What Does It Mean That PRIMES Is in P? Popularization and Distortion Revisited
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
- 1 - What does It Mean that PRIMES is in P? Popularization and Distortion Revisited Boaz Miller This paper was published with very minor changes in Social Studies of Science 39:2, 2009, pp. 257-288. Abstract In August 2002, three Indian computer scientists published a paper, ‘PRIMES is in P’, online. It presents a ‘deterministic algorithm’ which determines in ‘polynomial time’ if a given number is a prime number. The story was quickly picked up by the general press, and by this means spread through the scientific community of complexity theorists, where it was hailed as a major theoretical breakthrough. This is although scientists regarded the media reports as vulgar popularizations. When the paper was published in a peer-reviewed journal only two years later, the three scientists had already received wide recognition for their accomplishment. Current sociological theory challenges the ability to clearly distinguish on independent epistemic grounds between distorted and non-distorted scientific knowledge. It views the demarcation lines between such forms of presentation as contextual and unstable. In my paper, I challenge this view. By systematically surveying the popular press coverage of the ‘PRIMES is in P’ affair, I argue-- against the prevailing new orthodoxy--that distorted simplifications of scientific knowledge are distinguishable from non-distorted simplifications on independent epistemic grounds. I argue that in the ‘PRIMES is in P’ affair, the three scientists could ride on the wave of the general press-distorted coverage of their algorithm, while counting on their colleagues’ ability to distinguish genuine accounts from distorted ones. Thus, their scientific reputation was unharmed. This suggests that the possibility of the existence of independent epistemic standards must be incorporated into the new SSK model of popularization. Keywords popularization, distortion, science and media, social epistemology, computer science, mathematical proof In August 2002, three Indian computer scientists, Professor Manindra Agrawal and his two students Neeraj Kayala and Nitin Saxena, from the Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur (IIT) published a paper, ‘PRIMES is in P’, online. It presented a ‘deterministic algorithm’ which determines in ‘polynomial time’ if a given number is a prime number (the AKS algorithm). The - 2 - story was quickly picked up by The New York Times and the rest of the general press, and by this means spread through the relevant scientific communities of complexity theorists and number theorists, where it was hailed as a major theoretical breakthrough. By the time the paper was published in a peer-reviewed journal, two years after its initial publication on the Internet, Agrawal and his students had already received wide recognition for their accomplishment. The general media usually show little interest in theoretical developments in computer science or mathematics, important as they may be, but in this case, the general media devoted a surprising amount of attention to the story. However, the media’s interpretation of the meaning and implications of the new algorithm was very different from that of specialists in the relevant fields, who regarded the media’s interpretation as distorted. How come a theoretical development in computer science received this much attention from the general press? In what ways was the interpretation by the press of the AKS algorithm different from that of the scientists? Did the Indian scientists have an interest in this press coverage? Can we determine which one of the interpretations of the AKS algorithm is the ‘correct’ interpretation? Why is it that the three scientists’ choice to publish their result on the Internet and in a popularized manner in the general press rather than a peer-reviewed journal did not damage their scientific reputation among their peers? Current sociological theory challenges the ability to clearly distinguish on independent epistemic grounds between genuine and simplified scientific knowledge, as well as between faithful simplifications and distortions. It views the demarcation lines between such forms of presentation as largely contextual and unstable. In this paper, I challenge the epistemological assumptions that underpin and enable the current model of popularization. I give a systematic survey and analysis of the popular press coverage of the ‘PRIMES is in P’ affair in the English - 3 - language. I argue that when dealing with popularization, it is not necessarily true that distorted accounts of knowledge cannot be distinguished from faithful simplifications on independent and recognizable epistemic grounds. Additionally, the demarcation lines between distorted and non- distorted representations of scientific knowledge are not as open to political manipulation as the new sociological view of popularization suggests. The existence of such independent epistemic grounds will explain, in turn, the ability of Agrawal and his students to simultaneously communicate distorted and non-distorted accounts of their discovery to different audiences, without damaging their scientific reputations. If independent grounds for distinguishing distorted from non-distorted accounts did not exist, it would be very likely that Agrawal and his students’ choice to disseminate their results on the Internet and through the popular media would have damaged their reputations and negatively affected their careers. This is because not only did Agrawal and his students violate the social norms of the scientific community by turning to the popular media and communicating their research results directly to the public, these media reports were inconsistent with the consensual views among specialists. Therefore they stood in contrast to their cognitive interests. As I will show, although scientists first learned about Agrawal and his students’ achievements from the media, he and his team received full recognition of their achievement from their colleagues. I will argue that this is because scientists were able to identify the ‘genuine science’ within the media’s distorted accounts. 1 Generally speaking, my case study supports the view that while various interests of the actors involved affect the different representations of scientific knowledge in different media, distorted simplifications of scientific knowledge are distinguishable from non-distorted simplifications on independent epistemic grounds. Furthermore, because such independent - 4 - epistemic standards exist, scientists are able to communicate different contents to different target audiences in order to promote their interests. My paper links up with other work that tries to show, with various degrees of success, that the metaphysical and epistemological assumptions underpinning SSK theories hinder them from providing adequate social explanations of science even in terms of their own standards. 2 My paper may also be considered as part of what Collins and Evans call a ‘third wave’ science study. I rely on current SSK theory of popularization to explain the events of the ‘PRIMES is in P’ affair (hereinafter ‘PRIMES’). However, similarly to Collins and Evans, who (hesitantly) claim that science is not entirely reducible to politics (2002: 245, 286 fn 27), my paper calls for a reform to the current theory of popularization by acknowledging that scientific knowledge is at least partly constrained by non-political factors, and that this fact should be used as an explanatory resource in social explanations of scientific affairs. This paper consists of five sections. Section 1 presents the current theory about popularization and challenges the view that distorted simplifications cannot be clearly distinguished from non-distorted ones. Section 2 provides scientific background from the theory of computation which is necessary for understanding the meaning and significance of the AKS algorithm in its scientific context. Section 3 systematically surveys the general press coverage of the ‘PRIMES is in P’ paper. In that section, I analyze the explicit as well as the implicit ways in which the general press gave a false impression of the implications of the AKS algorithm to lay readers. Section 4 analyzes the interests that the scientists and the press had in the media coverage of PRIMES. In that section, I identify three interests – visibility, recognition and priority – which the scientists had in the general media coverage of their algorithm. Section 5 - 5 - addresses possible criticisms of my argument and discuss its methodological significance and generalizability to other sciences. 1. Between Popularization, Simplification and Distortion Roughly speaking, two views regarding popularization of scientific knowledge may be identified in the literature, the traditional model and the new model. They differ on three main points. First, the traditional model assumes that audiences are atomistic uninformed assimilators of information, with little or no collective internal structure (Whitley, 1985: 3). Traditionally, ‘science is the active disseminator and the fountain of meaning and agency, the public are merely the passive receivers and repositories’ (Michael, 1996: 109). Second, popularization is traditionally viewed as external to the knowledge production and validation process, which is left to non-scientists. Scientists’ dissemination of scientific knowledge to audiences of non-scientists is viewed as a subsidiary activity that does contribute to a researcher’s reputation, or may even in fact damage it (Whitley, 1985: