A Defense of Materialism Against Attacks Based on Qualia

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Defense of Materialism Against Attacks Based on Qualia University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1998 A defense of materialism against attacks based on qualia. J. C. Beall University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Beall, J. C., "A defense of materialism against attacks based on qualia." (1998). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2312. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2312 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A DEFENSE OF MATERIALISM AGAINST ATTACKS BASED ON QUALIA A Dissertation Presented by JEFFREY C. BEALL Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY February 1998 Philosophy Department © Copyright by Jeffrey Charles Beall 1998 All Rights Reserved A DEFENSE OF MATERIALISM AGAINST ATTACKS BASED ON QUALIA A Dissertation Presented by JEFFREY C. BEALL Approved as to style and content by: Lynne.ynne Baker, Chair ruce Aune, Member Gateih Matthews, Member Harlan Sturm, Member on, Department Head osophy Department ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many people deserve to be richly thanked for their help, in various ways, with this project. Among these folks are David Braddon-Mitchell, Ben Bradley, David Chalmers, Fred Feldman, Gary Hardegree, Gilbert Harman, Frank Jackson, and Erik Wielenberg. Gary Matthews and Bruce Aune deserve special thanks for their helpful roles as committee members for this project. Jay Garfield likewise deserves special thanks for his very helpful email correspondence on almost every issue in this project. Without Lynne Baker’s consistently encouraging words but equally consistent criticism, this project would be a mess — plain and simple. To her I owe a great deal. Of course, as usual, I alone deserve the blame for messiness that remains. I also want to thank my first philosophy teacher, Professor Richard Trammell. He’s to blame for the frustrations I’ve had with philosophy; but he’s also to thank for giving me the desire to persevere through those frustrations — and unto the Truth (I hope!). In addition, my family has always been important to me, and has never failed to be an unshakable source of strength. Thanks to Kathy, Beth, Mark, Rebecca, Dee Dee & Pop, and, especially, Mom and Dad. Above all, I wish to thank the most important person in my life — alas, another Australian! My wife, Katrina Higgins Beall, has been through this entire journey — indeed, she was there, four years ago in Australia, at the start of my frustrations with the Knowledge Argument. She has endured a great deal of stress since that time, especially IV while I’ve tried to write this project in a very short ttme-span. With my deepest gratitude and love, I dedicate this project to her - despite the fact that she won’t read it! V ABSTRACT A DEFENSE OF MATERIALISM AGAINST ATTACKS BASED ON QUALIA FEBRUARY 1998 JEFFREY C. BEALL, B.A., GROVE CITY COLLEGE M.DIV., PRINCETON THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY M.A., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Ph D., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Directed by: Professor Lynne R. Baker Qualia — the “what it’s like features” of minds — pose a great challenge to a materialist view of the world. The two strongest and most popular objections to materialism based on qualia are the Zombie Argument and the Knowledge Argument. The current dissertation defends (minimal) materialism against these two popular arguments. I argue that if zombie worlds exist, then qualia cause no physical events — they’re epiphenomenalp, or epiphenomenal with respect to the physical domain of our world. I argue, however, that there is good reason to reject the view that qualia are epiphenomenalp, and thus that there is good reason to deny the existence of zombie worlds. In turn, I argue that the Knowledge Argument likewise requires the existence of zombie worlds, and thus that the Knowledge Argument should likewise be rejected. vi PREFACE This project stems from a frustration I’ve had for the last four years. The frustration comes from Australia in the work of Frank C. Jackson - in particular, Jackson’s infamous Knowledge Argument against 1 materialism. For the last four years, I ve thought of various objections to the argument but none of them ultimately satisfied me. (The most frustrating part was the recurring pattern of thinking that this objection is the one onl t0 ’ y dlscover a few days later that that objection couldn 7 be one at all.) Along the way, I also consulted the objections of others. These, too, were ultimately unsatisfactory. But despite all these unsatisfactory objections, I still believed that something, somewhere, had to be wrong with the Knowledge Argument, though I couldn t exactly put my finger on it. Soon, frustration grew into disgust, and I was all but ready to solve the problem by ignoring it — which, of course, is a psychological solution but makes for no philosophical progress. During this near-quitting period, I began to notice a tremendous surge of interest in what is now called the Zombie Argument against materialism. Keith Campbell (another Australian) used this sort of argument against materialism in 1977, but not much more was made of it — until very recently. During the last year and a half, the Zombie Argument against materialism has become a very hot topic, both in (hardcopy) literature and electronic journals, discussion lists, et cetera. Much of this popularity has to do with the popularity of David Chalmers’ (yet another Australian!) Zombie Argument, published in his The Conscious Mind (1996). But irrespective of its origins, the Zombie Argument 1 All of Chapter 4 is devoted to Jackson’s argument, so I don’t bother giving references here in the Preface. has taken off; and it's now perhaps the most popular, and in many ways the most fundamental, argument against materialism today. Not long after soaking myself in zombie literature did I realize that I finally had a solid response to Jackson's Knowledge Argument. As it turned out, the response I came up with against the Zombie Argument has an immediate application to the Knowledge Argument. Thanks to discussion with Jay Garfield - who, at the time, happened to be thinking about the same topic — my response to both arguments were quickly sharpened into their present form. This project presents these arguments. The basic thesis is that materialism is threatened by neither the Zombie Argument — which, for reasons that will be clear in the main discussion, takes center stage — nor the long-dreaded Knowledge Argument. This result is both philosophically and, of course, psychologically satisfying — at least to me! In some ways, this discussion is a narrow debate — a debate between so-called zombiephiles and minimal materialists. The framework of the debate will be made clear in both Chapter I and Chapter II. The heart of the project lies in Chapter III, and extends into Chapter IV. Chapter V, finally, is offered in response to general objections to the overall project objections that will be clear as things progress. But despite its potential narrowness, I do that hope the current discussion is of value to those whose views fall outside of its bounds. I hope so, anyway. viii 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ABSTRACT iii PREFACE Chapter 1. MINIMAL MATERIALISM, THE MIND, AND QUALIA i 1.1 Materialism and The Mind j 1.1.1 Broadly Logical Possibility 2 1 . 1.2 Supervenience 7 1.1.3 Materialism As Supervenience 10 1.1.4 Objections and Replies \ § 1.2 The Mind Versus Materialism 24 1 . 2.1 Mind: Intentional and Phenomenal 24 1 .2.2 Materialism and The Intentional Mind 28 1 .2.3 Materialism and The Phenomenal Mind 34 1.3 Review of Chapter 1 2. THE ZOMBIE ARGUMENT 2.1 Zombies, Zombie Worlds, and The Zombie Argument 50 2.1.1 Zombies 50 2. 1 .2 Zombie Worlds 53 2. 1 .3 The Zombie Argument Against Materialism 55 2.2 Some Common Objections to the Zombie Argument — and Replies 58 2.2 . The Question-Begging Objection 58 2.2.2 The Conceivability Objection 62 2.2.3 The “If you believe it, then you got it” Objection 69 2.2.4 Two Objections Against “Intentional Duplicates” 73 2.2.4. 1 The Qualitative Belief Objection 74 2. 2. 4. 2 The “Qualia Are Necessary For Some Beliefs” Objection 79 IX 1 1 2.3 Review of Chapter 2 THE MAIN DEFENSE AGAINST THE ZOMBIE ARGUMENT 92 3.1 The Epiphenomenalp Objection 93 3 11 The Epiphenomenalp Argument 93 3.1.2 Objections and Replies 99 3. 1.2.1 The Causal Overdetermination Objection (0.1) 99 3. 1.2. 2 Causal closure and question-begging objection (0.2) 102 3. 1.2.3 The Partial Causation Objection (0.3) 104 3. 1.2.4 The Overdetermination Objection - Again (0.4) 106 3.1.3 Review of Subchapter 3.1 3.2 Epiphenomenalp qualia? jq9 3.2.1 The Case From Commonsense 1 10 3.2.2 The Argument from Complete Science 1 13 3.2.3 Why the argument from complete science fails 115 3.3 Review of Chapter 3 120 ZOMBIE WORLDS & THE KNOWLEDGE ARGUMENT 123 4.1 The Story of Mary and The Knowledge Argument 124 4.1.1 The Story of Mary 124 4.1.2 The Knowledge Argument 126 4.2 Common Objections to the Knowledge Argument 128 4.2. 1 The Intensional Fallacy Objection 1 29 4.2.2 The “no metaphysics from epistemology” Objection 1 3 4.2.3 The Question-Begging Objection 134 4.3.14.2.4 The Language Objection 138 4.2.5 The Abilities Objection 141 4.2.6 The Different Descriptions or “Modes” Objection 145 4.2.7 Review of 4.2 150 4.3 Zombie Worlds & the Real Problem with the Knowledge Argument 151 Zombie Worlds & The Knowledge Argument 151 4.3.
Recommended publications
  • Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 12 Issue 4 Article 1 10-1-1995 Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia? David Merrihew Lewis Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Lewis, David Merrihew (1995) "Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 12 : Iss. 4 , Article 1. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol12/iss4/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. SHOULD A MATERIALIST BELIEVE IN QUALIA? David Lewis Should a materialist believe in qualia? Yes and no. 'Qualia' is a name for the occupants of a certain functional role that is spelled out in our tacitly known folk psychology. If materialism is true, there are no perfect occu­ pants of the role, and hence no perfect deservers of the name. But in all probability there are imperfect occupants of the role, imperfect deservers of the name. Good enough deservers of the name? May they just be called 'qualia'? I say yes. But I take this to be a case of semantic indecision. There is no settled answer to the question 'how good is good enough?'.
    [Show full text]
  • Dennett's Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness
    Dennett’s Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness1 Justin Sytsma Abstract: It is not uncommon to find assumptions being made about folk psychology in the discussions of phenomenal consciousness in philosophy of mind. In this article I consider one example, focusing on what Dan Dennett says about the “folk theory of consciousness.” I show that he holds that the folk believe that qualities like colors that we are acquainted with in ordinary perception are phenomenal qualities. Nonetheless, the shape of the folk theory is an empirical matter and in the absence of empirical investigation there is ample room for doubt. Fortunately, experimental evidence on the topic is now being produced by experimental philosophers and psychologists. This article contributes to this growing literature, presenting the results of six new studies on the folk view of colors and pains. I argue that the results indicate against Dennett’s theory of the folk theory of consciousness. The existence of phenomenal consciousness is often taken for granted in the philosophical and scientific literature on the topic. Sometimes, this attitude is supported by claims that phenomenal consciousness is in some way evident in our ordinary experience itself.2 The prevalence of this attitude can also be seen in the way that some skeptics about phenomenal consciousness discuss the supposed phenomenon. For example, the qualia eliminativist Dan Dennett seems to accept that belief in qualia is part of our “folk theory of consciousness” (2005, 31). In contrast, I have argued that phenomenal consciousness is not evident in ordinary experience alone—that it is not phenomenologically obvious—and that this can be drawn out by 1 To appear in the Journal of Consciousness Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Privileged Access and Qualia
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by European Scientific Journal (European Scientific Institute) European Scientific Journal December 2015 edition vol.11, No.35 ISSN: 1857 – 7881 (Print) e - ISSN 1857- 7431 PRIVILEGED ACCESS AND QUALIA Thomas W. Smythe Retired Associate Professor, North Carolina Central University Abstract In this paper I shall examine some recent literature that purports to show that sensations or qualia are not real psychological phenomena, and that we do not have privileged access to our psychological states. In particular, I shall criticize some work by Daniel C. Dennett, who has argued against the existence of qualia and privileged access to the mental. I will maintain that Dennett has not made a convincing case for eliminating qualia, and has not shown that we do not have privileged access to psychological phenomena from a first-person point of view. Keywords: Qualia, Privileged Access, Self-Warranting Knowledge Introduction I will defend the view that certain criticisms of what has been called self-justifying or self-warranting knowledge of our psychological states have not succeeded. I will do this by arguing that attempts by Dennett and others to undermine self-justifying knowledge are unsuccessful. I begin by examining a paper by Dennett where he attempts to eliminate qualia. In a notable paper called ”Quining Qualia,” Dennett explains that he uses the verb ‘to quine’ in honor of W. V. O. Quine. It means to deny resolutely the existence or importance of something seemingly real and significant, for example, the soul. Quining qualia means saying there is no such thing as qualia.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia NICHOLAS HARKNESS Harvard University, USA
    Qualia NICHOLAS HARKNESS Harvard University, USA Qualia (singular, quale) are cultural emergents that manifest phenomenally as sensuous features or qualities. The anthropological challenge presented by qualia is to theorize elements of experience that are semiotically generated but apperceived as non-signs. Qualia are not reducible to a psychology of individual perceptions of sensory data, to a cultural ontology of “materiality,” or to philosophical intuitions about the subjective properties of consciousness. The analytical solution to the challenge of qualia is to con- sider tone in relation to the familiar linguistic anthropological categories of token and type. This solution has been made methodologically practical by conceptualizing qualia, in Peircean terms, as “facts of firstness” or firstness “under its form of secondness.” Inthephilosophyofmind,theterm“qualia”hasbeenusedtodescribetheineffable, intrinsic, private, and directly or immediately apprehensible experiences of “the way things seem,” which have been taken to constitute the atomic subjective properties of consciousness. This concept was challenged in an influential paper by Daniel Dennett, who argued that qualia “is a philosophers’ term which fosters nothing but confusion, and refers in the end to no properties or features at all” (Dennett 1988, 387). Dennett concluded, correctly, that these diverse elements of feeling, made sensuously present atvariouslevelsofattention,wereactuallyidiosyncraticresponsestoapperceptions of “public, relational” qualities. Qualia were, in effect,
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology's
    Augsburg Honors Review Volume 12 Article 4 2019 Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Allison Mangan Augsburg University Follow this and additional works at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended Citation Mangan, Allison (2019) "Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire," Augsburg Honors Review: Vol. 12 , Article 4. Available at: https://idun.augsburg.edu/honors_review/vol12/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Idun. It has been accepted for inclusion in Augsburg Honors Review by an authorized editor of Idun. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Allison Mangan Qualia, the Heart of the Mind-Body Problem and Epistemology’s Quagmire Alio Maga, Augbug Univesty ualia are layered and complex, the basic philosophic understanding a labyrinth of a concept, of qualia today. We will see how Q rife with debate as to their consciousness is necessary for qualia, existence, state, and what they mean and why this makes defning qualia for our understanding of knowledge, a challenge. Next, we will go over the relationship with the world, and explanatory gap of qualia. From there, ourselves. Toughtful exploration into we will see how qualia relate to the mind- the complexities of what qualia are body problem, and the early exploration and how they relate to the mind-body of this problem through Descartes, problem will be wrestled with though Locke, and Berkeley. Additionally, we research applied within this paper. will go over the main schools of thought Qualia can be found in philosophical that surround the mind-body problem: debates surrounding epistemology materialism, idealism, and dualism.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a REFUTATION of QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael
    1 To appear in M. O’Rourke and C. Washington (eds.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry (MIT Press) A REFUTATION OF QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University Recent defenders of reductive physicalism such as Brian Loar (1990, 1997) and John Perry (2001) have adopted an intriguing new strategy:i (1) accept as so much common sense (nearly) everything that property-dualists want to say about sensory qualia, including the central claims that sensory qualia determine ‘what it’s like’ to have a given sense experience, and that persons are directly aware of these qualia in the having of such experiences; (2) contend that while these common sense facts about qualia may show that our ways of thinking and speaking about qualia are conceptually different from our ways of thinking and speaking about physical properties of the brain, these facts do not show that sensory qualia themselves (as opposed to our ways of thinking and speaking about them) are distinct from physical properties of the brain; (3) use this contention to turn aside the few existing arguments against reductive physicalism by such property dualists as Kripke (1972), Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996); and finally (4) insist that sensory qualia are in fact just identical with physical properties of the brain, so that consequently, the facts about the sensory qualities of conscious experience are nothing over and above physical facts about the brain. I will call the view that incorporates this strategy ‘qualia-physicalism’, or ‘Q-physicalism’ for short. In this paper I will argue that Q-physicalism is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind/Body Overview
    Mind/Body Overview 1. Physics and Folk Psychology a. Physics: hard-nosed, particles, observables, repeatable b. Folk Psychology: Beliefs, hopes, desires, sensations, subjective, consciousness 2. Issues a. Ontological 1. What are mental states and processes? 2. What are physical states and processes? 3. How are the mental and physical related? 4. Example: Replace NS with silicon starting at retina. Still conscious? b. Semantical 1. Where do propositional attitudes get their meanings? Ex: Belief; Belief that p. 2. Where do qualia get their meanings? Ex: pain, red, warmth 3. Where do other terms get their meanings? Ex: horse, electron c. Epistemological 1. How do we know anything? 2. How do we know if something has a mind? (Problem of other minds) 3. How do I know my own mental states? (Problem of self-consciousness) d. Methodological 1. What are appropriate methods for studying psychology? 2. What determines their propriety? 3. Ontologies a. Substance Dualism 1. Descartes: Mind is a distinct substance from matter 2. Matter: extended in space; has length, width, breadth, and position. 1 3. Mind: essence is thinking; has no extension or position in space. 4. Reasons: how could matter ever use language or reason mathematically? 5. Problem: How can mind interact with matter, and not violate conservation laws? 6. Problem: Electrons have no extension or determinate postion in space. Yet physical. 7. Eccles and Popper: mind affects probabilities of exocytosis at all synapses b. Popular Dualism 1. Mind is a “ghost in a machine”; machine=body; mind=spiritual substance 2. Mind is inside body (probably brain) 3. Mind interacts with brain by some form of energy exchange 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Environments of Intelligence
    Environments of Intelligence “An absorbing volume that integrates an extraordinarily wide area of work, with interesting observations and new twists right to the end.” Ruth Millikan, University of Connecticut, USA What is the role of the environment, and of the information it provides, in cognition? More specifically, may there be a role for certain artefacts to play in this context? These are questions that motivate “4E” theories of cognition (as being embodied, embedded, extended, enactive). In his take on that family of views, Hajo Greif first defends and refines a concept of information as primarily natural, environmen- tally embedded in character, which had been eclipsed by information-processing views of cognition. He continues with an inquiry into the cognitive bearing of some artefacts that are sometimes referred to as “intelligent environments”. With- out necessarily having much to do with Artificial Intelligence, such artefacts may ultimately modify our informational environments. With respect to human cognition, the most notable effect of digital computers is not that they might be able, or become able, to think but that they alter the way we perceive, think and act. Hajo Greif teaches at the Munich Center for Technology in Society (MCTS), Technical University of Munich, Germany, and the Department of Philosophy, University of Klagenfurt, Austria. His research interests cover the philosophy – and some of the history and the social studies – of science and technology, as well as the philosophy of mind. History and Philosophy of Technoscience Series Editor: Alfred Nordmann For a full list of titles in this series, please visit www.routledge.com 1 Error and Uncertainty in Scientific Practice Marcel Boumans, Giora Hon and Arthur C.
    [Show full text]
  • 15 How to Believe in Qualia
    15 How to Believe in Qualia Amy Kind Why should we believe that qualia exist? It would not be su~prisingif, when confronted with this question, the qualia realist were puzzled. "Look around you," she might say, "and then pause for just a moment and retlest on your experiences. Isn't there a redness to your experience of that soda can on your desk? And isn't there a sweetness to your experience as you take a sip from it? Surely your experiences have qualitative aspect+surely there is something your experiences are like!' And thus, to many a qualia realist, the answer to the question posed above is simple. Why believe in qualia? Because our every experience meals their existence. Unfortunately, the matter cannot be resolved this easily. (If it could, then there would be no need to produce a collection of papers making the case for quaUa.) The existence of qualia has long been under attack. Opponents of qualia typically fall into two camps. In the &st camp, we have philosophers who admit that, at least on the face of it, the phenom- enological data support the existence of qualia. By their lights, however, thm are strong theoretical reasons that count against qualia (typically that they cannot be accommodated within a physicalist framework). These opponents thui have the task of explaining why we should disregard the phenomenology of ow experience. They must convince us why we should not believe in qualia. In the second camp, however, are philosophers who deny the phenorn- enological data. Qualia realists have it wrong, they say.
    [Show full text]
  • Dennett's Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Philsci-Archive Dennett’s Theory of the Folk Theory of Consciousness1 Justin Sytsma Abstract: It is not uncommon to find assumptions being made about folk psychology in the discussions of phenomenal consciousness in philosophy of mind. In this article I consider one example, focusing on what Dan Dennett says about the “folk theory of consciousness.” I show that he holds that the folk believe that qualities like colors that we are acquainted with in ordinary perception are phenomenal qualities. Nonetheless, the shape of the folk theory is an empirical matter and in the absence of empirical investigation there is ample room for doubt. Fortunately, experimental evidence on the topic is now being produced by experimental philosophers and psychologists. This article contributes to this growing literature, presenting the results of six new studies on the folk view of colors and pains. I argue that the results indicate against Dennett’s theory of the folk theory of consciousness. The existence of phenomenal consciousness is often taken for granted in the philosophical and scientific literature on the topic. Sometimes, this attitude is supported by claims that phenomenal consciousness is in some way evident in our ordinary experience itself.2 The prevalence of this attitude can also be seen in the way that some skeptics about phenomenal consciousness discuss the supposed phenomenon. For example, the qualia eliminativist Dan Dennett seems to accept that belief in qualia is part of our “folk theory of consciousness” (2005, 31). In contrast, I have argued that phenomenal consciousness is not evident in ordinary experience alone—that it is not phenomenologically obvious—and that this can be drawn out by 1 To appear in the Journal of Consciousness Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Eidos Fecha De Recepción: Marzo 3 De 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha De Aceptación: Julio 28 De 2011 Issne 2011-7477
    eidos Fecha de recepción: marzo 3 de 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha de aceptación: julio 28 de 2011 ISSNe 2011-7477 IS THE PANPSYCHIST BETTER OFF AS AN IDEALIST? SOME LEIBNIZIAN REMARKS ON CONSCIOUSNESS AND COMPOSITION Michael Blamauer University of Vienna, Department of Philosophy [email protected] RESUMEN Algunos filósofos de la mente han defendido la idea de considerar la mente como otra característica fundamental de la realidad, además de las propiedades físicas. De ahí que la mayoría de ellos sean propiamente dualistas. Sin embargo, algunos de ellos son pansiquistas. En este artículo sostendré que ser propiamente un dualista implica, en esencia, ser pansiqui- sta. Incluso, si el pansiquismo aborda ciertas dificultades relacionadas con el problema de la conciencia de manera muy elegante, éstas permanecen inmodificables. Siendo partidario del carácter fundamental de la mente, de- fenderé la idea de que sólo mediante una revisión radical de la metafísica el pansiquista podrá evitar tales problemas y, en consecuencia, que debe adoptar el idealismo leibniciano. PALABRAS CLAVE Panpsiquismo, Leibniz, filosofía de la mente, dualismo, composición. ABSTRACT Some philosophers of mind have argued for considering consciousness as a further fundamental feature of reality in addition to its physical prop- erties. Hence most of them are property dualists. But some of them are panpsychists. In the present paper it will be argued that being a real prop- erty dualist essentially entails being a panpsychist. Even if panpsychism deals rather elegantly with certain problems of the puzzle of consciousness, there’s no way around the composition problem. Adhering to the funda- mentality claim of the mind, it will be shown that only a radical revision of metaphysics will allow the panpsychist to avoid these troubles, and hence that a panpsychist must adopt Leibnizian idealism.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz 1
    This article was downloaded by: [Stanford University Libraries] On: 24 September 2012, At: 17:23 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK British Journal for the History of Philosophy Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rbjh20 Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz Shane Duarte a a Stanford University, Version of record first published: 22 Sep 2009. To cite this article: Shane Duarte (2009): Ideas and Confusion in Leibniz , British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17:4, 705-733 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09608780903135089 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub- licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17(4) 2009: 705–733 ARTICLE IDEAS AND CONFUSION IN LEIBNIZ1 Shane Duarte I.
    [Show full text]