1 Raaflaub, Needle's Eye HO 15 Ancient Greece

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Raaflaub, Needle's Eye HO 15 Ancient Greece Ancient Greece: The Historical Needle’s Eye of Modern Politics and Political Thought Kurt A. Raaflaub Texts and Bibliographies 1. On the origins of Greek culture: Meier, Christian, A Culture of Freedom: Ancient Greece and the Origins of Europe (Oxford 2011). 2. On archaic Greek history: Anthony Snodgrass, Archaic Greece: The Age of Experiment (Berkeley 1980); Oswyn Murray, Early Greece (2nd ed. Cambridge MA 1993); Robin Osborne, Greece in the Making, 1200-479 B.C. (London 1996); Jonathan Hall, A History of the Archaic nd Greek World, ca. 1200-479 BCE (2 ed. Malden MA and Oxford 2014); K. A. Raaflaub and Hans van Wees (eds.), A Companion to Archaic Greece (Malden MA and Oxford 2009). 3. Ancient and modern democracy: Dunn, John (ed.), Democracy: The Unfinished Journey, 508 BC to AD 1993 (Oxford and New York 1992); Wood, Ellen M., “Democracy: An Idea of Ambigous Ancestry.” In J. Peter Euben, John R. Wallach, and Josiah Ober (eds.), Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy (Ithaca NY 1994) 59-80; Ober, Josiah, and Charles Hedrick (eds.), Dēmokratia: A Conversation on Democracies, Ancient and Modern (Princeton 1996); Barry S. Strauss, “Geneaology, Ideology, and Society in Democratic Athens,” in Ian Morris and Kurt A. Raaflaub (eds.), Democracy 2500? Questions and Challenges (Dubuque IA, 1998) 141-54. 4. On criticism of democracy from antiquity to early America: Roberts, Jennifer T., Athens on Trial: The Anti-Democratic Tradition in Western Thought (Princeton 1994); Ober, Josiah, Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule (Princeton 1998). 5. On the emergency of democracy and dēmokratia, and the working of democracy: Hansen, Mogens H., The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes, new, augmented ed. (Norman OK, 1999); Raaflaub, Kurt A., Josiah Ober, and Robert W. Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (Berkeley 2007). On constitutional terminology: Meier, Christian, The Greek Invention of Politics (Cambridge MA 1990) chapter 7. On political values: Raaflaub, Kurt, The Discovery of Freedom in Ancient Greece (Chicago 2004); Raaflaub, “Equalities and Inequalities in Athenian Democracy,” in Ober and Hedrick, Dēmokratia (section 3 above) 139-74. See also other chapters in the latter volume. 6. On reflections about government and 5th century debates about democracy: Kurt Raaflaub, “Archaic and Classical Greek Reflections on Politics and Government,” in Hans Beck (ed.), A Companion to Ancient Greek Government (Malden MA and Oxford 2013) 73-92; Raaflaub, “Contemporary Perceptions of Democracy in Fifth-Century Athens,” Classica et Mediaevalia 40: 33-70. 7. On cultural influences of the ancient Near East on early Greek culture: West, M. L., Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient (Oxford 1971); West, The East Face of Helicon: West Asiatic 1 Raaflaub, Needle’s Eye HO 15 Elements in Greek Poetry and Myth (Oxford 1997); Burkert, Walter, The Orientalizing Revolution: Near Eastern Influence on Greek Culture in the Early Archaic Age (Cambridge MA 1992); Burkert, Babylon — Memphis — Persepolis: Eastern Contexts of Greek Culture (Cambridge MA 2004). 8. On Near Eastern “ancestors” of Greek democracy: Jacobsen, Thorkild, Toward the Image of Tammuz and Other Essays on Mesopotamian History and Culture (Cambridge 1970: containing essays on “primitive democracy”; for discussion, see Robinson, E. W., The First Democracies: Early Popular Government outside Athens [Stuttgart 1997] 17-22); Fleming, Daniel, Democracy’s Ancient Ancestors: Mari and Early Collective Governance (Cambridge 2004). 9. On forms of “collective governance” in the ancient Near East: Fleming (last section); Schemeil, Yves, La Politique dans l’ancien Orient (Paris 1999); Momrak, Kristoffer, Popular Power in Ancient Near Eastern and Archaic Greek Polities (Dissertation University of Bergen, Norway, 2013). 10. On the polis as a “citizen state” and its role in Homer: Hansen, Mogens H., “The Polis as a Citizen State,” in Hansen (ed.), The Ancient Greek City State (Copenhagen 1993) 7-29; Raaflaub, Kurt A., “Homer to Solon: The Rise of the Polis. The Written Evidence,” ibid. 41-105; Hansen, Polis and City-State: An Ancient Concept and Its Modern Equivalent (Copenhagen 1998). See also chapters in books listed in (1) and (2) above. On the concept of citizenship: Manville, P. Brook, The Origins of Citizenship in Ancient Athens (Princeton 1990); Whitehead, David, “Norms of Citizenship in Ancient Greece,” in Anthony Molho, Kurt Raaflaub, and Julia Emlen (eds.), Athens and Rome, Florence and Venice: City-States in Classical Antiquity and Medieval Italy (Stuttgart and Ann Arbor 1991) 135-41; Wood, E. M., “The Demos versus ‘We, the People’: From Ancient to Modern Conceptions of Citizenship,” in Wood, Democracy against Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism (Cambridge 1995) 204-37. 11. On the comparison between various types of city-states: Griffeth, Robert G., and Carol G. Thomas (eds.), The City-State in Five Cultures (Santa Barbara CA and Oxford 1981); Molho et al., Athens and Rome (section 10 above); Mogens H. Hansen (ed.), A comparative Study of Thirty City-State Cultures (Copenhagen 2000); Hansen (ed.), A comparative Study of Six City-State Cultures (Copenhagen 2002). 12. On “epic society” and the role of leaders, assemblies, and soldiers: Finley, M. I., The World of Odysseus (2nd ed. London 1977); Latacz, Joachim, Homer: His Art and His World (Ann Arbor 1986); Raaflaub, Kurt, “Homeric Society,” in Ian Morris and Barry Powell (eds.), A New Companion to Homer (Leiden 1997) 624-49; Raaflaub, “Politics and Interstate Relations in the World of Early Greek Poleis: Homer and Beyond,” Antichthon 31 (1997) 1-27; Raaflaub, “Homeric Warriors and Battles: Trying to Resolve Old Problems,” Classical World 101 (2008) 469-83. See also Finkelberg, Margalit (ed.), Homer Encyclopedia (3 vols., Malden MA and Oxford 2011). 13. On the Greek polis and its egalitarian foundations: Morris, Ian, Archaeology as Cultural History (Malden MA and Oxford 2000), part III; Raaflaub, Kurt A., and Robert W. Wallace, 2 Raaflaub, Needle’s Eye HO 15 “‘People’s Power’ and Egalitarian Trends in Archaic Greece,” in Raaflaub et al. 2007 (in section 5 above) 22-48. 14. On the Greeks’ need to find their own solutions for their own problems: Meier (section 1 above). 15. Humans are responsible for their own well-being or suffering: Homer, Odyssey 1.26-42: (Zeus is speaking in an assembly of the gods) “Ah, how shameless—the way these mortals blame the gods. / From us alone, they say, come all their miseries, yes, / but they themselves, with their own reckless ways, / compound their pains beyond their proper share…”; Solon, fragm. 4.1-6 West: “Our city will never be destroyed by the fate / of Zeus or the plans of the immortal gods, / for Pallas Athena, our protector,… holds her hands over us. / But the citizens themselves, lured by wealth, want to bring / this great city down with their recklessness.” 16. On the Greek invention of laws: Gagarin, Michael, Early Greek Law (Berkeley 1986); Gagarin, Writing Greek Law (Cambridge 2008); Thomas, Rosalind, “Written in Stone? Liberty, Equality, Orality, and the Codification of Law,” in Lin Foxhall and A.D.E. Lewis (eds.), Greek Law in Its Political Setting: Justifications not Justice (Oxford 1996) 9-31; Farenga, Vincent, Citizen and Self in Ancient Greece: Individuals Performing Justice and the Law (Cambridge 2006); Hawke, Jason, Writing Authority: Elite Competition and Written Law in Early Greece (DeKalb IL 2011). On Near Eastern and Greek Law: Raaflaub, Kurt A., “Early Greek Political Thought in Its Mediterranean Context,” in Ryan Balot (ed.), A Companion to Greek and Roman Political Thought (Malden MA and Oxford 2009) 37-56. 17. The Earliest Greek Law (from Dreros on Crete, c. 650-600 BCE): “This has been decided by the polis: When a man has been Kosmos [supreme magistrate], for ten years that same man shall not be Kosmos. If he should become Kosmos, whatever judgments he gives, he himself shall owe double, and he shall be useless [without active citizen rights] as long as he lives, and what he does as Kosmos shall be as nothing…” (#11 in Fornara, Charles W., Archaic Times to the End of the Peloponnesian War. Translated Documents of Greece and Rome, vol. 1 [2nd ed. Cambridge 1983] p.11). 18. On the lawgivers (mediators, or “straighteners”): Meier, Greek Invention (section 5 above) 40-52; Wallace, Robert W., “Charismatic Leaders,” in Raaflaub and van Wees, Companion (section 2 above) 411-26. 19. Sparta’s “Great Rhetra,” the first polis constitution: Tyrtaeus, fragm. 4 West: The god-honored kings shall be leaders of the council (or: first in debate), / they who care for the lovely city of Sparta, / and the elders of revered age, and then the men of the people, / responding in turn to straight proposals. / They shall speak what is good and do everything justly / and counsel nothing for the city (that is crooked). / Victory and power (kratos) shall accompany the mass of the people (demos). / For Phoibos has so revealed this to the city. Plutarch, Life of Lycurgus 6: When you have built a temple to Zeus Sullanius and Athena Sullania, divided the people into ‘phylai’ and into ‘obai’ [civic subdivisions] and established a council of thirty members, including the ‘archagetai’ [the ‘leaders’], then from time to time hold 3 Raaflaub, Needle’s Eye HO 15 an ‘appella’ [assembly] between Babyka and Knakion [probably locations], and there introduce and rescind measures; but the people (demos) must have the deciding voice [literally: victory] and the power (kratos). Between these [locations] they held their assemblies, having neither halls nor any other kind of building for the purpose… When the masses were thus assembled, no one of them was permitted to make a motion, but the motion laid before them by the councillors and kings could be accepted or rejected by the people. [Scholars debate whether the following was part of the original rhetra or a later addition.] But if the people should adopt a distorted [“crooked”] motion, the councilors and kings shall have the power of adjournment.
Recommended publications
  • Agorapicbk-17.Pdf
    Excavations of the Athenian Agora Picture Book No. 17 Prepared by Mabel L. Lang Dedicated to Eugene Vanderpool o American School of Classical Studies at Athens ISBN 87661-617-1 Produced by the Meriden Gravure Company Meriden, Connecticut COVER: Bone figure of Socrates TITLE PAGE: Hemlock SOCRATES IN THE AGORA AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY 1978 ‘Everything combines to make our knowledge of Socrates himself a subject of Socratic irony. The only thing we know definitely about him is that we know nothing.’ -L. Brunschvicg As FAR AS we know Socrates himselfwrote nothing, yet not only were his life and words given dramatic attention in his own time in the Clouds of Ar- istophanes, but they have also become the subject of many others’ writing in the centuries since his death. Fourth-century B.C. writers who had first-hand knowledge of him composed either dialogues in which he was the dominant figure (Plato and Aeschines) or memories of his teaching and activities (Xe- nophon). Later authors down even to the present day have written numerous biographies based on these early sources and considering this most protean of philosophers from every possible point of view except perhaps the topograph- ical one which is attempted here. Instead of putting Socrates in the context of 5th-century B.C. philosophy, politics, ethics or rhetoric, we shall look to find him in the material world and physical surroundings of his favorite stamping- grounds, the Athenian Agora. Just as ‘agora’ in its original sense meant ‘gathering place’ but came in time to mean ‘market place’, so the agora itself was originally a gathering place I.
    [Show full text]
  • S Cimon, Son of Miltiades (Father) And
    is is a version of an electronic document, part of the series, Dēmos: Clas- sical Athenian Democracy, a publicationpublication ofof e Stoa: a consortium for electronic publication in the humanities [www.stoa.org]. e electronic version of this article off ers contextual information intended to make the study of Athenian democracy more accessible to a wide audience. Please visit the site at http:// www.stoa.org/projects/demos/home. Cimon S Cimon, son of Miltiades (father) and Hegesipyle (mother), was a prominent Athenian in the fi rst half of the th cen- tury . He was instrumental in leading Athens to a dominant position in the Greek world a er the Persian Wars, and he opposed the more radical democratic re- forms of Ephialtes and Pericles, particularly their reform of the Court of the Areopagus. I: C’ F C In the early th century Athens became increasingly more democratic as the older institutions, which were dominated by the wealthy, lost power to newer institutions that were in the hands of the People. is change was not welcomed by everyone, and even a hundred years later, an aristocratic Athenian like Isocrates could complain of how, a er the Persian Wars, “the city grew powerful and seized the empire of the Greeks, and our fathers, growing more self–assured than was proper for them, began to look with Christopher W. Blackwell, “Cimon,” in C. Blackwell, ed., Dēmos: Classical Athenian Democracy (A.(A. MahoneyMahoney andand R.R. Scaife,Scaife, edd.,edd., e Stoa: a consortium for electronic publication in the humanities [www.stoa.org], .
    [Show full text]
  • Plato As a Game Theorist Towards an International Trade Policy
    Journal of Risk and Financial Management Article Plato as a Game Theorist towards an International Trade Policy George E. Halkos * , Nicholas C. Kyriazis and Emmanouil M. L. Economou Department of Economics, University of Thessaly, 38333 Volos, Greece; [email protected] (N.C.K.); [email protected] (E.M.L.E.) * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +30-2421-074-664 Abstract: In the beginning of the second book of his Politeia (Republic) Plato in passage 2.358e–359a–c raises the issue of the administration of justice as a means of motivating people to behave fairly regarding their relationships and when cooperating with each other because, at the end, this is mutually beneficial for all of them. We argue that this particular passage could be seen as a part of a wider process of evolution and development of the institutions of the ancient Athenian economy during the Classical period (508–322 BCE) and could be interpreted through modern theoretical concepts, and more particularly, game theory. Plato argued that there are two players, each with two identical strategies, to treat the other justly or unjustly. In the beginning, each player chooses the “unjust” strategy, trying to cheat the other. In this context, which could be seen as a prisoner’s dilemma situation, both end with the worst possible outcome, that is, deceiving each other and this has severe financial consequences for both of them. Realizing this, in a repeated game situation, with increasing information on the outcome and on each other, they choose the “just” strategy so achieving the best outcome and transforming the game in a cooperative one.
    [Show full text]
  • A Few Aspects of Well-Known Athenian Isonomia in Ancient Greece and Its Opposition to the Profession of a Logographer
    Scripta Neophilologica Posnaniensia. Tom XVI, strony: 207–218 Wydział Neofilologii, Uniwersytet im. Adama Mickiewicza w Poznaniu, 2016 DOI 10.7169/snp.2016.16.15 A FEW ASPECTS OF WELL-KNOWN ATHENIAN ISONOMIA IN ANCIENT GREECE AND ITS OPPOSITION TO THE PROFESSION OF A LOGOGRAPHER KRYSTYNA TUSZYŃSKA At the beginning of my article I should explain two terms used in the history of ancient Greek culture, that is LOGOGRAPHOS and ISONOMIA. Neither of them is definite. The first one, the Greek technical term LOGOGRAPHOS (English „lo- gographer‟), was in the history of literature popularized by German philologist and archaeologist Georg Friedrich (1771–1858) and was considered to have been connected with two kinds of literary men: (1) the Ionian writer telling stories before Herodotus and (2) the paid speech writer in Athens in the fifth and fourth century B.C. The first meaning is of little interest to us: the authors of the first ethnographical and geographical works did not distinguish facts from fiction; they are, nevertheless, the oldest prose writers in Greek literature. In the opinion of Thucydides, logogra- phers composed their works with a purpose to impress the audience rather than to present the truth (Peloponnesian War, book I, 21.1). The second term is linked with Athenian jurisdiction. The moral value of this term is my main interest in this article. The well-known Greek word ISONOMIA popularly meant no more than „equality before the law‟1. The term is usually related to Greek democracy, but, interestingly, it was used not only in reference to Athenian democracy and not only by Athenian writers.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham E-Theses
    Durham E-Theses The documents in the public speeches of Demosthenes: authenticity and tradition CANEVARO, MIRKO How to cite: CANEVARO, MIRKO (2011) The documents in the public speeches of Demosthenes: authenticity and tradition, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/3263/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk 2 Mirko Canevaro The documents in the public speeches of Demosthenes: authenticity and tradition The thesis is concerned with the official documents (laws and decrees) preserved in the public speeches of the Demosthenic corpus (18, 21, 23, 24, 59). These documents purport to be Athenian statutes and, if authentic, would provide invaluable information about fourth-century Athenian history and institutions. The introduction gives an account of the presence of the documents in the corpora of the orators and in the manuscript tradition, summarizes previous scholarship and delineates a new methodology for analyzing the documents.
    [Show full text]
  • The Athenian Ecclesia and the Assembly-Place on the Pnyx Mogens Herman Hansen
    HANSEN, MOGENS HERMAN, The Athenian "Ecclesia" and the Assembly-Place on the Pnyx , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 23:3 (1982:Autumn) p.241 The Athenian Ecclesia and the Assembly-Place on the Pnyx Mogens Herman Hansen N EARLIER ARTICLES in this journal I discussed the question how I many citizens the meeting place of the assembly on the Pnyx could accommodate and the question how the Athenians were seated during the sessions.l Inspired by H. A. Thompson's recent article about the Pnyx,2 I take this opportunity to return to the sub­ ject, concentrating on three problems. (1) The quorum of 6000 and the size of the auditorium of Pnyx I (ea 460-400), (2) the connec­ tion between admission and payment for attendance in the second period (ea 400-340), and (3) the evidence for subdivisions of the auditorium of Pnyx III (after 340). I. Pnyx I and the Quorum of 6000 It is fairly certain that the total area of the auditorium of Pnyx I was about 2400 square meters.3 The minimum space required for a human being attending a large meeting seems to be 0.4 square meters, a figure comprising the space filled by rows of benches (or cushions) and the space between the rows. 4 Consequently Pnyx I accommodated a maximum of 6000 citizens. In my opinion it cannot be a coincidence that the maximum attendance is identical with the quorum of 6000 prescribed in several laws;5 but the connection allows of two explana­ tions: either the quorum was fixed because 6000 was the maximum number of citizens that Pnyx I could accommodate, or Pnyx I was constructed with a view to the previously established quorum of 6000.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modes of Classical Athenian Justice
    Articles "Verdict Most Just": The Modes of Classical Athenian Justice Adriaan Lanni* I. INTRODUCTION Most comparative lawyers know a great deal about Roman law but almost nothing about the courts of classical Athens. This is no mystery: unlike Roman law, Athenian law produced no jurisprudence and very little legal doctrine, and contributed nothing to the courts of Europe, England, or any other modem legal system. For the most part, Athenians decided legal disputes by empowering juries to apply statutes that were hopelessly broad. Juries could give weight to any sort of fact or plea that a litigant * Harvard University, Society of Fellows. J.D. Yale Law School, Ph.D. (Ancient History) University of Michigan. I would like to thank Oren Bar-Gill, Victor Bers, Sara Forsdyke, Bruce Frier, Michael Gagarin, Michael Gordin, Robert Gordon, Thomas Green, Wesley Kelman, Eric Miller, James Whitman, and James Boyd White for their comments. Amanda Holm provided excellent research assistance. Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities, Vol. 16, Iss. 2 [2004], Art.[Vol 1 16:277 cared to bring before them. To us, this looks like lawlessness. Did the Athenians simply fail to grasp the value of the rule of law as we know it? Were legal disputes fundamentally contests for status decided without any pretence to justice? These are the explanations ancient historians commonly give. In my view, the Athenian legal system was more complex than is generally thought. The Athenians made a conscious decision to reject the rule of law in most cases, and they did so because they thought giving juries unlimited discretion to reach verdicts based on the particular circumstances of each case was the most just way to resolve disputes.
    [Show full text]
  • Development of Ancient Athens Before Hellenistic Period
    Center for Open Access in Science ▪ https://www.centerprode.com/ojsh.html Open Journal for Studies in History, 2019, 2(2), 27-34. ISSN (Online) 2620-066X ▪ https://doi.org/10.32591/coas.ojsh.0202.01027m _________________________________________________________________________ Development of Ancient Athens Before Hellenistic Period Juan Sergio Martinez Vazquez Autonomous University of Carmen, MEXICO Faculty of Educational Sciences, Campeche Received 1 October 2019 ▪ Revised 13 December 2019 ▪ Accepted 15 December 2019 Abstract This paper describes a brief overview of the history of ancient Athens, from the period of the first legislators to the Hellenistic period. One of the basic features that characterize this period is the continued presence of conflicts and hostilities between Athens and rival city-states, including those in present-day Greece, but also in Asia Minor and Southern Italy. Also, this period is followed by the continuing threatening and battles with the Persian Empire. It is a period of the history of Athens in which huge social development takes place, in all segments of social life. The various institutions of the state are established, and during this period, regardless of the presence of phases of tyranny as a form of government, the foundations of the democratic system, which exists in the modern world, are being created. Also, there has been an unprecedented period of development in history in the fields of philosophy, science, culture, art and social life in general. Keywords: ancient Athens, democracy, legislative, Golden age, Peloponnesian war. 1. Introduction In ancient times, Athens was ruled by kings, i.e. basileus (βασιλεύς). Their rule was first restricted and then abolished by eupatrids.
    [Show full text]
  • Busybody Athenians, Meddlesome Citizenship, and Epistemic Democracy in Classical Athens
    Bowdoin College Bowdoin Digital Commons Honors Projects Student Scholarship and Creative Work 2016 Political Polupragmones: Busybody Athenians, Meddlesome Citizenship, and Epistemic Democracy in Classical Athens Harry D. Rube Bowdoin College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bowdoin.edu/honorsprojects Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, and the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Rube, Harry D., "Political Polupragmones: Busybody Athenians, Meddlesome Citizenship, and Epistemic Democracy in Classical Athens" (2016). Honors Projects. 46. https://digitalcommons.bowdoin.edu/honorsprojects/46 This Open Access Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship and Creative Work at Bowdoin Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Projects by an authorized administrator of Bowdoin Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Political Polupragmones: Busybody Athenians, Meddlesome Citizenship, and Epistemic Democracy in Classical Athens An Honors Paper for the Department of Classics By Harry David Rube Bowdoin College, 2016 ©2016 Harry David Rube Table of Contents Acknowledgements p.iii Introduction p.1 Chapter One: “Minding One’s Own Business” in Homeric and Archaic Greek Literature p.11 Chapter Two: Being a Busybody in Fifth-Century Athens p.28 Chapter Three: From Rhetoric to the Republic: Polypragmosune in the Orators and Plato p.52 Chapter Four: Epistemic Democracy and the Polypragmon p.90 Conclusion p.128 Works Cited p.132 ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank a number of individuals and organizations that have supported me in carrying out this research project over the last year.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concepts of Demos, Ekklesia, and Dikasterion in Classical Athens Mogens Herman Hansen
    The Concepts of Demos, Ekklesia, and Dikasterion in Classical Athens Mogens Herman Hansen NTIL A GENERATION AGO it was generally believed by students of Athenian democracy that throughout the Classical period the sovereign body of government in U 1 Athens was the people’s assembly, called demos or ekklesia. Admittedly, the powers of the assembly were considerably restricted by the people’s court. Most of the judicial powers rested with the jurors sitting in the dikasteria2 and a decree passed by the assembly could be challenged by a graphe para- nomon and quashed if a majority of the jurors voted for the prosecution. There was, however, no proper separation of powers between assembly and court since the demos was iden- tical not only with the assembly but also with the court. The people’s court was a committee of the assembly or, simply, the demos sitting in judgment. To allow the people’s court to quash 1 The orthodox view is set out in detail 520–521 infra. The following will be cited by author’s name and date: M. H. Hansen, “Demos, Ecclesia and Di- casterion in Classical Athens,” in The Athenian Ecclesia. A Collection of Articles 1976–83 (Copenhagen 1983) 139–160, an updated version of GRBS 19 (1978) 127–146; The Athenian Assembly (Oxford 1987); “The Political Powers of the People’s Court in Fourth-Century Athens,” in O. Murray and S. Price (eds.), The Greek City from Homer to Alexander (Oxford 1990) 215–244; The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes (Oxford 1991, 2London 1999); J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Homicide Courts of Ancient Athens
    THE HOMICIDE COURTS OF ANCIENT ATHENS. Early Athens, like other primitive communities, was ruled not by laws, but by customs. The custom in any matter was what everyone did under similar circumstances. As Plato says! "'They [primitive men] could hardly have wanted lawyers as yet; nothing of that sort was likely to have existed in those days, for they had no letters at this early stage; they lived according to custom and the laws of their fathers, as they are termed." I In other words, in the absence of formal laws, justice was synonymous with precedent. At first, crimes, which later were looked upon as offenses against the state, were merely private affairs. Thus murder was only a private offense against the victim and his surviving kinsmen. To have slain a man was a misfortune, for it entailed serious consequences. In the Home- ric civilization the kinsmen might or might not accept wergeld as compensation for the loss and the idea of accepting it was' regarded as a perfectly justifiable alternative to exacting blood, vengeance. By giving presents to the relatives of the murdered man, the offender not only could repair the loss inflicted upon' them by the death of their kinsman, but he could also appease their anger, as the pleasure of revenge would tend to alleviate their indignation' and loss and the humiliation of their enemy would help to heal their resentment. Furthermore, the accept-" ance of compensation was a matter of expediency; for it saved the injured party from the risks involved in carrying out the blood-feud, i.
    [Show full text]
  • The Archaeology of “Celebrities” in the Greek and Roman Worlds
    L’Orange lecture 2017 THE ARCHAEOLOGY OF “CELEBRITIES” IN THE GREEK AND ROMAN WORLDS 311 JONATHAN M. HALL The archaeology of “celebrities” in the Greek and Roman worlds1 Abstract The debate about the identification of the house of Augustus on the Palatine hill or the controversy surrounding the occupant of Tomb 2 at Vergina or the recently excavated funerary complex at Amphipolis offer more than sufficient evidence for a public fascination with important historical personalities. Yet, at the same time, discipli- nary trends in archaeology have sought to emancipate the material record from historicizing narratives and to occlude or decentre the knowing subject. The archaeology of the individual has become, at best, a quaint, anti- quarian pursuit and, at worst, a celebration of neo-conservative ideology. This article will consider a series of case-studies from the ancient Greek and Roman worlds with the aim of illuminating the viability – and desirability – of practicing an archaeology of famous individuals. Unearthing celebrities To appreciate the impact that the archaeology of ancient celebrities can exercise on the popu- lar imagination, one has only to consider the extraordinary events that accompanied the exca- vation, between 2012 and 2014, of the monumental funerary complex at Kasta hill, near the ancient city of Amphipolis in northern Greece.2 Amidst a blaze of publicity, including daily news conferences, online discussions and blogs, and a high profile visit from the then prime minister, speculation ran rife as to the identity of the occupant of the tomb: among the most popular candidates were Alexander the Great’s Baktrian wife, Roxane; his posthumous son, Alexander IV; his mother, Olympias; his trusted companion, Hephaisteion; or even Alexan- der himself – despite the unanimous source tradition that located the Macedonian king’s final 1 An earlier version of this article was delivered as the L’Orange Lecture at the Norwegian Institute in Rome on Novem- ber 2, 2017.
    [Show full text]