Summer 2017 Astron 9 Week 5 Final Version

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Summer 2017 Astron 9 Week 5 Final Version RELATIVITY OF SPACE AND TIME IN POPULAR SCIENCE RICHARD ANANTUA PREDESTINATION (MON JUL 31) REVIEW OF JUL 24, 26 & 28 • Flying atomic clocks, muon decay, light bending around stars and gravitational waves provide experimental confirmation of relativity • In 1919, Einstein’s prediction for the deflection of starlight was confirmed by • The 1971 Hafele-Keating experiment confirmed • The 1977 CERN muon experiment confirmed • In 2016 LIGO confirmed the existence of REVIEW OF JUL 24, 26 & 28 • Flying atomic clocks, muon decay, light bending around stars and gravitational waves provide experimental confirmation of relativity • In 1919, Einstein’s prediction for the deflection of starlight was confirmed by Sir Arthur Eddington • The 1971 Hafele-Keating experiment confirmed motional and gravitational time dilation • The 1977 CERN muon experiment confirmed motional time dilation • In 2016 LIGO confirmed the existence of gravitational waves TIME TRAVEL IN RELATIVITY • Methods of time travel theoretically possible in relativity are • (Apparently) faster than light travel – window into the past? • Closed timelike curved • (Apparent) paradoxes with time travel • Kill your grandfather – past time travel may alter seemingly necessary conditions for the future time traveler to have started the journey • Predestination - apparent cause of past event is in the future SPECIAL RELATIVISTIC VELOCITY ADDITION • In special relativity, no object or information can travel faster than light, a fact reflected in the relativistic law of composition of velocities v &v vAB v = $% %' A !" v$%v%' (& * ) vBC B C • vAB is the (1D) velocity of A with respect to B • vBC is the (1D) velocity of B with respect to C POP QUIZ - FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL • A spaceship traveling at v>c is returning from a moving planet (L0 away right before the journey). Which arrives at the Earth observer earlier: information from later times or information from earlier times? Is there a speed at which the ship travels into the past? t=t t=t3 2 t=t1 v>c vPE L0 POP QUIZ - FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL • For the return trip, light emitted from later times arrives earlier at the Earth observer, so the observer sees the spaceship’s travel as a movie running backwards. t=t t=t3 2 t=t1 v>c vPE L0 POP QUIZ - FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL • For the return trip, light emitted from later times arrives earlier at the Earth observer, so the observer sees the spaceship’s travel as a movie running backwards. If the speed increases to make the total trip time negative, ships may arrive before a ship is launched. vSE vPE L0 (Δt)/0/=? +? POP QUIZ - FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL • For the return trip, light emitted from later times arrives earlier at the Earth observer, so the observer sees the spaceship’s travel as a movie running backwards. If the speed increases to make the total trip time negative, ships may arrive before a ship is launched. |vSP|=|vSE| v69 − v97 v67 = v v 1 − 69 97 c< vPE L0 � � + v 4 � 4 97 v − v (Δt) = 4 + 67 97 , v = v ≡ v /0/ v − v v69 − v97 69 67 67 97 v v 1 − 69 97 c< POP QUIZ - FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL • For the return trip, light emitted from later times arrives earlier at the Earth observer, so the observer sees the spaceship’s travel as a movie running backwards. If the speed increases to make the total trip time negative, ships may arrive before a ship is launched. -vSE vPE L0 � � + v 4 � 4 97 v − v (Δt) = 4 + 67 97 , v = v ≡ v /0/ v − v v69 − v97 69 67 67 97 v v 1 − 69 97 c< �< A �< ⟹ v = + � < − 1 v97 v97 REVIEW OF JUL 31 • Exercise: Faster-than-light travel has unexpected theoretical implications: • If a spaceship makes a faster-than-light journey to a distant planet and back, what appears different about the outbound and return journeys? • If the spaceship reverses instantly at the planet, what appears to happen? How could mass be conserved? REVIEW OF JUL 31 • Exercise: Faster-than-light travel has unexpected theoretical implications: • If a spaceship makes a faster-than-light journey to a distant planet and back, what appears different about the outbound and return journeys? • The outbound journey appears to run forward while the return journey appears to run backwards in time • If the spaceship reverses instantly at the planet, what appears to happen? How could mass be conserved? • Image pair annihilation: After the spaceship arrives on Earth, an image of the spaceship appears to go backwards until it reaches the outbound spaceship’s image at the planet, then both images disappear. Mass could be conserved if the backwards-moving ship is made of antimatter FASTER THAN LIGHT TRAVEL - WARPDRIVE SPACETIME • In 1994, Miguel Alcubierre proposed a partially curved spacetime in which long distance travel may appear faster than light travel according to observers in the flat portion of spacetime http://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/0264- 9381/11/5/001/meta;jsessionid=44D4E5916BC9330CA8BBC73C36457298.c2.iopscience.cld.iop.org . WARPDRIVE SPACETIME (GROUP ACTIVITY) NO • Consider the metric ��< = −�<��< + (�� − � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) v � )< + ��< + ��< , v (�) = P D D D NQ �D(�) �⃗D(�) = 0 where is the 0 worldline of a spaceship moving right and f is a positive function with f(0)=1, f(rs>R)=0 0 • Show that some future lightcones on an x -x-plane slice have slopes < 1; show vs>c for some portion of the journey. WARPDRIVE SPACETIME (GROUP ACTIVITY) NO • Consider the metric ��< = −�<��< + (�� − � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) v � )< + ��< + ��< , v (�) = P D D D NQ �D(�) �⃗D(�) = 0 where is the 0 worldline of a spaceship moving right and f is a positive function with f(0)=1, f(rs>R)=0 0 • Show that some future lightcones on an x -x-plane slice have slopes < 1; show vs>c for some portion of the journey. < < < < 0 = �� = −� �� + (�� − � �⃗ − �⃗D � vD � ) 4 < < ⟹ �� = �� − � �⃗ − �⃗D(�) vD � �� < �� v � ⟹ 1 = − � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) D ��4 D � �� v � ⟹ ±1 = − � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) D ��4 D � NOS ( ⟹ = W X NQ ±(&T U⃗VU⃗ (Q) P P ) �� If 0 < � �⃗ − �⃗ � < 1, and the ship moves right � > 0 D �� ��4 then <1 for the rightmost portion of the lightcone �� If 0 < � �⃗ − �⃗D � < 1, �� + � �� �� Warpdrive spacetime for smooth positive function = ±� + � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) v � ⟹ v � = > � j D D D �⃗ − �⃗D(�) . Confer Hartle p. 144. �� � �⃗ − �⃗D � � �⃗ − �⃗ (�) = 1 − D �j MINKOWSKI METRIC IN SPHERICAL COORDINATES • Minkowski flat space is empty, so it can be equally well represented in coordinates emphasizing spherical symmetry instead of planar symmetry Cartesian Coordinates Spherical Coordinates < no < < < < < < < < < < < < < < �� = �no�� = −� �� + �� + �� + �� �� = −� �� + �� + � �� + � sin � �� • Exercise: What are the lengths of Arc 1 and Arc 2 if the sphere has radius r+dr and �, �, d� and d� are defined as in the diagram? �̂ Arc 1dr � Arc 2 MINKOWSKI METRIC IN SPHERICAL COORDINATES • Minkowski flat space is empty, so it can be equally well represented in coordinates emphasizing spherical symmetry instead of planar symmetry Cartesian Coordinates Spherical Coordinates < no < < < < < < < < < < < < < < �� = �no�� = −� �� + �� + �� + �� �� = −� �� + �� + � �� + � sin � �� • Exercise: What are the lengths of Arc 1 and Arc 2 if the sphere has radius r+dr and �, �, d� and d� are defined as in the diagram? �̂ Arc 1dr � Arc 1: ��� Arc 2: � sin � �� Arc 2 SCHWARZSCHILD GEOMETRY • Schwarzschild line element for geometry around stationary black hole <t <t V( stz{ ��2= −�< 1 − ��< + 1 − ��< + �<(��< + ���<���<) � = U U v* <st • The metric has a coordinate singularity at r=2M= %u v* KERR GEOMETRY st � = z{ • Kerr metric v* <tU jt}U D~•*€ |* ��2=−�< 1 − ��< − ���� + ��< + < < < < |* |* • � ≡ �/�, � ≡ � + � cos �, < < <tU}* D~•*€ ∆≡ � − 2�� + � �<��< + (�< + �< + ) ���<���< |* • For a Kerr (rotating) black hole • The (outer) event horizon is slightly within the Schwarzschild radius • The ergosphere drags spacetime so fast all light appears to co-rotate with the black hole • The inner horizon is a 2-way horizon ROBERTSON-WALKER METRICS • The Universe is observed, to a large extent, to be spatially isotropic and homogeneous ��2=−�<��< + �<(�)��< where the scale factor sets the separation of points in the Universe at different times�(�) FLAT ROBERTSON-WALKER SPACE METRIC • The RW (homogeneous, isotropic) metric in flat 3D space is ��2=−�<��< + �<(�)(��< + ��< + ��<) which in polar coordinates � = � sin � cos � �� =? ‡� = � sin � sin � ⟹ ‡�� =? � = � cos � �� =? takes the form ??? FLAT ROBERTSON-WALKER SPACE METRIC • The RW (homogeneous, isotropic) metric in flat 3D space is ��2=−�<��< + �<(�)(��< + ��< + ��<) which in polar coordinates � = � sin � cos � �� = � cos � cos � �� − � sin � sin � �� + cos � cos � �� ‡� = � sin � sin � ⟹ ˆ �� = � cos � sin � �� + � sin � cos � �� + sin � sin � �� � = � cos � �� = −� sin � �� + cos � �� takes the form ��2=−�<��< + �<(�)(��< + �<(��< + sin<���<)) ROBERTSON-WALKER METRIC IN CURVED SPACES • Curved 3D spaces can be envisioned by embedding surfaced in higher dimensional space. Take the analogues of the sphere and hyperboloid living in 3-space to their generalizations to 4-space (r �� �-space) • For the unit 3-sphere in a positively curved isotropic, homogeneous space: ��2 = −�<��< + �<(�) ��< + sin< �( d�< + sin< � ��<) 0 ≤ �, � ≤ �, 0 ≤ � ≤ 2� • For negatively curved isotropic, homogeneous 3-space: 0 ≤ � ≤ �, 0 ≤ � ≤ 2� ��2 = −�<��< + �<(�) ��< + sinh< �( d�< + sin< � ��<) 0 ≤ � ≤ ∞ ROBERTSON-WALKER METRICS • Exercise: Show that for (sin � , 1) (�, �) = ˆ (�, 0) (sinh � , −1) the RW metrics ��2 = −�<��< + �<(�) ��< + sin< �( d�< + sin< � ��<) ��2 = −�<��< + �<(�)(��< + �<(��< + sin<���<)) ��2 = −�<��< + �<(�) ��< + sinh<
Recommended publications
  • Closed Timelike Curves Make Quantum and Classical Computing Equivalent
    Closed Timelike Curves Make Quantum and Classical Computing Equivalent Scott Aaronson∗ John Watrous† MIT University of Waterloo Abstract While closed timelike curves (CTCs) are not known to exist, studying their consequences has led to nontrivial insights in general relativity, quantum information, and other areas. In this paper we show that if CTCs existed, then quantum computers would be no more powerful than classical computers: both would have the (extremely large) power of the complexity class PSPACE, consisting of all problems solvable by a conventional computer using a polynomial amount of memory. This solves an open problem proposed by one of us in 2005, and gives an essentially complete understanding of computational complexity in the presence of CTCs. Following the work of Deutsch, we treat a CTC as simply a region of spacetime where a “causal consistency” condition is imposed, meaning that Nature has to produce a (probabilistic or quantum) fixed-point of some evolution operator. Our conclusion is then a consequence of the following theorem: given any quantum circuit (not necessarily unitary), a fixed-point of the circuit can be (implicitly) computed in polynomial space. This theorem might have independent applications in quantum information. 1 Introduction The possibility of closed timelike curves (CTCs) within general relativity and quantum gravity theories has been studied for almost a century [11, 15, 13]. A different line of research has sought to understand the implications of CTCs, supposing they existed, for quantum mechanics, computation, and information [9, 8, 5]. In this paper we contribute to the latter topic, by giving the first complete characterization of the computational power of CTCs.
    [Show full text]
  • Light Rays, Singularities, and All That
    Light Rays, Singularities, and All That Edward Witten School of Natural Sciences, Institute for Advanced Study Einstein Drive, Princeton, NJ 08540 USA Abstract This article is an introduction to causal properties of General Relativity. Topics include the Raychaudhuri equation, singularity theorems of Penrose and Hawking, the black hole area theorem, topological censorship, and the Gao-Wald theorem. The article is based on lectures at the 2018 summer program Prospects in Theoretical Physics at the Institute for Advanced Study, and also at the 2020 New Zealand Mathematical Research Institute summer school in Nelson, New Zealand. Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 Causal Paths 4 3 Globally Hyperbolic Spacetimes 11 3.1 Definition . 11 3.2 Some Properties of Globally Hyperbolic Spacetimes . 15 3.3 More On Compactness . 18 3.4 Cauchy Horizons . 21 3.5 Causality Conditions . 23 3.6 Maximal Extensions . 24 4 Geodesics and Focal Points 25 4.1 The Riemannian Case . 25 4.2 Lorentz Signature Analog . 28 4.3 Raychaudhuri’s Equation . 31 4.4 Hawking’s Big Bang Singularity Theorem . 35 5 Null Geodesics and Penrose’s Theorem 37 5.1 Promptness . 37 5.2 Promptness And Focal Points . 40 5.3 More On The Boundary Of The Future . 46 1 5.4 The Null Raychaudhuri Equation . 47 5.5 Trapped Surfaces . 52 5.6 Penrose’s Theorem . 54 6 Black Holes 58 6.1 Cosmic Censorship . 58 6.2 The Black Hole Region . 60 6.3 The Horizon And Its Generators . 63 7 Some Additional Topics 66 7.1 Topological Censorship . 67 7.2 The Averaged Null Energy Condition .
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Fluctuations and Thermodynamic Processes in The
    Quantum fluctuations and thermodynamic processes in the presence of closed timelike curves by Tsunefumi Tanaka A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Physics Montana State University © Copyright by Tsunefumi Tanaka (1997) Abstract: A closed timelike curve (CTC) is a closed loop in spacetime whose tangent vector is everywhere timelike. A spacetime which contains CTC’s will allow time travel. One of these spacetimes is Grant space. It can be constructed from Minkowski space by imposing periodic boundary conditions in spatial directions and making the boundaries move toward each other. If Hawking’s chronology protection conjecture is correct, there must be a physical mechanism preventing the formation of CTC’s. Currently the most promising candidate for the chronology protection mechanism is the back reaction of the metric to quantum vacuum fluctuations. In this thesis the quantum fluctuations for a massive scalar field, a self-interacting field, and for a field at nonzero temperature are calculated in Grant space. The stress-energy tensor is found to remain finite everywhere in Grant space for the massive scalar field with sufficiently large field mass. Otherwise it diverges on chronology horizons like the stress-energy tensor for a massless scalar field. If CTC’s exist they will have profound effects on physical processes. Causality can be protected even in the presence of CTC’s if the self-consistency condition is imposed on all processes. Simple classical thermodynamic processes of a box filled with ideal gas in the presence of CTC’s are studied. If a system of boxes is closed, its state does not change as it travels through a region of spacetime with CTC’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmic String Lensing and Closed Timelike Curves
    PHYSICAL REVIEW D 72, 043532 (2005) Cosmic string lensing and closed timelike curves Benjamin Shlaer* and S.-H. Henry Tye† Laboratory for Elementary Particle Physics, Cornell University, Ithaca, New York 14853, USA (Received 3 March 2005; revised manuscript received 21 July 2005; published 31 August 2005) In an analysis of the gravitational lensing by two relativistic cosmic strings, we argue that the formation of closed timelike curves proposed by Gott is unstable in the presence of particles (e.g. the cosmic microwave background radiation). Because of the attractorlike behavior of the closed timelike curve, we argue that this instability is very generic. A single graviton or photon in the vicinity, no matter how soft, is sufficient to bend the strings and prevent the formation of closed timelike curves. We also show that the gravitational lensing due to a moving cosmic string is enhanced by its motion, not suppressed. DOI: 10.1103/PhysRevD.72.043532 PACS numbers: 98.80.Cq, 04.20.Gz, 04.60.Kz, 11.27.+d I. INTRODUCTION strings in the sense opposite to their motion becomes a CTC. This is sometimes called the Gott spacetime or Gott Although cosmic strings as the seed of structure forma- time machine. tion [1] has been ruled out by observations, their presence Although there is no proof that a time machine cannot at a lower level is still possible. Indeed, cosmic strings are exist in our world [13], their puzzling causal nature leads generically present in brane inflation in superstring theory, many physicists to believe that CTCs cannot be formed. and their properties are close to, but within all observatio- This skepticism has been encoded in Hawking’s chronol- nal bounds [2–7].
    [Show full text]
  • Closed Timelike Curves Via Postselection: Theory and Experimental Test of Consistency
    Closed Timelike Curves via Postselection: Theory and Experimental Test of Consistency The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Lloyd, Seth, et al. "Closed Timelike Curves via Postselection: Theory and Experimental Test of Consistency." American Physical Society, 2011, 106:4, © 2011 The American Physical Society. As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.106.040403 Publisher American Physical Society Version Final published version Citable link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/63096 Terms of Use Article is made available in accordance with the publisher's policy and may be subject to US copyright law. Please refer to the publisher's site for terms of use. week ending PRL 106, 040403 (2011) PHYSICAL REVIEW LETTERS 28 JANUARY 2011 Closed Timelike Curves via Postselection: Theory and Experimental Test of Consistency Seth Lloyd,1 Lorenzo Maccone,1 Raul Garcia-Patron,1 Vittorio Giovannetti,2 Yutaka Shikano,1,3 Stefano Pirandola,1 Lee A. Rozema,4 Ardavan Darabi,4 Yasaman Soudagar,4 Lynden K. Shalm,4 and Aephraim M. Steinberg4 1xQIT, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 77 Massachusetts Avenue, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139-4307, USA 2NEST-CNR-INFM & Scuola Normale Superiore, Piazza dei Cavalieri 7, I-56126, Pisa, Italy 3Department of Physics, Tokyo Institute of Technology, 2-12-1 Oh-Okayama, Meguro, Tokyo, 152-8551, Japan 4CQIQC, IOS, Department of Physics, University of Toronto, Canada M5S 1A7 (Received 12 May 2010; revised manuscript received 22 November 2010; published 27 January 2011) Closed timelike curves (CTCs) are trajectories in spacetime that effectively travel backwards in time: a test particle following a CTC can interact with its former self in the past.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Violation and Singularities
    TIT/HEP-302/COSMO-59 October, 1995 Causality violation and singularities Kengo Maeda 1 and Akihiro Ishibashi 2 Department of Physics, Tokyo Institute of Technology, Oh-Okayama Meguro-ku, Tokyo 152, Japan ABSTRACT We show that singularities necessarily occur when a boundary of causality violating set exists in a space-time under the physically suitable assumptions except the global causality condition in the Hawking-Penrose singularity theo- rems. Instead of the global causality condition, we impose some restrictions on the causality violating sets to show the occurrence of singularities. 1 Introduction Space-time singularities have been discussed for a long time in general relativity. In 1970, Hawking and Penrose[1] showed that singularities, which mean causal arXiv:gr-qc/9606075v1 27 Jun 1996 geodesic incompleteness, could occur in a space-time under seemingly reasonable conditions in classical gravity. Their singularity theorem has an important impli- cation that our universe has an initial singularity if we do not consider quantum effects. However, this theorem is physically unsatisfactory in the sense that the causality requirement everywhere in a space-time seems too restrictive. We can only experience local events and there is no guarantee that the causality holds in the entire universe. As is well known, Kerr type black holes have causality violating sets if the space-time is maximally extended. Therefore, it will be im- portant to investigate occurrence of singularities in a space-time in which the global causality condition is violated. There are some works on a causality violation concerned with the occurrence of singularity. Tipler[2,3] showed that any attempt to evolve closed timelike curves from an initial regular Cauchy data would cause singularities to form in a 1e-mail:[email protected] 2e-mail:[email protected] 1 space-time.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:0710.4474V1 [Gr-Qc] 24 Oct 2007 I.“Apdie Pctmsadspruia Travel Superluminal and Spacetimes Drive” “Warp III
    Exotic solutions in General Relativity: Traversable wormholes and “warp drive” spacetimes Francisco S. N. Lobo∗ Centro de Astronomia e Astrof´ısica da Universidade de Lisboa, Campo Grande, Ed. C8 1749-016 Lisboa, Portugal and Institute of Gravitation & Cosmology, University of Portsmouth, Portsmouth PO1 2EG, UK (Dated: February 2, 2008) The General Theory of Relativity has been an extremely successful theory, with a well established experimental footing, at least for weak gravitational fields. Its predictions range from the existence of black holes, gravitational radiation to the cosmological models, predicting a primordial beginning, namely the big-bang. All these solutions have been obtained by first considering a plausible distri- bution of matter, i.e., a plausible stress-energy tensor, and through the Einstein field equation, the spacetime metric of the geometry is determined. However, one may solve the Einstein field equa- tion in the reverse direction, namely, one first considers an interesting and exotic spacetime metric, then finds the matter source responsible for the respective geometry. In this manner, it was found that some of these solutions possess a peculiar property, namely “exotic matter,” involving a stress- energy tensor that violates the null energy condition. These geometries also allow closed timelike curves, with the respective causality violations. Another interesting feature of these spacetimes is that they allow “effective” superluminal travel, although, locally, the speed of light is not surpassed. These solutions are primarily useful as “gedanken-experiments” and as a theoretician’s probe of the foundations of general relativity, and include traversable wormholes and superluminal “warp drive” spacetimes. Thus, one may be tempted to denote these geometries as “exotic” solutions of the Einstein field equation, as they violate the energy conditions and generate closed timelike curves.
    [Show full text]
  • Computers with Closed Timelike Curves Can Solve Hard Problems
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by CERN Document Server Computers with closed timelike curves can solve hard problems Todd A. Brun Institute for Advanced Study, Einstein Drive, Princeton, NJ 08540 September 19, 2002 Abstract A computer which has access to a closed timelike curve, and can thereby send the results of calculations into its own past, can ex- ploit this to solve difficult computational problems efficiently. I give a specific demonstration of this for the problem of factoring large num- bers, and argue that a similar approach can solve NP-complete and PSPACE-complete problems. I discuss the potential impact of quan- tum effects on this result. Keywords: Closed timelike curves, Computation, Algorithms 1 Computing with closed timelike curves The recent success in the field of quantum computation shows how the power of computation can be affected by the particular choice of physical model for a computer. By assuming a computer which operates according to the laws of quantum mechanics, Peter Shor was able to devise an algorithm to factor large numbers exponentially more efficiently than the best known classical algorithm [1]. This success leads one to ask: are there other physical models for com- putation which will also result in much more powerful algorithms? As long as one is speculating, one might as well speculate wildly; so let us consider 1 computers with access to closed timelike curves (CTCs), which are thereby able to send information (such as the results of calculations) into their own past light cones [2, 3]. I argue that such computers would be able to solve computationally dif- ficult problems with amazing (indeed, almost magical) efficiency.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum Physics of Chronology Protection
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CERN Document Server The quantum physics of chronology protection Matt Visser Physics Department, Washington University, Saint Louis, Missouri 63130-4899, USA. 2 April 2002; LATEX-ed April 8, 2002 Abstract: This is a brief survey of the current status of Stephen Hawking’s “chronol- ogy protection conjecture”. That is: “Why does nature abhor a time machine?” I’ll discuss a few examples of spacetimes containing “time ma- chines” (closed causal curves), the sorts of peculiarities that arise, and the reactions of the physics community. While pointing out other possibilities, this article concentrates on the possibility of “chronology protection”. As Stephen puts it: It seems that there is a Chronology Protection Agency which prevents the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians. To appear in: The future of theoretical physics and cosmology; Proceedings of the conference held in honour of Stephen Hawking on the occasion of his 60’th birthday. (Cambridge, 7–10 January 2002.) E-mail: [email protected] Homepage: http://www.physics.wustl.edu/~visser Archive: gr-qc/0204022 Permanent address after 1 July 2002: School of Mathematics and Computer Science, Victoria University, PO Box 600, Wellington, New Zealand. [email protected] 1 The quantum physics of chronology protection Simply put, chronology protection is the assertion that nature abhors a time machine. In the words of Stephen Hawking [1]: It seems that there is a Chronology Protection Agency which prevents the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum Physics of Chronology Protection
    The quantum physics of chronology protection Matt Visser Physics Department, Washington University, Saint Louis, Missouri 63130-4899, USA. 2 April 2002; Additional references 17 April 2002; LATEX-ed February 3, 2008 Abstract: This is a brief survey of the current status of Stephen Hawking’s “chronol- ogy protection conjecture”. That is: “Why does nature abhor a time machine?” I’ll discuss a few examples of spacetimes containing “time ma- chines” (closed causal curves), the sorts of peculiarities that arise, and the reactions of the physics community. While pointing out other possibilities, this article concentrates on the possibility of “chronology protection”. As Stephen puts it: It seems that there is a Chronology Protection Agency which prevents the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians. To appear in: The future of theoretical physics and cosmology; Proceedings of the conference held in honour of Stephen Hawking on the occasion of his 60’th birthday. (Cambridge, 7–10 January 2002.) arXiv:gr-qc/0204022v2 17 Apr 2002 E-mail: [email protected] Homepage: http://www.physics.wustl.edu/˜visser Archive: gr-qc/0204022 Permanent address after 1 July 2002: School of Mathematics and Computer Science, Victoria University, PO Box 600, Wellington, New Zealand. [email protected] 1 The quantum physics of chronology protection Simply put, chronology protection is the assertion that nature abhors a time machine. In the words of Stephen Hawking [1]: It seems that there is a Chronology Protection Agency which prevents the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Closed Timelike Curves in Exact Solutions
    Uppsala University Department of Physics and Astronomy Division of Theoretical Physics Closed Timelike Curves in Exact Solutions Bachelor Degree Project Supervisor: Konstantina Polydorou Author: Timea Vitos Subject reader: Ulf Danielsson June 16, 2017 Abstract This project aims to study general relativity to the extent to understand the occurrence and behaviors of closed timelike curves (CTCs) in several exact solutions of Einstein’s eld equations. The rotating black hole solution, the Gödel universe and the cosmic string solutions are studied in detail to show how CTCs arise in these spacetimes. The chronology-violationing paradoxes and other unphysical aspects of CTCs are discussed. The spacetimes where CTCs arise possess properties which are argumented to be unphysical, such as lack of asymptotic atness and being innite models. With quantum computational networks it is possible to resolve the paradoxes which CTCs evoke. With all these attempts of resolving CTCs, our conclusion is that CTCs exist quantum mechanically, but there is a mechanism which inhibits them to be detected classically. Sammanfattning Detta projekt åsyftar att studera allmän relativitet i den grad att kunna förstå uppkomsten och före- teelsen av tidsliknande slutna kurvor (CTC) i några exakta lösningar till Einsteins ekvationer. Dessa lösningar inkluderar Gödel universen, kosmiska strängar och det roterande svarta hålet, där CTC stud- eras i mer detalj. CTC är kronologi-kränkande företeelser och paradoxen som uppstår presenteras, samt de argument som ligger till grund till att CTC inte är fysikaliskt verkliga objekt. De tidrum där CTC up- pkommer delar gemensamma egenskaper som anses ofysikaliska, som att vara icke asymptotiskt platta tidrum, samt att vara oändliga modeller.
    [Show full text]
  • Global Spacetime Structure∗
    Global Spacetime Structure∗ John Byron Manchak [Forthcoming in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics.] Abstract Here, we outline the basic structure of relativistic spacetime and record a number of facts. We then consider a distinction between local and global spacetime properties and provide important examples of each. We also ex- amine two clusters of global properties and question which of them should be regarded as physically reasonable. The properties concern \singulari- ties" and \time travel" and are therefore of some philosophical interest. 1 Introduction The study of global spacetime structure is a study of the more foundational aspects of general relativity. One steps away from the details of the theory and instead examines the qualitative features of spacetime (e.g. its topology and causal structure). We divide the following into three main sections. In the first, we outline the basic structure of relativistic spacetime and record a number of facts. In the second, we consider a distinction between local and global spacetime properties and provide important examples of each. In the third, we examine two clusters of global properties and question which of them should be regarded as physically reasonable. The properties concern \singularities" and \time travel" and are therefore of some philosophical interest. 2 Relativistic Spacetime We take a (relativistic) spacetime to be a pair (M; gab). Here M is a smooth, connected, n-dimensional (n ≥ 2) manifold without boundary. The metric gab is a smooth, non-degenerate, pseudo-Riemannian metric of Lorentz signature (+; −; :::; −) on M.1 ∗I am grateful to Bob Batterman, Erik Curiel, David Malament, and Jim Weatherall for comments on a previous draft.
    [Show full text]