Variational Ansatz-Based Quantum Simulation of Imaginary Time Evolution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Variational Ansatz-Based Quantum Simulation of Imaginary Time Evolution Variational ansatz-based quantum simulation of imaginary time evolution Sam McArdle,1 Tyson Jones,1 Suguru Endo,1 Ying Li,2 Simon Benjamin,1 and Xiao Yuan1, ∗ 1Department of Materials, University of Oxford, Parks Road, Oxford OX1 3PH, United Kingdom 2Graduate School of China Academy of Engineering Physics, Beijing 100193, China (Dated: September 17, 2019) Imaginary time evolution is a powerful tool for studying quantum systems. While it is possible to simulate with a classical computer, the time and memory requirements generally scale exponentially with the system size. Conversely, quantum computers can efficiently simulate quantum systems, but not non-unitary imaginary time evolution. We propose a variational algorithm for simulating imaginary time evolution on a hybrid quantum computer. We use this algorithm to find the ground state energy of many-particle systems; specifically molecular Hydrogen and Lithium Hydride, finding the ground state with high probability. Our method can also be applied to general optimisation problems and quantum machine learning. As our algorithm is hybrid, suitable for error mitigation, and can exploit shallow quantum circuits, it can be implemented with current quantum computers. INTRODUCTION to represent the real time propagator with a sequence of Imaginary time is an unphysical, yet powerful, mathe- gates stems from its unitarity. In contrast, because the matical concept. It has been utilised in numerous phys- imaginary time operator is non-unitary, it is not straight- ical domains including: quantum mechanics, statistical forward to decompose it into a sequence of unitary gates mechanics, and cosmology. Often referred to as perform- using Trotterization, and thus directly realise it with a ing a `Wick rotation' [1], replacing real time with imag- quantum circuit. As a result, alternative methods are inary time connects Euclidean and Minkowski space [2], required to implement imaginary time evolution using a quantum and statistical mechanics [3], and static prob- quantum computer. lems to problems of dynamics [4]. In quantum mechan- Classically, we can simulate real (imaginary) time evo- ics, propagating a wavefunction in imaginary time en- lution of parametrised trial states by repeatedly solving ables: the study of finite temperature properties [5{7], the (Wick-rotated) Schr¨odingerequation over a small finding the ground state wavefunction and energy (such timestep, and updating the parameters for the next as in density matrix renormalisation group) [8{11], and timestep [8, 9, 11, 24{27]. This method has recently simulating real time dynamics (such as time dependent been extended to quantum computing, where it was used Hartree) [12, 13]. For a system with Hamiltonian, H, to simulate real time dynamics [28]. Closely related evolving in real time, t, the propagator is given by e−iHt. are the variational quantum eigensolver (VQE) [29{35] The corresponding propagator in imaginary time, τ = it, and the quantum approximate optimisation algorithm is given by e−Hτ ; a non-unitary operator. (QAOA) [36], which update the parameters using a clas- Using a classical computer, we can simulate imaginary sical optimisation routine, to find the minimum energy time evolution by evaluating the propagator and applying eigenvalue of a given Hamiltonian. As `hybrid quantum- it to the system wavefunction. There also exist various classical methods', these algorithms use a small quantum related classical methods, such as quantum Monte Carlo computer to carry out a classically intractable subrou- [14, 15] and density matrix renormalization group [16, 17] tine, and a classical computer to solve the higher level for solving different problems. However, because the di- problem. The quantum subroutine may only require a mension of the wavefunction grows exponentially with small number of qubits and a low depth circuit, present- the number of particles, classical simulation of many- ing a potential use for noisy intermediate-scale quantum body quantum systems is generally hard [18]. While ef- hardware [37]. arXiv:1804.03023v4 [quant-ph] 16 Sep 2019 ficient variational trial states have been developed for a In this paper, we propose a method to simulate number of applications [19], powerful trial wavefunctions imaginary time evolution on a quantum computer, using typically require classical computational resources which a hybrid quantum-classical variational algorithm. The scale exponentially with the system size [11]. proposed method thus combines the power of quantum Quantum computing can naturally and efficiently store computers to efficiently represent many-body quantum many-body quantum states, and hence is suitable for sim- states, with classical computers' ability to simulate ulating quantum systems [20]. We can map the system arbitrary (including unphysical) processes. We discuss Hamiltonian to a qubit Hamiltonian, and simulate real using this method to find the ground state energy of time evolution (as described by the Schr¨odingerequa- many-body quantum systems, and to solve optimisation tion) by realising the corresponding unitary evolution problems. We then numerically test the performance with a quantum circuit [21]. Using Trotterization [22], of our algorithm at finding the ground state energy of the real time propagator can be decomposed into a se- both the Hydrogen molecule (H2) and Lithium Hydride quence of single and two qubit gates [23]. The ability (LiH). We compare our results for LiH to those obtained 2 using the VQE with gradient descent. As our algorithm where kρk = Tr[pρρy] denotes the trace norm of a state. only requires a low depth circuit, it can be realised with By replacing j (τ)i with jφ(τ)i = jφ(θ~(τ))i, we effec- current and near-term quantum processors. tively project the desired imaginary time evolution onto the manifold of the ansatz space. The evolution of the pa- RESULTS rameters is obtained from the resulting differential equa- Variational imaginary time evolution. We focus on tion many-body systems that are described by Hamiltonians P X _ H = i λihi, with real coefficients, λi, and observ- Aijθj = Ci; (4) ables, hi, that are tensor products of Pauli matrices. j We assume that the number of terms in this Hamilto- nian scales polynomially with the system size, which is where true for many physical systems, such as molecules or the @ hφ(τ)j @ jφ(τ)i Fermi-Hubbard model. Given an initial state j i, the Aij = < ; normalised imaginary time evolution is defined by @θi @θj ! (5) X @ hφ(τ)j −Hτ C = < − λ h jφ(τ)i ; j (τ)i = A(τ)e j (0)i; (1) i α @θ α α i where A(τ) = 1=ph (0)j e−2Hτ j (0)i is a normalisation and hα and λα are the Pauli terms and coefficients of factor. In the instance that the initial state is a maxi- the Hamiltonian, as described above. The derivation of mally mixed state, the state at time τ is a thermal or Eq. (4) can be found in the Supplementary Materials. −Hτ −Hτ Gibbs state ρT =1/τ = e =Tr[e ], with temperature _ As both Aij and Ci are real, the derivative θj is also T = 1/τ. When the initial state has a non-zero overlap real, as required for parametrising a quantum circuit. with the ground state, the state at τ ! 1 is the ground Interestingly, although the average energy term Eτ state of H. Equivalently, the Wick rotated Schr¨odinger appears in Eq. (2), it does not appear in Eq. (4). This is equation is, because the ansatz applied maintains normalisation, as it is composed of unitary operators. @ j (τ)i = −(H − E ) j (τ)i ; (2) @τ τ Imaginary time evolution with quantum circuits. By where the term Eτ = h (τ)jHj (τ)i results from enforc- following a similar method to that introduced in ing normalisation. Even if j (τ)i can be represented by a Ref. [28], we can efficiently measure Aij and Ci us- quantum computer, the non-unitary imaginary time evo- ing a quantum computer. We assume that the deriva- lution cannot be naively mapped to a quantum circuit. tive of a unitary gate Ui(θi) can be expressed as P In our variational method, instead of directly encod- @Ui(θi)=@θi = k fk;iUi(θi)σk;i, with unitary op- ing the quantum state j (τ)i at time τ, we approxi- erator σk;i. The derivative of the trial state is P ~ ¯ ~ mate it using a parametrised trial state jφ(θ~(τ))i, with given by @ jφ(τ)i=@θi = k fk;iVk;i j0i, with Vk;i = ~ UN (θN ) :::Ui+1(θi+1)Ui(θi)σk;i :::U1(θ1). There are θ(τ) = (θ1(τ); θ2(τ); : : : ; θN (τ)). This stems from the in- tuition that the physically relevant states are contained typically only one or two terms resulting from each in a small subspace of the full Hilbert space [38]. The trial derivative. As an example, when Ui(θi) is a single qubit −iθiσz =2 state is referred to as the ansatz. In condensed matter rotation Rz(θi) = e , the derivative @Ui(θi)=@θi = −iθiσz =2 physics and computational chemistry, a wide variety of −i=2×σze . The coefficients Aij and Ci are given ans¨atzehave been proposed for both classical and quan- by tum variational methods [11, 20, 39, 40]. 0 1 Using a quantum circuit, we prepare the trial state, X A = < f ∗ f h0¯j V~ y V~ j0¯i ; jφ(θ~)i, by applying a sequence of parametrised unitary ij @ k;i l;j k;i l;j A k;l gates, V (θ~) = U (θ ) :::U (θ ) :::U (θ ) to our initial N N k k 1 1 0 1 (6) ~ ~ state, j0¯i. We express this as jφ(θ)i = V (θ) j0¯i and re- X C = < f ∗ λ h0¯j V~ y h V j0¯i : mark that V (θ~) is also referred to as the ansatz.
Recommended publications
  • On the Emergence of Time in Quantum Gravity
    Imperial/TP/98–99/23 On the Emergence of Time in Quantum Gravity1 J. Butterfield2 All Souls College Oxford OX1 4AL and C.J. Isham3 The Blackett Laboratory Imperial College of Science, Technology & Medicine South Kensington London SW7 2BZ 13 December 1998 Abstract We discuss from a philosophical perspective the way in which the normal concept of time might be said to ‘emerge’ in a quantum the- ory of gravity. After an introduction, we briefly discuss the notion of arXiv:gr-qc/9901024v1 8 Jan 1999 emergence, without regard to time (Section 2). We then introduce the search for a quantum theory of gravity (Section 3); and review some general interpretative issues about space, time and matter (Section 4). We then discuss the emergence of time in simple quantum ge- ometrodynamics, and in the Euclidean approach (Section 5). Section 6 concludes. 1To appear in The Arguments of Time, ed. J. Butterfield, Oxford University Press, 1999. 2email: [email protected]; jeremy.butterfi[email protected] 3email: [email protected] 1 Introduction The discovery of a satisfactory quantum theory of gravity has been widely regarded as the Holy Grail of theoretical physics for some forty years. In this essay, we will discuss a philosophical aspect of the search for such a theory that bears on our understanding of time: namely, the senses in which our standard ideas of time, and more generally spacetime, might be not fundamental to reality, but instead ‘emergent’ as an approximately valid concept on sufficiently large scales. In taking up this topic, our aim in part is to advertise to philosophers of time an unexplored area that promises to be fruitful.
    [Show full text]
  • A More Direct Representation for Complex Relativity
    A more direct representation for complex relativity D.H. Delphenich ∗∗∗ Physics Department, Bethany College, Lindsborg, KS 67456, USA Received 22 Nov 2006, revised 5 July 2007, accepted 5 July 2007 by F. W. Hehl Key words Complex relativity, pre-metric electromagnetism, almost-complex structures, 3- spinors. PACS 02.10.Xm, 02.40.Dr, 03.50.De, 04.50.+h An alternative to the representation of complex relativity by self-dual complex 2-forms on the spacetime manifold is presented by assuming that the bundle of real 2-forms is given an almost- complex structure. From this, one can define a complex orthogonal structure on the bundle of 2- forms, which results in a more direct representation of the complex orthogonal group in three complex dimensions. The geometrical foundations of general relativity are then presented in terms of the bundle of oriented complex orthogonal 3-frames on the bundle of 2-forms in a manner that essentially parallels their construction in terms of self-dual complex 2-forms. It is shown that one can still discuss the Debever-Penrose classification of the Riemannian curvature tensor in terms of the representation presented here. Contents 1 Introduction …………………………………………………………………………. 1 2 The complex orthogonal group …………………………………………………….. 3 3 The geometry of bivectors ………………………………………………………….. 4 3.1 Real vector space structure on A 2……………………………………………….. 5 3.2 Complex vector space structure on A 2…………………………………………... 8 3.3 Relationship to the formalism of self-dual bivectors……………………………. 12 4 Associated principal bundles for the vector bundle of 2-forms ………………….. 16 5 Levi-Civita connection on the bundle SO (3, 1)( M)………………………………… 19 6 Levi-Civita connection on the bundle SO (3; C)( M)……………………………….
    [Show full text]
  • On the Rational Relationship Between Heisenberg Principle and General
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by CERN Document Server On the Rational Relationship between Heisenberg Principle and General Relativity Xiao Jianhua Henan Polytechnic University, Jiaozuo City, Henan, P.R.C. 454000 Abstract: The research shows that the Heisenberg principle is the logic results of general relativity principle. If inertia coordinator system is used, the general relativity will logically be derived from the Heisenberg principle. The intrinsic relation between the quantum mechanics and general relativity is broken by introducing pure-imaginary time to explain the Lorentz transformation. Therefore, this research shows a way to establish an unified field theory of physics. PACS: 01.55.+b, 03.65.-w, 04.20.-q, 04.20.Ky Keywords: Heisenberg principle, general relativity, commoving coordinator, Riemannian geometry, gauge field 1. Introduction There are many documents to treat the relationship between the Newton mechanics and general relativity. There are also many documents to treat the relationship between the quantum mechanics and general relativity. For some researchers, the related research shows that an unified field theory be possible. For others, the actual efforts to establish an unified field theory for physics have shown that such an unified field theory is totally non-possible. The physics world is divided into three kingdoms. Hence, the title of this paper may make the reader think: See! Another nut! However, the unification of matter motion is the basic relieves for science researchers. The real problem is to find the way. This is the topic of this paper. The paper will firstly derive the Heisenberg principle from general relativity principle.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: the Possibility of Time Travel
    University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well Honors Capstone Projects Student Scholarship 2017 The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The Possibility of Time Travel Ramitha Rupasinghe University of Minnesota, Morris, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/honors Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Physics Commons Recommended Citation Rupasinghe, Ramitha, "The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The Possibility of Time Travel" (2017). Honors Capstone Projects. 1. https://digitalcommons.morris.umn.edu/honors/1 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Capstone Projects by an authorized administrator of University of Minnesota Morris Digital Well. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Philosophy and Physics of Time Travel: The possibility of time travel Ramitha Rupasinghe IS 4994H - Honors Capstone Project Defense Panel – Pieranna Garavaso, Michael Korth, James Togeas University of Minnesota, Morris Spring 2017 1. Introduction Time is mysterious. Philosophers and scientists have pondered the question of what time might be for centuries and yet till this day, we don’t know what it is. Everyone talks about time, in fact, it’s the most common noun per the Oxford Dictionary. It’s in everything from history to music to culture. Despite time’s mysterious nature there are a lot of things that we can discuss in a logical manner. Time travel on the other hand is even more mysterious.
    [Show full text]
  • The No-Boundary Proposal Via the Five-Dimensional Friedmann
    The no-boundary proposal via the five-dimensional Friedmann-Lemaˆıtre-Robertson-Walker model Peter K.F. Kuhfittig* and Vance D. Gladney* ∗Department of Mathematics, Milwaukee School of Engineering, Milwaukee, Wisconsin 53202-3109, USA Abstract Hawking’s proposal that the Universe has no temporal boundary and hence no be- ginning depends on the notion of imaginary time and is usually referred to as the no-boundary proposal. This paper discusses a simple alternative approach by means of the five-dimensional Friedmann-Lemaˆıtre-Robertson-Walker model. PAC numbers: 04.20.-q, 04.50.+h Keywords: no-boundary proposal, FLRW model 1 Introduction It is well known that Stephen Hawking introduced the no-boundary proposal using the concept of imaginary time, making up what is called Euclidean spacetime [1]. While ordi- nary time would still have a big-bang singularity, imaginary time avoids this singularity, implying that the Universe has no temporal boundary and hence no beginning. By elim- inating the singularity, the Universe becomes self-contained in the sense that one would arXiv:1510.07311v2 [gr-qc] 7 Jan 2016 not have to appeal to something outside the Universe to determine how the Universe began. Given that imaginary time is orthogonal to ordinary time, one could view imaginary time as an extra dimension. The existence of an extra dimension suggests a different start- ing point, the five-dimensional Friedmann-Lemaˆıtre-Robertson-Walker model (FLRW) [2]. This model produces a simple alternative version of the no-boundary proposal. 2 The FLRW model Let us recall the FLRW model in the usual four dimensions [3]: dr2 ds2 = dt2 + a2(t) + r2(dθ2 + sin2θdφ2) , (1) − 1 Kr2 − ∗kuhfi[email protected] 1 where a2(t) is a scale factor.
    [Show full text]
  • THE PHYSICS of TIMLESSNESS Dr
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 14, no. 2, 2018 THE PHYSICS OF TIMLESSNESS Dr. Varanasi Ramabrahmam ABSTRACT: The nature of time is yet to be fully grasped and finally agreed upon among physicists, philosophers, psychologists and scholars from various disciplines. Present paper takes clue from the known assumptions of time as - movement, change, becoming - and the nature of time will be thoroughly discussed. The real and unreal existences of time will be pointed out and presented. The complex number notation of nature of time will be put forward. Natural scientific systems and various cosmic processes will be identified as constructing physical form of time and the physical existence of time will be designed. The finite and infinite forms of physical time and classical, quantum and cosmic times will be delineated and their mathematical constructions and loci will be narrated. Thus the physics behind time-construction, time creation and time-measurement will be given. Based on these developments the physics of Timelessness will be developed and presented. KEYWORDS: physical time, psychological time, finite and infinite times, scalar and vector times, Classical, quantum and cosmic times, timelessness, movement, change, becoming INTRODUCTION: “Our present picture of physical reality, particularly in relation to the nature of time, is due for a grand shake-up—even greater, perhaps, than that which has already been provided by present-day relativity and quantum mechanics” [1]. Time is considered as www.cosmosandhistory.org 1 COSMOS AND HISTORY 2 one of the fundamental quantities in physics. Second, which is the duration of 9,192,631,770 cesium-133 atomic oscillations, is the unit.
    [Show full text]
  • Swinging in Imaginary Time More on the Not-So-Simple Pendulum
    GENERAL ARTICLE Swinging in Imaginary Time More on the Not-So-Simple Pendulum Cihan Saclioglu When the small angle approximation is not made, the exact solution of the simple pendulum is a Jacobian elliptic function with one real and one imaginary period. Far from being a physically meaningless mathematical curiosity, the second period represents the imaginary time the pendu- lum takes to swing upwards and tunnel through Cihan Saclioglu teaches the potential barrier in the semi-classical WKB physics at Sabanci approximation1 in quantum mechanics. The tun- University, Istanbul, neling here provides a simple illustration of simi- Turkey. His research lar phenomena in Yang{Mills theories describing interests include solutions of Yang–Mills, Einstein weak and strong interactions. and Seiberg–Witten equations and group 1. Introduction theoretical aspects of string theory. Consider a point mass m at the end of a rigid massless stick of length l. The acceleration due to gravity is g and the oscillatory motion is con¯ned to a vertical plane. Denoting the angular displacement of the stick from the 1When the exact quantum me- vertical by Á and taking the gravitational potential to chanical calculation of the tun- be zero at the bottom, the constant total energy E is neling probability for an arbitrary given by potential U(x) is impracticable, the Wentzel–Kramers–Brillouin 1 dÁ 2 approach, invented indepen- E = ml2 + mgl(1 cos Á) dently by all three authors in the 2 dt ¡ µ ¶ same year as the Schrödinger = mgl(1 cos Á0); (1) equation, provides an approxi- ¡ mate answer. 2 where Á0 is the maximum angle.
    [Show full text]
  • On Stability of Physical Systems in a Complex Plane
    ON STABILITY OF PHYSICAL SYSTEMS IN A COMPLEX PLANE V.V. Lyahov, V.M. Neshchadim 1. Introduction Complex numbers have fully come into common use in mathematics from the very moment of their discovery. Let's mention only one their property – the property of algebraic closedness of the field of complex numbers. The physics even now is in the stage of half-recognizing of complex numbers. On the one hand, the physics, using mathematical means, manipulates imaginaries; on the other hand, common sense says that all observable quantities should be associated with real numbers. Complex calculus should be only an auxiliary, mathematically formal tool. The line of reasoning of a modern physicist is as follows: “We live in the real world; therefore, all quantities should be featured by real numbers”. This statement seems to be completely natural without any additional argumentation. Such situation is an example of paradigm and is taken for granted by scientists. It may be said that the advancement of science confirms this thesis. But it seems that there are also opposite examples. Imaginary timeτ=i⋅ct is introduced into the relativity theory, and only in this form together with three spatial coordinates it forms a four-dimensional space-time. The fourth axis of space-time is an imaginary quantity. In the theory of relativity, on the one hand, it is always underlined that imaginary time is of conditional nature, but, on the other hand, it is also always noted that a deeply essential linkage between space and time was discovered for the first time. The basic object of the quantum mechanics - a complex-valued wave function is referred to as not being of any physical sense, but the square of this function has physical sense.
    [Show full text]
  • A Scenario for a Natural Origin of Our Universe Using a Mathematical Model Based on Established Physics and Cosmology
    A Scenario for a Natural Origin of Our Universe Using a Mathematical Model Based on Established Physics and Cosmology Victor J. Stenger Abstract: A mathematical model of the natural origin of our universe is presented. The model is based only on well-established physics. No claim is made that this model uniquely represents exactly how the universe came about. But the viability of a single model serves to refute any assertions that the universe cannot have come about by natural means. Why is there something rather than nothing? This question is often the last resort of the theist who seeks to argue for the existence of God from physics and cosmology and finds all his other arguments fail. Philosopher Bede Rundle calls it "philosophy's central, and most perplexing, question." His simple (but book-length) answer, "There has to be something."1 Clearly many conceptual problems are associated with this question. How do we define "nothing"? What are its properties? If it has properties, doesn't that make it something? The theist claims that God is the answer. But, then, why is there God rather than nothing? Assuming we can define "nothing," why should nothing be a more natural state of affairs than something? In fact, we can give a plausible scientific reason based on 2 our best current knowledge of physics and cosmology that something is more natural than nothing! It is commonly believed that the universe cannot have come about naturally. Although many authors writing at both the popular and academic levels have described various scenarios for a natural origin, usually based on the vague notion of "quantum fluctuations," even they admit that their ideas are speculative and surrender to the prevailing wisdom that the origin of our universe remains unexplained.2 What is it that science does when it "explains" some phenomenon? At least in the case of the physical sciences, it builds a mathematical model to describe the empirical data associated with the phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Thomism and the End of Infinity: Exploring the Infinite Regression of Causality with Theoretical Physics in 'Faith and Reaso
    Thomism and The End of Infinity: Exploring the Infinite Regression of Causality With Theoretical Physics In ‘Faith and Reason’ Saint Thomas Aquinas articulates five main arguments for the existence of God. His second argument proceeds as follows: things cause other things; these causes are in a series (or ordered); nothing can cause itself; there is no effect without cause; a series must have an initiating cause; therefore, there must be a first cause (which we have defined as ‘God’). Almost all of the aforementioned premises are either tautologically true or widely agreed upon. However, one of Aquinas’s assertions, monistic initiation, is the subject of much contention. A countertheory of infinite regression has gained popularity. In this context, an infinite regression would be an endless series of causality. Aquinas, on the other hand, believed that there must logically be one determinable start. He wrote, “Now if you eliminate a cause you eliminate its effects, so that you cannot have one last cause, nor an intermediate one, unless you have a first… One is therefore forced to suppose some first cause, to which everyone gives the name God.”1 Lexically, the two ideas seem to clash: after all, how can something both be never ending and have an end? However, monistic initiation and infinite regression need not be entirely mutually exclusive. A series could have an infinite regression that asymptotically approaches a distinct beginning. This paper explores how that could be possible. In Zeno’s famed paradox, a runner covers half his distance remaining to travel each day. Given eternity this runner would, technically, never complete the entirety of the journey.
    [Show full text]
  • Vacuum Decay in Real Time and Imaginary Time Formalisms
    PHYSICAL REVIEW D 100, 016011 (2019) Vacuum decay in real time and imaginary time formalisms † Mark P. Hertzberg1,2,* and Masaki Yamada1, 1Institute of Cosmology, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Tufts University, Medford, Massachusetts 02155, USA 2Department of Physics, Tokyo Institute of Technology, Ookayama, Meguro-ku, Tokyo 152-8551, Japan (Received 24 April 2019; published 18 July 2019) We analyze vacuum tunneling in quantum field theory in a general formalism by using the Wigner representation. In the standard instanton formalism, one usually approximates the initial false vacuum state by an eigenstate of the field operator, imposes Dirichlet boundary conditions on the initial field value, and evolves in imaginary time. This approach does not have an obvious physical interpretation. However, an alternative approach does have a physical interpretation: in quantum field theory, tunneling can happen via classical dynamics, seeded by initial quantum fluctuations in both the field and its momentum conjugate, which was recently implemented in Braden et al. [arXiv:1806.06069]. We show that the Wigner representation is a useful framework to calculate and understand the relationship between these two approaches. We find there are two, related, saddle point approximations for the path integral of the tunneling process: one corresponds to the instanton solution in imaginary time and the other one corresponds to classical dynamics from initial quantum fluctuations in real time. The classical approximation for the dynamics of the latter process is justified only in a system with many degrees of freedom, as can appear in field theory due to high occupancy of nucleated bubbles, while it is not justified in single particle quantum mechanics, as we explain.
    [Show full text]
  • Conjectures on Spacetime
    Conjectures on SpaceTime Alessandro Capurso – [email protected] – linkedin.com/in/capurso/ v190915 - Accepted as contribution at TM2019 INAF conference (Turin, Italy) Available online at indico.ict.inaf.it/event/751/contributions/5182/ Abstract Index The aim of this contribution is to propose new Abstract ................................................................................... 1 conjectures on SpaceTime variables and their description Index ........................................................................................ 1 through the concepts of network and coherent decoding (borrowed from Information Theory) and to offer a Variables and Geometry ....................................................... 2 possible wider perspective on SpaceTime fabric and Time, Memory and discreteness ..................................... 2 evolution. The model follows latest efforts to restore the Imaginary time and Information Space......................... 2 importance of Time in Physics (as Smolin in [1]). Perception of each Self ..................................................... 3 The critical step suggested is towards how we perceive AdS/CFT and Neural networks..................................... 4 SpaceTime dimensions: a 4D quantized expanding Living on the Surface ............................................................ 6 SpaceTime with 2 components for Information Space and Few bits of SpaceTime ....................................................... 6 2 orthogonal time-momentum components is considered. The time-dimensions
    [Show full text]