Homo Economicus Is Stochastically Patient
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Homo Economicus is Stochastically Patient Eric R. Ulm, Daniel Bauer, Justin Sydnor∗ July 2020 Abstract DeJarnette et al. (2020) introduce the concept of generalized expected discounted utility (GEDU) and show that it can explain the empirical finding that people tend to be risk-averse over time lotteries but violates an intuitively appealing property they call stochastic impatience. This note extends their analysis to the classical case of an agent that maximizes expected utility of future consumption subject to a budget constraint. We show that these classical agents ad- here to GEDU preferences with risk aversion over time lotteries and will often be stochastically patient. We argue that while stochastic impatience may be an intuitively appealing criterion when lottery payouts map directly to concurrent utility experiences, when agents can save, bor- row, and optimize, stochastic patience is a natural result. We present results of a simple survey experiment consistent with this view, finding that individuals exhibit stochastic impatience for small-scale monetary risks but stochastic patience for large-scale risks. JEL classification: D81; D90; C91. Keywords: Risk and Time Preferences, Stochastic Impatience, Expected Consumption Utility. Introduction DeJarnette et al. (2020) advance our understanding of consumers’ preferences across risk and time by analyzing time lotteries. As one of their key results, they show that under Expected Discounted Utility (EDU), individuals must be risk-seeking over time lotteries (RSTL). Yet their experimental results show that the majority of people are risk-averse over time lotteries (RATL). They show that a modification of EDU they call Generalized EDU (GEDU) can account for this risk aversion over time lotteries. However, they highlight that a necessary sacrifice for overcoming RSTL is to accept that individuals violate an intuitively appealing property they call stochastic impatience, ∗Ulm: School of Economics and Finance, Victoria University of Wellington, 23 Lambton Quay Wellington, NZ, [email protected]. Bauer/Sydnor: Department of Risk and Insurance, University of Wisconsin-Madison, 975 Uni- versity Avenue, Madison, WI 53706, USA, [email protected]/[email protected]. 1 HOMO ECONOMICUS IS STOCHASTICALLY PATIENT 2 the “risky counterpart to the standard notion of Impatience” that individuals “should [behave] in accordance with” (p. 621). They show that this incompatibility plagues a broad class of models, including many forms of non-expected utility and time discounting. Ultimately, they conclude that their results call into question some of the foundations of the models that are core to many applied economics insights. In the EDU framework and related models that are the focus of DeJarnette et al. (2020), lottery payouts at a moment in time map directly to utility realizations at that time. This framework is likely the relevant approach for situations where risk and time delays are over direct consump- tion experiences that cannot be reallocated or reoptimized over time. It may also be the right as if approximation for psychological reactions to small dollar rewards at different points in time. However, in many economic applications the dominant modeling approach is intertemporal maxi- mization of consumption utility subject to a budget constraint so that it is probably inappropriate to consider EDU as the “standard model in economics” as DeJarnette et al. claim (Frederick, Loewen- stein, and O’donoghue, 2002; Cohen el al., 2020, and references therein). In models of intertem- poral consumption utility, individuals reoptimize consumption streams in reaction to stochastic monetary realizations and this has important implications for how to think about reactions to risky lotteries over time. In this note we show that when extending the DeJarnette et al. analysis to this classical case of an agent who maximizes utility over consumption subject to an intertemporal budget constraint, there is nothing problematic about the inconsistency between risk aversion over time lotteries and stochastic impatience. We show theoretically that agents maximizing intertemporal utility of con- sumption will adhere to DeJarnette et al.’s Generalized EDU preferences in the context they con- sider, albeit with specific parameter choices. They will (thus) often display risk aversion over time lotteries. Moreover, these classical agents will – and should – violate stochastic impatience as long as they are sufficiently risk-averse. Stochastic patience, rather than stochastic impatience, is the natural result in this classical model of intertemporally maximized consumption utility. To provide intuition for our arguments, it is helpful to revisit one of the examples DeJarnette et al. present to showcase stochastic impatience (p. 627): • Lottery A: (50-50) $100 today or $20 in one month. • Lottery B: (50-50) $20 today or $100 in one month. Stochastic impatience implies that agents prefer the larger prize earlier, so that Lottery A will be preferred. This seems to an intuitively appealing criterion when the monetary prizes map directly to utility received at that time. If I can have either utility of $100 or $20 and that utility will arise either today or in one month, preferring the higher utility earlier is intuitive. HOMO ECONOMICUS IS STOCHASTICALLY PATIENT 3 However, for an agent that is optimizing consumption utility over time, when they learn which monetary prize they are receiving, they will smooth consumption and allocate part of that prize to both time periods. Prizes received later have a lower present-discounted value than prizes received earlier and result in lower utility in both periods. That reduction in utility from the later receipt of the prize has a bigger effect when the overall level of consumption is lower. As a result, a sufficiently risk-averse person anticipating smoothing consumption will not prefer lotteries where low wealth positively correlates with later receipt of the wealth. Instead they prefer diversification, where better wealth realizations correlate with more delay.1 That is, they will be stochastically patient. This intuition can be made more transparent by recasting DeJarnette et al.’s example into a naturalistic situation with larger stakes and income received over time, where consumption utility maximization is likely more intuitive. Consider the following example where a currently unem- ployed person (e.g., a new college graduate) has two potential jobs they might land with very different annual salaries and the potential for a delayed start: • Lottery A’: (50-50) $100,000 starting right away or $50,000 with 6 months wait to start. • Lottery B’: (50-50) $50,000 starting right away or $100,000 with 6 months wait to start. We suspect that for most people in this formulation, Lottery B’ – the stochastically patient option – is more naturally appealing.2 To test that intuition, we conducted a simple pre-registered survey experiment on Amazon’s Mechanical Turk platform with 162 participants. We randomized participants to choose between either Lotteries A/B (DeJarnette et al.’s small-dollar choice) or Lotteries A’/B’ (our large-stakes choice), with both being hypothetical choices. Consistent with DeJarnette et al.’s conjecture that stochastic impatience is an intuitive property for their lottery, 68 percent of subjects made the stochastically impatient choice of Lottery A over Lottery B. However, in the larger-stakes option, the majority of subjects (57 percent) instead made the stochastically patient choice of Lottery B’ over Lottery A’. Overall, the results of our theoretical analysis and this supplementary experiment suggest that violations of stochastic impatience are natural in environments where people are likely to optimize in response to stochastic realizations. More generally, these results call for nuance in interpreting 1We show that the intuition for this result can be illustrated using familiar insights from financial asset pricing theory by decomposing DeJarnette et al.’s stochastic impatience lotteries into an identical background lottery and differing supplemental lotteries. 2The optimal consumption streams will diverge more between realizations in Lottery A’ than Lottery B’: Note that the two lotteries are equivalent after the first year and therefore someone who is smoothing consumption might focus on the total income differences over the first year; Lottery A’ involves a total of either $100,000 or $25,000 in income during the first year while Lottery B’ guarantees a certain level of $50,000 income during the first year. HOMO ECONOMICUS IS STOCHASTICALLY PATIENT 4 the implications of DeJarnette et al. (2020). Their analysis suggests the need to reconsider the EDU model and its close cousins. Yet there is little reason to believe these concerns are an issue for economic analysis in environments when people save and optimize, where models of intertemporal consumption utility maximization subject to budget constraints are the norm. In order to keep the discussion that follows transparent and accessible, we first describe our analysis of DeJarnette et al.’s simple lotteries in a setting with two pay-out days, simple preferences with a constant relative risk aversion/elasticity of intertemporal substitution, and their motivating example in favor of stochastic impatience (p. 627). However, we also provide results that document the general validity of our main points (with proofs relegated to an online appendix). Utility of Intertemporally Optimized Consumption and GEDU