Mental Metalogic: a New Paradigm in Psychology of Reasoning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mental Metalogic: a New Paradigm in Psychology of Reasoning Mental MetaLogic: A New Paradigm in Psychology of Reasoning Yingrui Yang & Selmer Bringsjord [email protected] [email protected] Dept. of Philosophy, Psychology &• Cognitive Science (S.B. & Y.Y.) The Minds & Machines Laboratory (S.B. & Y.Y.) Department of Computer Science (S.B.) Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute Troy NY USA Abstract mental logic theory claims that logically untrained hu- mans reason using domain-independent inference rules We introduce a new theory of reasoning, Mental Meta- or schemas (e.g., that from p q and p one can infer to q; Logic (MML), which uni®es the mental logic and men- proponents of mental logic would_ say: that something like tal models theories currently deadlocked in opposition to each other. MML, as we explain, is based on the ªpsychol- this particular rule is operative in the case of our hypo- ogizingº of all of symbolic logic Ð which includes a syn- thetical Smith). On the other hand, mental model theory tactic component (proof theory) with which mental logic holds that ordinary humans reason using not abstract syn- is associated, a semantic component (model theory and tactic rules, but semantic possibilities they in some sense its relatives) with which mental models is associated, and a ªmetaº component (metatheory or metalogic), hitherto imagine. Scientists on both sides are incontestably sem- largely ignored in the psychology of reasoning. We set inal and proli®c, and the content offered by each is pow- out the seven research questions that MML is designed to erful. But the two sides stand vehemently apart, and as a enable answers to, present the research agenda that arises result the science of reasoning is, in a real sense, funda- from the goal of answering three of these questions, and mentally paralyzed.2 MML will end this paralysis. brie¯y summarize two samples of MML-based empiri- cal/experimental work, and a sample of MML-based AI R&D. 2 The 3 Components of Symbolic Logic MML is a meta-theory because it is inspired by modern symbolic logic, which is primarily a meta-inquiry, as it is 1 Introduction devoted to the mathematical study of mathematical and Few would dispute the claim that logical reasoning is a logical systems.3 And although MML is a psychological fundamental human ability. Smith can't ®nd his car keys, theory, to present it we need a quick review of the three but knows both that he last had them minutes ago in the main components of symbolic logic. kitchen, and that he has only been in one other room In broad strokes, modern symbolic logic has three since then. After scouring every millimeter of the other main components: one is syntactic, one is semantic, and room, he reenters the kitchen and, with con®dence, pokes one is meta-theoretical. The syntactic component in- around and ®nds them. His con®dence is the result of de- cludes speci®cation of the alphabet of a given logical ductive reasoning, that much we know. But what is de- system, the grammar for building well-formed formu- ductive reasoning? In the last three decades, the psychol- las (wffs) from this alphabet, and a proof theory that ogy of reasoning has produced countless papers in psy- precisely describes how and when one formula can be chological journals (such as Psychological Review, Sci- proved from a set of formulas. The semantic compo- ence,andBehavioral & Brain Sciences) aimed at pro- nent includes a precise account of the conditions under viding an answer to this question, and aimed thereby at which a formula in a given system is true or false. The providing a scienti®c explanation of what Smith has just meta-theoretical component includes theorems, conjec- done. Alas, the answer and explanation have never ar- tures, and hypotheses concerning the syntactic compo- rived. The reason is that if one had to capture the psychol- nent, the semantic component, and connections between ogy of reasoning in a word or two, the ®rst choice would these two components. doubtless be ªThe Controversy.º 2 The Controversy is well-known to many of our read- There are ways of avoiding the Controversy. For example, one can lump all abstract ªanalyticº reasoning (deductive rea- ers. In brief, it arises from two competing theories 1 soning of all kinds, statistical reasoning, and so on) together, for modeling and explaining ordinary human reason- and give this reasoning a name, and then give another name ing (especially deductive reasoning). On the one hand, to intuitive, concrete, non-symbolic thinking thinking. This is something Stanovich & West (2000) do. But such a move really 1We say `ordinary' here to exclude those experts who are is avoidance; it makes no progress in the face of the challenge to extensively educated in the ways of formal deductive reason- give a precise scienti®c account of all the various forms of an- ing, and those humans apparently gifted to the degree that their alytic reasoning, including that species of most concern to us: performance on deductive reasoning tasks is what would be ex- deductive reasoning. pected from such experts. For a discussion of such experts, see 3Tellingly, mathematical logic, a part of symbolic logic, is (Bringsjord, Bringsjord & Noel 1998). sometimes called `meta-mathematics.' As an example, consider the familiar logical system Mental MetaLogic known as the propositional calculus (also known as sen- Mental Mental tential logic). The alphabet in this case is simply an in- Logic-like Model-like ®nite list p1;p2;:::;pn;pn+1;:::of propositional vari- Content Content ables (according to tradition p1 is p, p2 is q,andp3 is r), and the ®ve familiar truth-functional connectives ; ; ; ; . The grammar for the propositional calculus: ! is $ ^ _ straightforward and well-known. in untrained reasoners Various proof theories for the propositional calculus "Naturally Occurring" Reasoning are possible. One such theory, a so-called natural deduc- in math/logic, & experts thereof tion theory, includes the inference rule which says that from a pair of formulas having the form φ and φ one ! can infer ; this rule is known as modus ponens.Given Proof Formal a full set of rules of inference, one can speak in general Theory Semantics about an individual formula φ being derivable from a set Metatheory Φ of formulas that serve as suppositions; this is tradition- Symbolic Logic ally written Φ φ. ` Figure 1: Overview of Mental MetaLogic Symmetry A formula derivable from the null set is said to be a the- with Symbolic Logic orem, and where φ is such a formula, we follow custom and write φ holds. When the ®rst direction holds, a logical system is ` to express such a fact. said to be sound, and this fact can be expressed in the no- The semantic side of the propositional calculus is of tation we've invoked as course based on the notion of a truth-value assignment, If Φ φ then Φ = φ. an assignment of a truth-value (T or F , or sometimes, in- ` j stead, 1 or 0) to each propositional variable p , and upon i Roughly put, a logical system is sound if it's guaranteed the truth-functions expressed by the ®ve connectives al- that true formulas can only yield (through derivations) luded to just above; usually these truth-functions are de- true formulas; one cannot pass from the true to the false. ®ned via truth tables. When the ªother directionº is true of a system that system Given a truth-value assignment v, the truth or falsity is said to be complete; in our notation this is expressed by of a given propositional formula, no matter how com- plicated, can be mechanically calculated. Armed with a If Φ = φ then Φ φ. truth-value assignment v, we can say that v ªmakes trueº j ` or ªmodelsº or ªsatis®esº a given formula φ; this is stan- As a matter of fact, the propositional calculus is both dardly written provably sound and complete. One consequence of this v = φ. j is that all theorems in the propositionalcalculus are valid, Some formulas are true on all models. For example, the and all validities are theorems.4 formula ((p q) q) pis in this category. Such formulas are_ said to^: be valid!and are sometimes referred 3 The Components & ML, MM, MML to as validities. To indicate that a formula φ is valid we Now, using the review provided in the previous section, write we characterize mental logic, mental models, and Mental = φ. MetaLogic. This characterization is summed up in Figure j Another important semantic notion is consequence.An 1. individualformulaφ is said to be a consequence of a set Φ The representational system of current mental logic of formulas provided that all the truth-value assignments theory can be viewed as (at least to some degree) a psy- on which all of Φ are true is also one on which φ is true; chological selection from the syntactic components of this is customarily written systems studied in modern symbolic logic. For exam- ple, in mental logic modus ponens is often selected as a Φ = φ. schema while modus tollens5 isn't; yet both are valid in- j ferences in most standard logical systems. Another ex- At this point it's easy enough to describe, through ample can be found right at the heart of Lance Rips' sys- the example of the propositional calculus, the meta- tem of mental logic, PSYCOP, set out in (Rips 1994), theoretical component of modern symbolic logic that is for this system includes conditional proof (p. 116), but particularly relevant to Mental MetaLogic: Meta-theory not the rule which sanctions passing from the denial of would deploy logical and mathematical techniques in or- der to answer such questions as whether or not provabil- 4A fact captured by: = φ if and only if φ.
Recommended publications
  • PHIL 677 Lec 01 Metalogic Fall Term 2019 MW 14:00–15:15, Math Sciences 319
    PHIL 677 Lec 01 Metalogic Fall Term 2019 MW 14:00–15:15, Math Sciences 319 Course Outline Instructor: Richard Zach (he/him) Email: [email protected] Oce: Social Sciences 1230 Oce Hours: MW 13:00–13:50, or by appointment Phone: (403) 220–3170 Teaching Assistant: Weidong Sun (he/him) Email: [email protected] Oce: Social Sciences 1242 Oce Hours: T 15:40-16:40, R 10:00–11:00 Phone: (403) 220–6464 Email is preferred over phone. However please keep the following in mind: 1. Please ensure that “Phil 677” or some other clearly identifying term occurs in the subject line. Otherwise there is a strong possibility that your message will be deleted unread as spam. 2. If you email to make an appointment please indicate the times when you are available. 3. Please make sure your first and last names are clearly included in the body of any email message. 4. We will not respond to email after 7pm or on weekends. 1 Course Information Formal logic has many applications both within philosophy and outside (espe- cially in mathematics, computer science, and linguistics). This second course will introduce you to the concepts, results, and methods of formal logic neces- sary to understand and appreciate these applications as well as the limitations of formal logic. It will be mathematical in that you will be required to master abstract formal concepts and to prove theorems about logic; but it does not presuppose any (advanced) knowledge of mathematics. We will start from the basics. We will begin by studying some basic formal concepts: sets, relations, and functions, and the sizes of infinite sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Incompleteness Theorems
    The Incompleteness Theorems ● Here are some fundamental philosophical questions with mathematical answers: ○ (1) Is there a (recursive) algorithm for deciding whether an arbitrary sentence in the language of first-order arithmetic is true? ○ (2) Is there an algorithm for deciding whether an arbitrary sentence in the language of first-order arithmetic is a theorem of Peano or Robinson Arithmetic? ○ (3) Is there an algorithm for deciding whether an arbitrary sentence in the language of first-order arithmetic is a theorem of pure (first-order) logic? ○ (4) Is there a complete (even if not recursive) recursively axiomatizable theory in the language of first-order arithmetic? ○ (5) Is there a recursively axiomatizable sub-theory of Peano Arithmetic that proves the consistency of Peano Arithmetic (even if it leaves other questions undecided)? ○ (6) Is there a formula of arithmetic that defines arithmetic truth in the standard model, N (even if it does not represent it)? ○ (7) Is the (non-recursively enumerable) set of truths in the language of first-order arithmetic categorical? If not, is it ω-categorical (i.e., categorical in models of cardinality ω)? ● Questions (1) -- (7) turn out to be linked. Their philosophical interest depends partly on the following philosophical thesis, of which we will make frequent, but inessential, use. ○ Church-Turing Thesis:A function is (intuitively) computable if/f it is recursive. ■ Church: “[T]he notion of an effectively calculable function of positive integers should be identified with that of recursive function (quoted in Epstein & Carnielli, 223).” ○ Note: Since a function is recursive if/f it is Turing computable, the Church-Turing Thesis also implies that a function is computable if/f it is Turing computable.
    [Show full text]
  • On Synthetic Undecidability in Coq, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem
    On Synthetic Undecidability in Coq, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem Yannick Forster Dominik Kirst Gert Smolka Saarland University Saarland University Saarland University Saarbrücken, Germany Saarbrücken, Germany Saarbrücken, Germany [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract like decidability, enumerability, and reductions are avail- We formalise the computational undecidability of validity, able without reference to a concrete model of computation satisfiability, and provability of first-order formulas follow- such as Turing machines, general recursive functions, or ing a synthetic approach based on the computation native the λ-calculus. For instance, representing a given decision to Coq’s constructive type theory. Concretely, we consider problem by a predicate p on a type X, a function f : X ! B Tarski and Kripke semantics as well as classical and intu- with 8x: p x $ f x = tt is a decision procedure, a function itionistic natural deduction systems and provide compact д : N ! X with 8x: p x $ ¹9n: д n = xº is an enumer- many-one reductions from the Post correspondence prob- ation, and a function h : X ! Y with 8x: p x $ q ¹h xº lem (PCP). Moreover, developing a basic framework for syn- for a predicate q on a type Y is a many-one reduction from thetic computability theory in Coq, we formalise standard p to q. Working formally with concrete models instead is results concerning decidability, enumerability, and reducibil- cumbersome, given that every defined procedure needs to ity without reference to a concrete model of computation. be shown representable by a concrete entity of the model.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Metalogic an Introduction to Classical Model Theory & Computability
    Classical Metalogic An Introduction to Classical Model Theory & Computability Notes by R.J. Buehler January 5, 2015 2 Preface What follows are my personal notes created in preparation for the UC-Berkeley Group in Logic preliminary exam. I am not a computability theorist, nor a model theorist; I am a graduate student with some knowledge who is–alas–quite fallible. Accordingly, this text is made available as a convenient reference, set of notes, and summary, but without even the slight hint of a guarantee that everything contained within is factual and correct (indeed, some areas are entirely unchanged from the moment I copied them off the blackboard). This said, if you find a serious error, I would greatly appreciate it if you would let me know so that it can be corrected. The material for these notes derives from a wide variety of sources: Lectures by Wes Holliday Lectures by Antonio Montalban Lectures by John Steel Kevin Kelly’s computability theory notes David Marker’s “Model Theory: An Introduction” Wilfrid Hodge’s “A Shorter Model Theory” Robert Soare’s “Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees" Richard Kaye’s “Models of Peano Arithmetic” Chang and Keisler’s “Model Theory" While I certainly hope my notes are beneficial, if you’re attempting to learn the contained material for the first time, I would highly suggest picking up (at least) a copy of Marker and Soare’s texts in addition. To those Group in Logic students who may be using these notes to help themselves prepare for their preliminary exam, chapters 1-5, 7, and 9-18 contain relevant material, as well as chapter 8, section 3.
    [Show full text]
  • METALOGIC METALOGIC an Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic
    METALOGIC METALOGIC An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic Geoffrey Hunter Senior Lecturer in the Department of Logic and Metaphysics University of St Andrews PALGRA VE MACMILLAN © Geoffrey Hunter 1971 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1971 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without permission. First published 1971 by MACMILLAN AND CO LTD London and Basingstoke Associated companies in New York Toronto Dublin Melbourne Johannesburg and Madras SBN 333 11589 9 (hard cover) 333 11590 2 (paper cover) ISBN 978-0-333-11590-9 ISBN 978-1-349-15428-9 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-1-349-15428-9 The Papermac edition of this book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, resold, hired out, or otherwise circulated without the publisher's prior consent, in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser. To my mother and to the memory of my father, Joseph Walter Hunter Contents Preface xi Part One: Introduction: General Notions 1 Formal languages 4 2 Interpretations of formal languages. Model theory 6 3 Deductive apparatuses. Formal systems. Proof theory 7 4 'Syntactic', 'Semantic' 9 5 Metatheory. The metatheory of logic 10 6 Using and mentioning. Object language and metalang- uage. Proofs in a formal system and proofs about a formal system. Theorem and metatheorem 10 7 The notion of effective method in logic and mathematics 13 8 Decidable sets 16 9 1-1 correspondence.
    [Show full text]
  • MAT 440: Mathematical Logic
    Program Cover Sheet --- MAT 440: Mathematical Logic I. Basic Course Information MAT 440: Mathematical Logic is an upper level course scheduled for two 80-minute lecture periods. Sophomore standing or above is a prerequisite. Every upper level math course is designed in part to increase a student’s ability to reason logically, and this 400-level Mathematical Logic course is no different. Despite its name, however, it is not particularly designed for this goal. Instead, this course is designed to take a mathematical and philosophical view at the mechanisms of logical reasoning. There will be three major themes: the process, characteristics and limits of logical reasoning. Much of the mathematical content and processes that will be used in this course will already have been introduced somewhere else in the curriculum, most directly in our Discrete Mathematics which serves as an introduction to techniques of proof. The most notable exception to this is that we will require some knowledge of set theory, in particular, infinite sets and cardinalities. II. Learning Goals The learning goals of this course reflect its major themes. Students will learn the process of logic by exploring propositional and first-order logic languages. Students will learn how to work inside these languages to derive proofs of statements. Secondly, students will study these languages from outside, in the language of metalogic. Here, students will learn the characteristics of these languages. For example, the different notions of ‘truth’ and ‘proof’ will be compared and contrasted. Lastly, students will learn the limits of mathematics in the context of completeness and consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • PL 3014 - Metalogic
    PL 3014 - Metalogic Important topics in Chapter 5 (Mathematical Systems) Let S be a first order system. 1. Logical axioms of S are axioms of S that are logically valid (i.e., (K1)-(K6)). 2. Proper axioms of S are axioms of S that are not logically valid. Def. 5.3. A first order system with equality is an extension of K obtained by including the following proper axioms (axioms of equality): 2 (E7) A1 (x1, x1) 2 2 n n n (E8) A1 (tk, u) → A1 (fi (t1, ..., tk, ..., tn), fi (t1, ..., u, ..., tn)), where t1, ..., tn, u are any terms, and fi is any function letter of L. 2 n n n (E9) (A1 (tk, u) → (Ai (t1, ..., tk, ..., tn) → Ai (t1, ..., u, ..., tn))), where t1, ..., tn, u are any terms, and Ai is any predicate letter of L. 2 2 A1 is a 2-place predicate letter representing equality. Convention: We abbreviate A1 (x, x) by x = x. The first order system N of arithmetic . The language LN of N contains: individual variables: x1, x2, ... (below abbreviated x, y, z, ... ) individual constant: a1 (for 0) 1 2 2 function letters: f1 , f1 , f2 (successor ', sum +, product, ×) 2 predicate letter: A1 (equality =) punctuation: (, ), , connectives: ∼, → quantifier: ∀ N is the extension of K obtained by including as axioms (E7), (E8), (E9), and the following: (N1) (∀x)∼(x') = 0 (N2) (∀x)(∀y)(x' = y' → x = y) (N3) (∀x)(x + 0 = x) (N4) (∀x)(∀y)(x + y' = (x + y)') (N5) (∀x)(x × 0 = 0) (N6) (∀x)(∀y)(x × y' = (x × y) + x) (N7) A(0) → ((∀x)(A(x) → A(x') → (∀x)A(x)), for each wf A(x) of L N in which x occurs free.
    [Show full text]
  • The Decision Problem and the Development of Metalogic
    Historical Background Behmann’s Solution for the Monadic Class Decision Problems after Behmann Historical Discussion The Decision Problem and the Development of Metalogic Richard Zach University of Calgary, Canada Department of Philosophy and Calgary Institute for the Humanities www.ucalgary.ca/∼rzach/ ASL Annual Meeting March 12, 2007 1/38 Richard Zach Decision Problem and Development of Metalogic Historical Background Behmann’s Solution for the Monadic Class Decision Problems after Behmann Historical Discussion Outline 1 Historical Background 2 Behmann’s Solution for the Monadic Class 3 Decision Problems after Behmann 4 Historical Discussion 2/38 Richard Zach Decision Problem and Development of Metalogic Historical Background Introduction Behmann’s Solution for the Monadic Class Dramatis personae Decision Problems after Behmann Early Work on Decidability Historical Discussion The Decision Problem Introduction Decision Problem: find a procedure which decides after finitely many steps if a given formula is valid or not One of the fundamental problems for the development of modern logic in the 1920s and 1930s Intimately tied up with Hilbert’s philosophical project development of model theory development of notion of decision procedure/computation 3/38 Richard Zach Decision Problem and Development of Metalogic Historical Background Introduction Behmann’s Solution for the Monadic Class Dramatis personae Decision Problems after Behmann Early Work on Decidability Historical Discussion The Decision Problem David Hilbert, 1862–1943 Studied mathematics
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Metalogic: Completeness
    Philosophy 244: #7|Modal Metalogic: Completeness Soundness for a system S says that its theorems are S-valid, valid in all S-frames. Com- pleteness says that every S-valid wff is provable in S. The two together show system S is adequate. You might think this is no great accomplishment; why would it be called S-validity if it wasn't going to line up with provability in S? For provability in S to agree with S-validity is about as informative as being told that Lou Gehrig died of Lou Gehrig's disease. What we Well, but that is somewhat informative; learn is that there's a distinctive form of validity corresponding to system T. Given how va- we learn that he had a disease and it was that disease that killed him; he lidity was defined we learn that there's a distinctive sort of frame. The surprise isn't that the didn't die of boredom or whatever. relevant frames are called T-frames; it's that there's that kind of frame in the first place. Adequacy results are informative in a similar way. Systems can be defined either in terms of an axiomatic basis, or in terms of theorems; the Not all modal systems have associated first approach is more fine-grained since there can be two bases for the same set of theorems. frames. KH = K + 2(2p≡p)⊃p For the most part we'll be using the second notion. A system is a set of wffs. Not any old set, doesn't (160-1) e.g., not the wffs of length 51! The set has to be closed under some kind of implication.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Semantics and Logic.Pdf
    Formal Semantics and Logic Bas C. van Fraassen Copyright c 1971, Bas C. van Fraassen Originally published by The Macmillan Company, New York This eBook was published by Nousoul Digital Publishers. Its formatting is optimized for eReaders and other electronic reading devices. For information, the publisher may be con- tacted by email at: [email protected] 2 To my parents 3 Preface to the .PDF Edition With a view to the increasing academic importance of digital media this electronic edition was created by Nousoul Digital Publishers. Thanks to the diligent work and expertise of Brandon P. Hopkins this edition has fea- tures that no book could have in the year of its original publication: searchable text and hyperlinked notes. The text itself remains essentially unchanged, but in addition to typographical corrections there are also some substantive corrections. Apart from the change in the solution to exercise 5.4 of Chapter 3, none comprise more than a few words or symbols. However, as different as digital media are from print media, so too is digital for- matting different from print formatting. Thus there are significant formatting differences from the earlier edition. The font and page dimensions differ, as well as the page numbering, which is made to accord with the pagina- tion automatically assigned to multi-paged documents by most standard document-readers. Bas van Fraassen 2016 4 Contents Preface (1971)9 Introduction: Aim and Structure of Logical Theory 12 1 Mathematical Preliminaries 19 1.1 Intuitive Logic and Set Theory....... 19 1.2 Mathematical Structures.......... 23 1.3 Partial Order and Trees.........
    [Show full text]
  • 21 Metatheory of Logics and the Characterization Problem
    21 Metatheory of Logics and the Characterization Problem JAN WOLENSKI´ 1 Introduction The word ‘metatheory’ denotes or perhaps suggests a theory of theories. Metascientific studies in the twentieth century used the term ‘metatheory’ to refer to investigations of theories in a variety of disciplines, for example, logic, sociology, psychology, history, etc. However, the philosophers of the Vienna Circle who made metatheoretical studies of science the main concern of their philosophy restricted metatheory to the logic of science modeled on developments in the foundations of mathematics. More specifically, the logic of science was intended to play a role similar to metamathematics in Hilbert’s sense; that is, it was projected as formal analysis of scientific theories understood as well-defined linguistic items. The word ‘metamathematics’ was used before Hilbert, but with a different meaning from his (see Ritter et al. 1980: 1175–8). In the early nine- teenth century, mathematicians, like Gauss, spoke about metamathematics in an explicitly pejorative sense. It was for them a speculative way of looking at mathematics – a sort of metaphysics of mathematics. A negative attitude to metaphysics was at that time inherited from Kant and early positivists. The only one serious use of ‘metamath- ematics’ was restricted to metageometry, and that was due to the fact that the invention of different geometries in the nineteenth century stimulated comparative studies. For example, investigations were undertaken of particular axiomatizations, their mutual relations, models of various geometrical systems, and attempts to prove their consistency. The prefix ‘meta’ presently suggests two things. First, it indicates that metatheoretical considerations appear ‘after’ (in the genetic sense) theories are formulated.
    [Show full text]
  • Metalogic Cheat Sheet
    Metalogic Cheat Sheet The formal language P: Six symbols: p, 0, ∼, ⊃, (, ) Propositional symbols of P: p followed by one or more 0, e.g. p0, p00, p000 Formulas (wffs) of P: valid sentences in the formal language P satisfy the following criteria: (1) A single propositional symbol of P. (2) If A is a formula, the ∼ A is a formula. (3) If A and B are formulas, then (A ⊃ B) is a formula (parentheses are sometimes dropped if A ⊃ B is alone). Definition: An interpretation of P is an assignment to each propositional symbol of P a T or F, but not both. Definition: I is a true interpretation of P if for any formulas A and B (1) If A is a propositional formula, the A is true for I iff I assigns a value of T to A (2) ∼ A is true for I iff A is not true for I (3) A ⊃ B is true for I iff either A is not true or B is true for I Definition: A false interpretation of P: A is false for I iff A is not true for I Definition: An interpretation I is a model of a set of formulas of P iff every formula in the set is true for I. Definition: (j=P A) A is a logically valid formula of P iff A is true for every interpretation I of P. Definition: A model-theoretically consistent set of formulas of P is one that has a model. Definition: A model-theoretically inconsistent set of formulas of P is one that has no model.
    [Show full text]