs • I’ll try to convince you that Bell inequalities and measurement-based quantum computation are related... • ...in ways which are “trivial but interesting”. Talk outline • A (MBQC-inspired) very simple derivation / characterisation of CHSH-type Bell inequalities and loopholes. • Understand post-selection loopholes. • Develop methods of post-selection without loopholes. • Applications: • Bell inequalities for Measurement-based Quantum Computing. • Implications for the range of CHSH quantum correlations. Bell inequalities Bell inequalities • Bell inequalities (BIs) express bounds on the statistics of spatially separated measurements in local hidden variable (LHV) theories. random random setting setting > ct Bell inequalities random A choice of different measurements setting chosen “at random”. A number of different outcomes Bell inequalities • They repeat their experiment many times, and compute statistics. • In a local hidden variable (LHV) universe, their statistics are constrained by Bell inequalities. • In a quantum universe, the BIs can be violated. CHSH inequality In this talk, we will only consider the simplest type of Bell experiment (Clauser-Horne-Shimony-Holt). Each measurement has 2 settings and 2 outcomes. Boxes We will illustrate measurements as “boxes”. s 0, 1 j ∈{ } In the 2 setting, 2 outcome case we can use bit values 0/1 to label settings and outcomes. m 0, 1 j ∈{ } Local realism • Realism: Measurement outcome depends deterministically on setting and hidden variables λ.
    [Show full text]
  • Bell's Inequalities and Their Uses
    The Quantum Theory of Information and Computation http://www.comlab.ox.ac.uk/activities/quantum/course/ Bell’s inequalities and their uses Mark Williamson [email protected] 10.06.10 Aims of lecture • Local hidden variable theories can be experimentally falsified. • Quantum mechanics permits states that cannot be described by local hidden variable theories – Nature is weird. • We can utilize this weirdness to guarantee perfectly secure communication. Overview • Hidden variables – a short history • Bell’s inequalities as a bound on `reasonable’ physical theories • CHSH inequality • Application – quantum cryptography • GHZ paradox Hidden variables – a short history • Story starts with a famous paper by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen in 1935. • They claim quantum mechanics is incomplete as it predicts states that have bizarre properties contrary to any `reasonable’ complete physical theory. • Einstein in particular believed that quantum mechanics was an approximation to a local, deterministic theory. • Analogy: Classical statistical mechanics approximation of deterministic, local classical physics of large numbers of systems. EPRs argument used the peculiar properties of states permitted in quantum mechanics known as entangled states. Schroedinger says of entangled states: E. Schroedinger, Discussion of probability relations between separated systems. P. Camb. Philos. Soc., 31 555 (1935). Entangled states • Observation: QM has states where the spin directions of each particle are always perfectly anti-correlated. Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (1935) EPR use the properties of an entangled state of two particles a and b to engineer a paradox between local, realistic theories and quantum mechanics Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Roughly speaking : If a and b are two space-like separated particles (no causal connection between the particles), measurements on particle a should not affect particle b in a reasonable, complete physical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms 2014, 3, 153-165; Doi:10.3390/Axioms3020153 OPEN ACCESS Axioms ISSN 2075-1680
    Axioms 2014, 3, 153-165; doi:10.3390/axioms3020153 OPEN ACCESS axioms ISSN 2075-1680 www.mdpi.com/journal/axioms/ Article Bell Length as Mutual Information in Quantum Interference Ignazio Licata 1,* and Davide Fiscaletti 2,* 1 Institute for Scientific Methodology (ISEM), Palermo, Italy 2 SpaceLife Institute, San Lorenzo in Campo (PU), Italy * Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mails: [email protected] (I.L.); [email protected] (D.F.). Received: 22 January 2014; in revised form: 28 March 2014 / Accepted: 2 April 2014 / Published: 10 April 2014 Abstract: The necessity of a rigorously operative formulation of quantum mechanics, functional to the exigencies of quantum computing, has raised the interest again in the nature of probability and the inference in quantum mechanics. In this work, we show a relation among the probabilities of a quantum system in terms of information of non-local correlation by means of a new quantity, the Bell length. Keywords: quantum potential; quantum information; quantum geometry; Bell-CHSH inequality PACS: 03.67.-a; 04.60.Pp; 03.67.Ac; 03.65.Ta 1. Introduction For about half a century Bell’s work has clearly introduced the problem of a new type of “non-local realism” as a characteristic trait of quantum mechanics [1,2]. This exigency progressively affected the Copenhagen interpretation, where non–locality appears as an “unexpected host”. Alternative readings, such as Bohm’s one, thus developed at the origin of Bell’s works. In recent years, approaches such as the transactional one [3–5] or the Bayesian one [6,7] founded on a “de-construction” of the wave function, by focusing on quantum probabilities, as they manifest themselves in laboratory.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mechanics for Beginners OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, Spi
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, SPi Quantum Mechanics for Beginners OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, SPi Quantum Mechanics for Beginners with applications to quantum communication and quantum computing M. Suhail Zubairy Texas A&M University 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 10/3/2020, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © M. Suhail Zubairy 2020 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2020 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing
    [Show full text]
  • Nonlocal Single Particle Steering Generated Through Single Particle Entanglement L
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Nonlocal single particle steering generated through single particle entanglement L. M. Arévalo Aguilar In 1927, at the Solvay conference, Einstein posed a thought experiment with the primary intention of showing the incompleteness of quantum mechanics; to prove it, he employed the instantaneous nonlocal efects caused by the collapse of the wavefunction of a single particle—the spooky action at a distance–, when a measurement is done. This historical event preceded the well-know Einstein– Podolsk–Rosen criticism over the incompleteness of quantum mechanics. Here, by using the Stern– Gerlach experiment, we demonstrate how the instantaneous nonlocal feature of the collapse of the wavefunction together with the single-particle entanglement can be used to produce the nonlocal efect of steering, i.e. the single-particle steering. In the steering process Bob gets a quantum state depending on which observable Alice decides to measure. To accomplish this, we fully exploit the spreading (over large distances) of the entangled wavefunction of the single-particle. In particular, we demonstrate that the nonlocality of the single-particle entangled state allows the particle to “know” about the kind of detector Alice is using to steer Bob’s state. Therefore, notwithstanding strong counterarguments, we prove that the single-particle entanglement gives rise to truly nonlocal efects at two faraway places. This opens the possibility of using the single-particle entanglement for implementing truly nonlocal task. Einstein eforts to cope with the challenge of the conceptual understanding of quantum mechanics has been a source of inspiration for its development; in particular, the fact that the quantum description of physical reality is not compatible with causal locality was critically analized by him.
    [Show full text]
  • Simulation of the Bell Inequality Violation Based on Quantum Steering Concept Mohsen Ruzbehani
    www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN Simulation of the Bell inequality violation based on quantum steering concept Mohsen Ruzbehani Violation of Bell’s inequality in experiments shows that predictions of local realistic models disagree with those of quantum mechanics. However, despite the quantum mechanics formalism, there are debates on how does it happen in nature. In this paper by use of a model of polarizers that obeys the Malus’ law and quantum steering concept, i.e. superluminal infuence of the states of entangled pairs to each other, simulation of phenomena is presented. The given model, as it is intended to be, is extremely simple without using mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics. However, the result completely agrees with prediction of quantum mechanics. Although it may seem trivial, this model can be applied to simulate the behavior of other not easy to analytically evaluate efects, such as defciency of detectors and polarizers, diferent value of photons in each run and so on. For example, it is demonstrated, when detector efciency is 83% the S factor of CHSH inequality will be 2, which completely agrees with famous detector efciency limit calculated analytically. Also, it is shown in one-channel polarizers the polarization of absorbed photons, should change to the perpendicular of polarizer angle, at very end, to have perfect violation of the Bell inequality (2 √2 ) otherwise maximum violation will be limited to (1.5 √2). More than a half-century afer celebrated Bell inequality 1, nonlocality is almost totally accepted concept which has been proved by numerous experiments. Although there is no doubt about validity of the mathematical model proposed by Bell to examine the principle of the locality, it is comprehended that Bell’s inequality in its original form is not testable.
    [Show full text]
  • Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox, Bell Inequalities and the Relation to the De Broglie-Bohm Theory
    Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox, Bell Inequalities and the Relation to the de Broglie-Bohm Theory Bachelor Thesis for the degree of Bachelor of Science at the University of Vienna submitted by Partener Michael guided by Ao. Univ. Prof. Dr. Reinhold A. Bertlmann Vienna, Dezember 2011 EPR - Bell Inequalities 2 Contents 1 Introduction3 2 Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox3 2.1 An Example to show Incompleteness.................5 2.2 Contributions from D. Bohm and Y. Aharonov............7 3 Bell's Inequality9 3.1 Experimental Verification....................... 12 4 A new Interpretation 12 4.1 Copenhagen Interpretation....................... 12 4.2 de Broglie-Bohm Theory........................ 15 4.3 Introduction to the de Broglie-Bohm Theory............. 16 4.4 The de Broglie-Bohm Theory and the Uncertainty Relation..... 18 4.5 Reality and Nonlocality in the de Broglie-Bohm Theory....... 20 5 Criticism of the de Broglie-Bohm Theory 21 5.1 Metaphysical Debate.......................... 21 5.1.1 Ockham's Razor......................... 21 5.1.2 Asymmetry in de Broglie-Bohm Theory............ 22 5.2 Theory Immanent Debate....................... 22 5.2.1 The \Surreal Trajectory" Objection.............. 22 6 Conclusion 24 7 Appendix 25 7.1 Appendix A............................... 25 EPR - Bell Inequalities 3 1 Introduction Is quantum mechanics incomplete? Are hidden variables needed? Does spooky interaction exist? Do we need a new interpretation for quantum mechanics? Is there an equivalent interpretation to the common Copenhagen interpretation? In this work, these questions will be raised and discussed. Quantum mechanics is known to be strange and describe phenomena which do not exist in the world of classical mechanics. The first main topic is about entanglement, a correlation between two separated systems which cannot interact with each other.
    [Show full text]
  • Bell Inequalities and Density Matrix for Polarization Entangled Photons Out
    Bell inequalities and density matrix for polarization entangled photons out of a two-photon cascade in a single quantum dot Matthieu Larqué, Isabelle Robert-Philip, Alexios Beveratos To cite this version: Matthieu Larqué, Isabelle Robert-Philip, Alexios Beveratos. Bell inequalities and density matrix for polarization entangled photons out of a two-photon cascade in a single quantum dot. Physical Review A, American Physical Society, 2008, 77, pp.042118. 10.1103/PhysRevA.77.042118. hal-00213464v2 HAL Id: hal-00213464 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00213464v2 Submitted on 8 Apr 2008 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Bell inequalities and density matrix for polarization entangled photons out of a two-photon cascade in a single quantum dot M. Larqu´e, I. Robert-Philip, and A. Beveratos CNRS - Laboratoire de Photonique et Nanostructures, Route de Nozay, F-91460 Marcoussis, FRANCE (Dated: April 9, 2008) We theoretically investigate the joint photodetection probabilities of the biexciton-exciton cascade in single semiconductor quantum dots and analytically derive the density matrix and the Bell’s inequalities of the entangled state. Our model includes different mechanisms that may spoil or even destroy entanglement such as dephasing, energy splitting of the relay excitonic states and incoherent population exchange between these relay levels.
    [Show full text]
  • Frontiers of Quantum and Mesoscopic Thermodynamics 14 - 20 July 2019, Prague, Czech Republic
    Frontiers of Quantum and Mesoscopic Thermodynamics 14 - 20 July 2019, Prague, Czech Republic Under the auspicies of Ing. Miloš Zeman President of the Czech Republic Jaroslav Kubera President of the Senate of the Parliament of the Czech Republic Milan Štˇech Vice-President of the Senate of the Parliament of the Czech Republic Prof. RNDr. Eva Zažímalová, CSc. President of the Czech Academy of Sciences Dominik Cardinal Duka OP Archbishop of Prague Supported by • Committee on Education, Science, Culture, Human Rights and Petitions of the Senate of the Parliament of the Czech Republic • Institute of Physics, the Czech Academy of Sciences • Department of Physics, Texas A&M University, USA • Institute for Theoretical Physics, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands • College of Engineering and Science, University of Detroit Mercy, USA • Quantum Optics Lab at the BRIC, Baylor University, USA • Institut de Physique Théorique, CEA/CNRS Saclay, France Topics • Non-equilibrium quantum phenomena • Foundations of quantum physics • Quantum measurement, entanglement and coherence • Dissipation, dephasing, noise and decoherence • Many body physics, quantum field theory • Quantum statistical physics and thermodynamics • Quantum optics • Quantum simulations • Physics of quantum information and computing • Topological states of quantum matter, quantum phase transitions • Macroscopic quantum behavior • Cold atoms and molecules, Bose-Einstein condensates • Mesoscopic, nano-electromechanical and nano-optical systems • Biological systems, molecular motors and
    [Show full text]
  • Bell's Theorem...What?!
    Bell’s Theorem...What?! Entanglement and Other Puzzles Kyle Knoepfel 27 February 2008 University of Notre Dame Bell’s Theorem – p.1/49 Some Quotes about Quantum Mechanics Erwin Schrödinger: “I do not like it, and I am sorry I ever had anything to do with it.” Max von Laue (regarding de Broglie’s theory of electrons having wave properties): “If that turns out to be true, I’ll quit physics.” Niels Bohr: “Anyone who is not shocked by quantum theory has not understood a single word...” Richard Feynman: “I think it is safe to say that no one understands quantum mechanics.” Carlo Rubbia (when asked why quarks behave the way they do): “Nobody has a ******* idea why. That’s the way it goes. Golden rule number one: never ask those questions.” Bell’s Theorem – p.2/49 Outline Quantum Mechanics (QM) Introduction Different Formalisms,Pictures & Interpretations Wavefunction Evolution Conceptual Struggles with QM Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) Paradox John S. Bell The Inequalities The Experiments The Theorem Should we expect any of this? References Bell’s Theorem – p.3/49 Quantum Mechanics Review Which of the following statements about QM are false? Bell’s Theorem – p.4/49 Quantum Mechanics Review Which of the following statements about QM are false? 1. If Oy = O, then the operator O is self-adjoint. 2. ∆x∆px ≥ ~=2 is always true. 3. The N-body Schrödinger equation is local in physical R3. 4. The Schrödinger equation was discovered before the Klein-Gordon equation. Bell’s Theorem – p.5/49 Quantum Mechanics Review Which of the following statements about QM are false? 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonlocality Claims Are Inconsistent with Hilbert Space Quantum
    Nonlocality Claims are Inconsistent with Hilbert Space Quantum Mechanics Robert B. Griffiths∗ Department of Physics Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 Version of 3 March 2020 Abstract It is shown that when properly analyzed using principles consistent with the use of a Hilbert space to describe microscopic properties, quantum mechanics is a local theory: one system cannot influence another system with which it does not interact. Claims to the contrary based on quantum violations of Bell inequalities are shown to be incorrect. A specific example traces a violation of the CHSH Bell inequality in the case of a spin-3/2 particle to the noncommutation of certain quantum operators in a situation where (non)locality is not an issue. A consistent histories analysis of what quantum measurements measure, in terms of quantum properties, is used to identify the basic problem with derivations of Bell inequalities: the use of classical concepts (hidden variables) rather than a probabilistic structure appropriate to the quantum do- main. A difficulty with the original Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) argument for the incompleteness of quantum mechanics is the use of a counterfactual argument which is not valid if one assumes that Hilbert-space quantum mechanics is complete; locality is not an issue. The quantum correlations that violate Bell inequalities can be understood using local quantum common causes. Wavefunction collapse and Schr¨odinger steering arXiv:1901.07050v3 [quant-ph] 3 Mar 2020 are calculational procedures, not physical processes. A general Principle of Einstein Locality rules out nonlocal influences between noninteracting quantum systems. Some suggestions are made for changes in terminology that could clarify discussions of quan- tum foundations and be less confusing to students.
    [Show full text]
  • Statistics, Causality and Bell's Theorem
    Statistical Science 2014, Vol. 29, No. 4, 512–528 DOI: 10.1214/14-STS490 c Institute of Mathematical Statistics, 2014 Statistics, Causality and Bell’s Theorem Richard D. Gill Abstract. Bell’s [Physics 1 (1964) 195–200] theorem is popularly sup- posed to establish the nonlocality of quantum physics. Violation of Bell’s inequality in experiments such as that of Aspect, Dalibard and Roger [Phys. Rev. Lett. 49 (1982) 1804–1807] provides empirical proof of nonlocality in the real world. This paper reviews recent work on Bell’s theorem, linking it to issues in causality as understood by statis- ticians. The paper starts with a proof of a strong, finite sample, version of Bell’s inequality and thereby also of Bell’s theorem, which states that quantum theory is incompatible with the conjunction of three formerly uncontroversial physical principles, here referred to as locality, realism and freedom. Locality is the principle that the direction of causality matches the direction of time, and that causal influences need time to propagate spatially. Realism and freedom are directly connected to statistical thinking on causality: they relate to counterfactual reasoning, and to randomisation, respectively. Experimental loopholes in state-of-the-art Bell type experiments are related to statistical issues of post-selection in observational studies, and the missing at random assumption. They can be avoided by properly matching the statistical analysis to the ac- tual experimental design, instead of by making untestable assumptions of independence between observed and unobserved variables. Method- ological and statistical issues in the design of quantum Randi challenges (QRC) are discussed.
    [Show full text]