The Value of Humanity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Value of Humanity The Value of Humanity Lisa Nandi Theunissen Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2012 © 2012 Lisa Nandi Theunissen All rights reserved ABSTRACT The Value of Humanity Lisa Nandi Theunissen My dissertation is on foundational questions about the value of human beings. This is a Kantian topic but I develop a proposal in a non-Kantian framework. I argue that to be a Kantian in ethics is to be committed to rationalism, but that the foundations of ethics should take account of the nature of human beings and our circumstances in the world. I develop a non-Kantian theory in which the value of human beings is no diVerent, metaphysically speaking, from the value of other valuable things. Human beings have value, just as anything of value has value: because we are capable of being good-for something or someone. Most fundamentally, I argue that we are capable of being good-for ourselves. I propose that human beings have value in virtue of a capacity for having final ends, and that the capacity for having final ends makes us valuable because it makes us capable of living a good life, a life that is valuable because it is good-for the person who leads it. I show how the value of human beings gives everyone reason to treat human beings in certain ways. In particular, I show how everyone has reason not to destroy the capacity of human beings to have final ends, and, more positively, to help others realise their ends. Contents Acknowledgments iv 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Kant on Ends-In-Themselves........................ 3 1.2 A Normative Doctrine........................... 5 1.3 Kant on the Absolute Value of Humanity................. 7 1.4 A Non-Kantian Account of the Value of Human Beings.......... 11 1.5 Open Questions.............................. 14 2 Kant’s Commitment to Metaphysics of Morals 18 2.1 Introduction................................ 18 2.2 Metaphysics of morals........................... 24 2.3 Kant’s Argument for Metaphysics of Morals................ 27 2.4 The Positive Role for Empirical Considerations.............. 29 2.5 Virtue-Ethical Lessons from The Metaphysics of Morals .......... 33 2.6 A Foundational Role for Human Nature?................. 36 2.7 Bindingness Without Metaphysics?..................... 39 2.8 Conclusion................................. 44 3 Responsibility and the Value of Intelligible Beings 46 3.1 Introduction................................ 46 3.1.1 Regarding Others as Intelligible Beings.............. 47 3.1.2 A Dilemma About Responsibility................. 48 3.1.3 Kant’s Dilemma.......................... 49 3.2 Velleman on Valuing Others as Intelligible Beings............. 52 i 3.2.1 The Pre-existing Value of Intelligible Beings........... 52 3.2.2 Right Appreciation: Respect and Love............... 53 3.2.3 Exclusion of the Bad in Sensible Nature.............. 54 3.2.4 Love as an Ideal for Interpersonal Relations............ 57 3.2.5 A Model of Interpersonal Relations................ 58 3.2.6 The First Horn of the Dilemma.................. 60 3.3 Korsgaard on Respecting Others as Agents................. 63 3.3.1 The Second Horn of the Dilemma................ 66 3.4 A Disjunctive Conclusion......................... 72 3.4.1 Concessive Kantianism....................... 72 3.4.2 Rejection of the Distinction Between Intelligibility and Sensibility 74 4 On Regress Arguments for the Value of Valuers 78 4.1 Introduction................................ 78 4.2 The Notion of Value Simpliciter...................... 80 4.3 The Regress Schema: A Source Intuition.................. 87 4.3.1 Stage 1 ............................... 87 4.3.2 Stage 2 ............................... 88 4.3.3 Responses to the argument..................... 88 4.4 The Regress Schema: An End to the Chain of Dependence........ 89 4.4.1 Stage 1 ............................... 90 4.4.2 Stage 2 ............................... 90 4.4.3 Two notes about Stage 1 ...................... 91 4.5 The Alternatives.............................. 94 4.6 Being valuable for Ourselves........................ 100 ii 4.7 Conclusion................................. 101 5 On the Value of Human Beings 102 5.1 Introduction................................ 102 5.2 The Basis of Human Value......................... 106 5.3 The Explanation of Human Value..................... 113 5.3.1 The value of human beings as bearers of final ends........ 116 5.4 The Response to Human Value....................... 121 5.5 The Responses We Should Have...................... 125 5.6 Conclusion................................. 128 References 130 iii Acknowledgments Many people have been involved in shaping the direction of my project. I acknowledge various people in footnotes in various chapters, but I would like to acknowledge several people more fully here. I am grateful to Jens Timmermann on the Kant side of things. Jens invited me to participate in a conference on Kant and the dignity of humanity at the University of St Andrews in May 2011, and it was the occasion of several important conversations about Kant on value. I am also grateful to Pat Kitcher for providing helpful feedback on the Kant side of things. I was very grateful to Pat for meeting me on the eve of 2012—while everybody else was beginning their New Year celebrations—before I was to leave to give a talk on Kant on metaphysics of morals. I was fortunate to be able to attend David Velleman’s undergraduate lectures on Kant’s ethics, and to learn first hand from his distinctive take on Kant. As I remember, there were obstacles to entering the building at New York University where David was lecturing, and he was kind enough to meet me in front of the building in the mornings, so I could gain entry. Our brief exchanges through the corridors and up the elevator were the start of many subsequent conversations. David has patiently made his way through each of the chapters of my dissertation, and I am very grateful for his feedback on all of them. Joseph Raz’s influence on the direction of my thinking will be obvious. Much of my dissertation engages in a detailed way with Joseph’s writing. Our working relationship has been (relative to my life as a philosopher) rather long. I was a nervous student in two of his seminars at the Law School at Columbia, and a nervous student in several Oxford-style meetings about this or that paper, where I had to defend something I had provisionally put together. Since then Joseph has become a mentor and friend. His guidance has, and will iv continue to have, a lasting impact on my life. Philosophy would not be what it is for me without him. It is not easy to put my gratitude to Katja Vogt into words, or to trace all aspects of her guidance on my work. This project grew out of a seminar Katja gave on Kant and his critics in the Spring of 2008. That seminar profoundly shaped my thinking about ethics, and about philosophy. It was also in that seminar that I began to learn how to read diYcult texts in the history of the tradition. I have discussed every aspect of my project with Katja over many years. It was Katja who first challenged me to think about whether the notion of absolute value is a notion we fully understand, and she who brought me to think about the ancient view, in a Stoic formulation, that the good is benefit. But I have learnt from Katja in more indirect ways, too. I have attended nearly all her seminars at Columbia, and been a TA for several of her undergraduate courses. Without Katja, if I can put it this way, I believe I would be somebody else. A person whose influence will be less obvious on the page is Bradley Weslake, but his influence has been profound. I met Brad when I was doing my Honours in philosophy at the University of Sydney in 2003. He shook up everything I thought philosophy was, often to my irritation. Our partnership over the eight years that followed meant that I engaged philosophically every day with someone who had some years experience over me, and a stronger hand. He has been an editor, an interlocutor, a friend, and a partner. v 1 1 Introduction My dissertation begins with the question of why human beings are to be viewed, treated, and generally related to in very special ways. It asks: what kind of value grounds this distinctive status? Accordingly, the starting-point of my project is the central ethical question of what we owe to others. I am concerned with our ethical relations with human beings, whose value I take to be distinctive, while allowing that there could be an analogous (if less ambitious) picture about what we owe to non-human animals. From what we owe to human beings it is a short step to the value of human beings. We take that step when we ask what it is about human beings that makes us subjects of ethical concern. That we ‘have an elbow’, or ‘a vestigial appendage’, that we ‘walk upright’, are so many joking candidates.1 But they make a serious point. If human beings are such as to merit being treated in certain ways, it is because something about us is valuable. The question of my dissertation is: what makes human beings valuable, and accordingly, such as to be treated in certain ways and not in others? Much of the literature on the value of human beings begins with Kant. Recent emphasis on the so-called ‘Formula of Humanity’ version of the Categorical Imperative has made Kant the central interlocutor in accounts of human value generally. Now there are various ways of appealing to Kant on this topic, and of working out whether to construct a positive account of the value of human beings in a Kantian framework.
Recommended publications
  • Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 4-16-2012 Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Krista, Hyde Dawn, "Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife" (2012). Theses. 261. http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/261 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Krista Hyde M.L.A., Washington University in St. Louis, 2010 B.A., Philosophy, Southeast Missouri State University – Cape Girardeau, 2003 A Thesis Submitted to The Graduate School at the University of Missouri – St. Louis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy April 2012 Advisory Committee Gualtiero Piccinini, Ph.D. Chair Jon McGinnis, Ph.D. John Brunero, Ph.D. Copyright, Krista Hyde, 2012 Abstract Thomas Aquinas nearly succeeds in addressing the persistent problem of the mind-body relationship by redefining the human being as a body-soul (matter-form) composite. This redefinition makes the interaction problem of substance dualism inapplicable, because there is no soul “in” a body. However, he works around the mind- body problem only by sacrificing an immaterial afterlife, as well as the identity and separability of the soul after death. Additionally, Thomistic psychology has difficulty accounting for the transmission of universals, nor does it seem able to overcome the arguments for causal closure.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2014 Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Bradley Taylor University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Taylor, Bradley, "Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy" (2014). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1468. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Abstract ABSTRACT HUMAN BEINGS AND THE MORAL LAW: MORAL PRECARIOUSNESS IN KANT'S ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY Bradley M. Taylor Dr. Paul Guyer This dissertation is an examination of human moral precariousness in Kant's ethics. Human beings are in a state of moral precariousness insofar as they are ever-capable of transgressing the moral law and are often uncertain of the moral worth of their actions. Put another way, in this dissertation I argue that the basic relationship between human beings and the moral law, in Kant's moral philosophy, is, most fundamentally, one of tenuousness and vacillation. This relation is the fundamental characteristic of the human moral condition because such a relation is built into Kant's account of human moral agency. We have a tenuous relation to the moral law because we always have at least the possibility of conflict between our desire for happiness (i.e. the satisfaction of our inclinations) and the requirements of the moral law.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Phronãªsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, And
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 2013 Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Citation Salkever, Stephen, "Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice" (2013). Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship. Paper 25. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 For more information, please contact [email protected]. DRAFT—NOT FOR QUOTATION OR CITATION. Aristotelian Phronêsis , the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College August, 2013 (A version of this paper was presented at a conference on Practical Wisdom and Globalizing Practice held in November 2012 at Sun Yat-sen University, Guangzhou, China. For questions and comments I thank my fellow conferees and especially the conference organizer, Prof. Xu Changfu of the SYSU Philosophy Department.) In this paper, I will outline some fundamental differences between the evaluative and explanatory language of Aristotelian practical reason based on his empirical psychological
    [Show full text]
  • Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity Author(S): Japa Pallikkathayil Source: Ethics, Vol
    Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity Author(s): Japa Pallikkathayil Source: Ethics, Vol. 121, No. 1 (October 2010), pp. 116-147 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/656041 . Accessed: 13/01/2011 10:19 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity* Japa Pallikkathayil Kant’s Formula of Humanity famously forbids treating others merely as a means.
    [Show full text]
  • XUNWU CHEN/ Global Justice and Duty to Humanity
    GLOBAL JUSTICE AND DUTY TO HUMANITY —A PHENOMENOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE Xunwu Chen Abstract: This essay is devoted to exploring global justice as duty to humanity. The essay first explores humanity as the universal substance of all humankind, indicating that if a person loses a quality, s/he is not alienated or less than himself/herself; but if a person loses his/her humanity, s/he is alienated and absurd. Second, the essay demonstrates that the idea of humanity as the universal substance of all humankind is necessary to make senses those operating norms and principles of global justice in our time, including human rights, crimes against humanity and toleration. Third, essay indicates that global justice is the way of human living because it is consistent with humanity as the universal substance of all humankind. Therefore, the essay concludes that global justice is giving due to humanity as a substance. We can hardly talk about global justice today without mentioning the concepts of the law of humanity, human rights, crimes against humanity, and global cultural toleration. What are conspicuous also follow. First, we search for global justice of, for, and by all humankind in the globe, not justice for all beings—humans and non-humans included. We aim at global principles of justice that normalize all humankind on the earth, not principles of justice that regulate all beings, humans and non-humans alike. Second, if there should be global justice of, for, and by all humankind on the earth, all humankind must share some commonalities. Third, the global human community formally declares the norms of human rights, crimes against humanity, and cultural toleration as the norms of global justice recognized in the UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights in 1948 and the Rome Statute of International Criminal Courts in 2002.
    [Show full text]
  • Inventing 'Humanity': Early- Modern Perspectives
    [Intellectual History Archive 5, 2018] Kontler, Inventing ‘humanity’ INVENTING ‘HUMANITY’: EARLY- MODERN PERSPECTIVES László Kontler1 Central European University I. Introduction This essay addresses a crucial chapter in the development of the modern concept of humanity (mankind , humanité, Menschheit) in European culture. 2 It is not an empirical study based on primary research, rather an attempt to sketch an analytical framework for approaching and understanding a broad array of specific historical topics and phenomena within the parameters of an encompassing theme. The methodological assumption at its heart is trivial: our concept of ‘humanity’ is not an intrinsic one, but a contextually defined cultural product shaped by processes of philosophical, historical, social-anthropological and political self-reflection, and of encounter with ‘others’ in modern times, which all raised important and disturbing questions about the differentiae specifica of the human kind. In tackling some of these questions and significant answers to them during the sixteenth to the nineteenth centuries, I focus on early-modern versions of three important intellectual frameworks that determined the consideration of the diversity versus unity, and diversity within unity, of mankind. These are, first, the temporalization of human difference: the notion that such difference is largely a matter of patterns in the development of human faculties and relations both among men and between them and their environment across (virtual) time. Second, the historicization of nature: the study of nature on the basis of the collection and ordering of data about phenomena as they actually exist in space as well as in time. Third, the naturalization of man: the study of humans without the ascription of a special status to them, with the approach of the naturalists, as coequal from the methodological point of view with any other product of the Creation.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Humanity As a Justification for Human Rights Claims Simon Hope
    Common humanity as a justification for human rights claims Simon Hope I Anyone familiar with the modern language of human rights will have heard the phrase human rights are held in virtue of our common humanity. In this chapter, I want to examine this phrase further; or rather, one sense thereof, for the claim under consideration is ambiguous – in virtue of the “in virtue of” clause – and this ambiguity must be cleared up. The claim might be deployed in a descriptive sense: human rights track certain features of our common humanity, but are justified on entirely different grounds (by, say, appeal to what would be chosen under certain con- straints in an idealized thought experiment.)1 However, the claim that human rights are held in virtue of our common humanity has appealed to many defenders of human rights as a justificatory claim: we can iden- tify features of our common humanity that count as reasons for some conception of human rights. It is the justificatory claim that I consider here. More precisely, my target is the following thought, basic to many philosophical conceptions of human rights: that, by appealing to the moral significance of features of human nature that all of us – of course – share, human rights can be justified by a conception of the human good that is accessible to all. My complaint will be that these bold invo- cations of common humanity idealize away the depth and breadth of moral diversity, and so cannot give a satisfactory account of the intelli- gibility of moral reasons in the face of this diversity.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Modern Asia Can We Speak of an ‘Early Modern’ World?
    > Comparative Intellectual Histories of Early Modern Asia Can we speak of an ‘early modern’ world? To speak of an ‘early modern’ world raises three awkward problems: the problem of early modernity, the problem of comparison and the problem of globalisation. In what follows, a discussion of these problems will be combined with a case study of the rise of humanism. Peter Burke (rationality, individualism, capitalism, distance’, it is probably best to describe ered at the end of the 15th century). Fol- The ethical wing has been discussed by and so on). the early modern period as at best a lowing the shock of the French invasion Theodore de Bary and others who note The Concept A major problem is the western ori- time of ‘proto-globalisation’, despite the of Italy in 1494, some leading human- the concern of Confucius (Kongzi) and The concept ‘early modern’ was origi- gin of the conceptual apparatus with increasing importance of connections ists, notably Machiavelli, shifted from a his followers and of ‘neo-confucians’ nally coined in the 1940s to refer to a which we are working. As attempts to between the continents, of economic, concern with ethics to a concern with like Zhu Xi with the ideal man, ‘princely period in European history from about study ‘feudalism’ on a world scale have political and intellectual encounters, politics. man’ or ‘noble person’ (chunzi) and also 1500 to 1750 or 1789. It became widely shown, it is very difficult to avoid circu- not only between the ‘West’ and the On the other side, we find the philolo- with the cultivation of the self (xiushen).
    [Show full text]
  • Bhagat Puran Singh a SERVA N T of the PEOPLE
    Bhagat Puran Singh A SERVA N T OF THE PEOPLE As Assessment by — S. Bhagat Singh (Retd. Judge) — Diwan Anand Kumar M. A. —S. Narain Singh M. A. —V. N. Narayanan — P. P. S. Gill —S Khushwant Singh —Bibi Amrit Kaur —I. J. Singh —Usha Pratap Singh Whatever you have received more than others in health, in talents, in ability, in success, in a pleasant childhood, in harmonious conditions of home life, all this you must not take as a matter of course. In gratitude for your fortune, you must render in return some sacrifice of your own life for other lives. —Albert Schweitzer. Publisher Dr. INDERJIT KAUR President ALL INDIA PINGALWARA SOCIET¥(Regd.) ASR. ■ ? a ™ 1 ^■^niMiailih.nra FOREWORD This booklet contains a number of articles, relating to Bhagat Puran Singh Ji which were written during his life time by eminent intellectuals and writers like Diwan Anand Kumar, Ex-Vice Chancellor, Punjab University; Sh. V. N. Narayanan, Editor-in-chief, Daily Tribune; S. Khushwant Singh and several others. The service and dedication of Bhagat Puran Singh to the suffering humanity influenced these authors so deeply that their pens were impelled to laud the , Bhagatji for his great mission he embarked upon. This great Samaritan is no more amongst us today, yet Pingalwara Ashram—a godly aegis for hundreds of destitutes and incurably sick people - is carrying on the ideals of Bhagatji under the super­ vision of his successor and present President, Dr. Inderjit Kaur with the same fervour and enthu­ siasm as was seen formerly. She is assisted and co­ operated in this great task by her colleagues who are equally devoted to this momentous cause.
    [Show full text]
  • A Spiritual W Ay of Life
    A Spiritual W ay of Life Bibi Dr. Inderjit Kaur Publisher : Dr. Inderjit Kaur, President All India Pingalwara, Charitable Society (Regd.) Amritsar (1) A Spiritual W ay of Life by Bibi Dr. Inderjit Kaur August : 2010 Publisher : Dr. Inderjit Kaur, President All India Pingalwara, Charitable Society (Regd.) Amritsar Printer Printwell 146, Industrial, Focal Point, Amritsar (2) Preface When a selfless person like Dr. Inderjeet Kaur puts down her thoughts on significant humanitarian topics, one sits up to take notice. Having worked with leprosy patients for 30 years only with Gurbani Guidance and God's grace, I can easily feel how as a successor of Bhagat Puran Singh, she feels the interminable wish to remain engrossed in the service of the down-trodden. Also her Gurbani-oriented exposition on death is heartening. Let me first dilate on the capacity of a selfless worker in terms of the message of Guru Granth Sahib. The worker is not, in my view, only a social worker but is a servant of Guru Nanak having no hiatus between what he says and what he does. Then, as I said in a London magazine some years ago, a Sikh is an Ambassador of love to humanity. Add to this the insatiable hunger for self-annihilation. Entrenched in the service and rememberance of the Lord and His creation, he always symbolizes the qualities of the Lord himself. My impression is that Dr. Inderjeet Kaur has beautifully encompassed the attributes of a selfless Servant of Humanity in her life and thoughts imbibed from the work and teachings of 'Bhagat Puran Singh'.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Nature According to Saint Thomas Aquinas
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1942 Human Nature According to Saint Thomas Aquinas Virginia Moore Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Moore, Virginia, "Human Nature According to Saint Thomas Aquinas" (1942). Master's Theses. 665. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/665 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1942 Virginia Moore HUMAN NATURE ACCORDIID TO SAINT THOMAS AQUINAS BY v:riG INIA MOORE A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFIT.I:MFm OF THE REQ.UIRJiJmN!'S FOR THE DIDREE OF MASI'ER OF .ARTS IN LOYOLA UNIVERSITY AIDUST 1942 TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page INTRODUCTION . iii I. r!ATERI.AL BEIIDS • 1 II. SPIRITUAL SUBSTANCES 25 III. THE NATURE OF MAN • . 42 IV. CONCLUSION . 81 v. REFERENCES . 84 VI. BIBLIOGRAPHY . 85 INTRODUCTION In the teachings of St. Thomas, philosophy is not a salve to theology. He demonstrates by the principles of reason, many propositions forming a doctrine separate from theology, strictly speaking. He teaches a philosophy distinct from theology; the former, solving problems by the natural resources of the human mind; the latter, seeking its proofs in divine revelation. Both can happen to meet on the ground of the same truths, but each conserves its physiognomy, its means of research, and of argumentation.
    [Show full text]
  • Stability of Moral Traits (Justice and Humanity) in Emerging Adults: a Longitudinal Analysis
    Stability of Moral Traits (Justice and Humanity) in Samantha Jacobson, Julia DeVere, Maddie Grigg, Mikayla Emerging Adults: A Longitudinal Analysis Logue, Lazarus Scarbrough, Mícheál D. Roe Presented at the Annual SPFC Research Conference 2019 Seattle Pacific University Introduction Materials • Emerging adulthood is a developmental time period characterized Demographic questionnaire Justice at Time 1 was not a significant predictor of Humanity at Time 2. In by identity formation, focus on the self, and wide-ranging opportunities VIA Survey of Character Strengths (Peterson & Seligman, 2004) contrast, Humanity at Time 1 was a significant predictor of Justice at Time 2; for exploration (Arnett, 2007). It is considered a particularly important • Six Virtues: Wisdom, Courage, Humanity, Justice, Temperance, and however, this relationship was in the negative direction (See Table 3) period for seeking life roles that provide a sense of purpose or Transcendence meaningfulness. It is also considered a critical formative period for moral • 24 Strengths (e.g., Spirituality, Humor, Love of Learning) maturity in adulthood, and for personality changes that relate closely to Table 3 character development (Noftle, 2015). Calling and Vocation Questionnaire (CVQ; DiK, Eldridge, Steger, & Duffy, 2012) Time 1 Predictors of Justice at Time 2 • Character traits are stable and universal personality characteristics that • Scales: Presence, Search influence thinking, feeling, willing, and action (Niemiec, 2013). Virtues • Subscales: Transcendent Summons, Purposeful Work, Prosocial Orientation Variable β t p value with their associated strengths (e.g., wisdom with creativity and Justice Time 1 .99 5.31 .000 curiosity) are considered positive character traits (Peterson & Seligman, Procedures 2004). Informed consent materials were explained and signatures collected.
    [Show full text]