DEDEKIND COMPLETIONS of BOUNDED ARCHIMEDEAN C

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

DEDEKIND COMPLETIONS of BOUNDED ARCHIMEDEAN C December 6, 2012 10:1 WSPC/S0219-4988 171-JAA 1250139 Journal of Algebra and Its Applications Vol. 12, No. 1 (2013) 1250139 (16 pages) c World Scientific Publishing Company DOI: 10.1142/S0219498812501393 DEDEKIND COMPLETIONS OF BOUNDED ARCHIMEDEAN -ALGEBRAS GURAM BEZHANISHVILI∗, PATRICK J. MORANDI† and BRUCE OLBERDING‡ Department of Mathematical Sciences New Mexico State University Las Cruces, NM 88003-8001, USA ∗[email protected][email protected][email protected] Received 19 July 2011 Accepted 28 February 2012 Published 10 December 2012 Communicated by D. Mundici All algebras considered in this paper are commutative with 1. Let ba be the category of bounded Archimedean -algebras. We investigate Dedekind completions and Dedekind complete algebras in ba . We give several characterizations for A ∈ ba to be Dedekind complete. Also, given A, B ∈ ba , we give several characterizations for B to be the Dedekind completion of A. We prove that unlike general Gelfand-Neumark-Stone duality, the duality for Dedekind complete algebras does not require any form of the Stone– Weierstrass Theorem. We show that taking the Dedekind completion is not functorial, but that it is functorial if we restrict our attention to those A ∈ ba that are Baer rings. As a consequence of our results, we give a new characterization of when A ∈ ba is a C∗-algebra. We also show that A is a C∗-algebra if and only if A is the inverse limit of an inverse family of clean C∗-algebras. We conclude the paper by discussing how to derive Gleason’s theorem about projective compact Hausdorff spaces and projective covers of compact Hausdorff spaces from our results. Keywords: -ring; -algebra; Baer ring; uniform completion; Dedekind completion; essen- tial closure; injective hull; C∗-algebra; compact Hausdorff space; Gelfand-Neumark- Stone duality; extremally disconnected space; projective cover. Mathematics Subject Classification 2000: 06F25, 13J25, 54C30, 54G05 1. Introduction In the theory of completions of -groups and f-rings, uniform completions and Dedekind completions are the most studied. Let ba be the category of (commuta- tive and unital) bounded Archimedean -algebras. It is known (see, e.g., [13, The- orem 11.5]) that uniformly complete objects in ba are precisely the commutative 1250139-1 December 6, 2012 10:1 WSPC/S0219-4988 171-JAA 1250139 G. Bezhanishvili, P. J. Morandi & B. Olberding real C∗-algebras with identity involution. Therefore, following [17, Ch. IV.4], we call uniformly complete objects in ba C∗-algebras. By [4, Theorem 3.4], A ∈ ba is uniformly complete if and only if A is epicomplete. Also, for A, B ∈ ba ,itis known that the following conditions are equivalent: (i) B is the uniform comple- tion of A; (ii) B is uniformly complete and A is isomorphic to a uniformly dense -subalgebra of B; (iii) B is isomorphic to C(XA), where XA is the (compact and Hausdorff) space of maximal -ideals of A and C(XA)isthe-algebra of all con- tinuous real-valued functions on XA. In this paper we obtain similar results for Dedekind complete algebras and Dedekind completions in ba .ForA ∈ ba , we prove that the following conditions are equivalent: (i) A is Dedekind complete; (ii) A is a Baer C∗-algebra; (iii) A is an injective object in ba ;(iv)A is essentially closed. Also, for A, B ∈ ba ,weprove that the following conditions are equivalent: (i) B is isomorphic to the Dedekind completion of A; (ii) B is the injective hull of A in ba ; (iii) B is the essential closure of A;(iv)ThespaceXB of maximal -ideals of B is the Gleason cover of the space XA of maximal -ideals of A and B isomorphic to C(XB ). Some of these results already follow from the work of Conrad [5] and Banaschewski and Hager [2], however our approach is different. We also show that unlike general Gelfand-Neumark-Stone duality, the duality for Dedekind complete algebras does not require any form of the Stone–Weierstrass Theorem; that taking the Dedekind completion is not functorial in general; but that it is functorial if we restrict our attention to those A ∈ ba that are Baer rings. As a consequence of our results, we prove that A ∈ ba is a C∗-algebra if and only if every bimorphism from A into an -subalgebra of the Dedekind completion D(A)ofA is onto, which provides an improvement of [4, Theorem 3.4]. We also show that A is a C∗-algebra if and only if A is the inverse limit of an inverse family of clean C∗-algebras, each of which is isomorphic to an -subalgebra of D(A). We conclude the paper by discussing how to derive Gleason’s theorem about projective compact Hausdorff spaces and projective covers of compact Hausdorff spaces from our results. 2. Preliminaries All algebras considered in this paper are assumed to be commutative with 1. Let A be a ring. We denote by Max(A) the set of maximal ideals of A, and recall that the closed sets of the Zariski topology on Max(A)arethesetsZ(I):={M ∈ Max(A):I ⊆ M},whereI is an ideal of A.ItiswellknownthatMax(A)isa T compact 1-space, but that it is not Hausdorff in general. The Jacobson radical of A is J(A)= Max(A), and an ideal I of A is an annihilator ideal if there exists an ideal J of A such that I =Ann(J):={a ∈ A : aJ =0}. We recall that A is a Gelfand ring if for each a, b ∈ A, whenever a + b =1, there exist r, s ∈ A such that (1 + ar)(1 + bs) = 0; that A is a clean ring if each element of A is the sum of an idempotent and a unit; and that A is a Baer ring 1250139-2 December 6, 2012 10:1 WSPC/S0219-4988 171-JAA 1250139 Dedekind Completions of Bounded Archimedean -Algebras if each annihilator ideal of A is a principal ideal generated by an idempotent. As follows from [4,Secs.4and5],ifJ(A)=0,thenA is a Gelfand ring if and only if Max(A) is a compact Hausdorff space; A is a clean ring if and only if Max(A)isa zero-dimensional compact Hausdorff space (a Stone space); and A is a Baer Gelfand ring if and only if Max(A) is an extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space. An -ring is a ring A with a partial order ≤ such that (A, ≤) is a lattice, a ≤ b and c ≤ d imply a + c ≤ b + d,anda ≤ b and 0 ≤ c imply ac ≤ bc.LetA be an -ring. Then: (1) A is bounded if for each a ∈ A there is n ∈ N such that a ≤ n · 1. (2) A is Archimedean if a, b ∈ A and na ≤ b for each n ∈ N imply a ≤ 0. (3) A is an f-ring if a ∧ b =0andc ≥ 0implyac ∧ b =0. (4) A has bounded inversion if each a ∈ A with 1 ≤ a is invertible in A. For an -ring A and a ∈ A,leta+ = a ∨ 0, a− = −a ∨ 0and|a| = a ∨ (−a). Then a+,a− ≥ 0, a+ ∧ a− =0,a = a+ − a− and |a| = a+ + a−.Moreover,ifA is an f-ring, then a2 ≥ 0and|ab| = |a||b|. Since each bounded -ring is an f-ring, these also hold for bounded -rings. We call an -ring A an -algebra if A is an R-vector lattice; that is, A is an R-vector space and for each 0 ≤ a ∈ A and 0 ≤ λ ∈ R we have λa ≥ 0. For -algebras A and B,amapα : A → B is an -algebra homomorphism if α is a (unital) R-algebra homomorphism and a lattice homomorphism. We denote by ba the category of bounded Archimedean -algebras and -algebra homomorphisms. We note that a morphism in ba is monic if and only if it is one-to-one, but not every epimorphism in ba is onto (see, e.g. [4, Sec. 3]). Let A ∈ ba .AnidealI of A is an -ideal if for all a, b ∈ A, whenever |a|≤|b| and b ∈ I,thena ∈ I.LetXA denote the set of all maximal -ideals of A.Then XA ⊆ Max(A), and we view XA as a subspace of Max(A), so closed sets of XA Z I Z I ∩ X {M ∈ X I ⊆ M} I A are the sets ( ):= ( ) A = A : ,where is an ideal of . By [14, Theorem 2.3(i)], the space XA is compact and Hausdorff. As XA =0, which follows from the proof of [14, Theorem 2.3], we have that J(A)=0foreach A ∈ ba . Let A ∈ ba . We define the uniform norm on A by a =inf{λ ∈ R : |a|≤λ}. This is well-defined because A is bounded, and as A is Archimedean, it follows that · is a norm on A.WecallA uniformly complete if the uniform norm on A is complete. Since each maximal -ideal of A has residue field isomorphic to R and the inter- section of all maximal -ideals is 0, to each element a ∈ A, we may associate a real-valued function fa : XA → R,givenbyfa(M)=λa,whereλa is the unique real number such that a − λa ∈ M. This produces the following important repre- sentation theorem. If A ∈ ba , then the map φA : A → C(XA), given by φ(a)=fa, is a monomorphism in ba .Conversely,ifA is isomorphic to an -subalgebra of 1250139-3 December 6, 2012 10:1 WSPC/S0219-4988 171-JAA 1250139 G. Bezhanishvili, P. J. Morandi & B. Olberding C(X), for X compact Hausdorff, then A ∈ ba .Thus,A ∈ ba if and only if A is isomorphic to an -subalgebra of C(X), where X is compact Hausdorff.
Recommended publications
  • Nearly Locally Presentable Categories Are Locally Presentable Is Equivalent to Vopˇenka’S Principle
    NEARLY LOCALLY PRESENTABLE CATEGORIES L. POSITSELSKI AND J. ROSICKY´ Abstract. We introduce a new class of categories generalizing locally presentable ones. The distinction does not manifest in the abelian case and, assuming Vopˇenka’s principle, the same happens in the regular case. The category of complete partial orders is the natural example of a nearly locally finitely presentable category which is not locally presentable. 1. Introduction Locally presentable categories were introduced by P. Gabriel and F. Ulmer in [6]. A category K is locally λ-presentable if it is cocomplete and has a strong generator consisting of λ-presentable objects. Here, λ is a regular cardinal and an object A is λ-presentable if its hom-functor K(A, −): K → Set preserves λ-directed colimits. A category is locally presentable if it is locally λ-presentable for some λ. This con- cept of presentability formalizes the usual practice – for instance, finitely presentable groups are precisely groups given by finitely many generators and finitely many re- lations. Locally presentable categories have many nice properties, in particular they are complete and co-wellpowered. Gabriel and Ulmer [6] also showed that one can define locally presentable categories by using just monomorphisms instead all morphisms. They defined λ-generated ob- jects as those whose hom-functor K(A, −) preserves λ-directed colimits of monomor- phisms. Again, this concept formalizes the usual practice – finitely generated groups are precisely groups admitting a finite set of generators. This leads to locally gener- ated categories, where a cocomplete category K is locally λ-generated if it has a strong arXiv:1710.10476v2 [math.CT] 2 Apr 2018 generator consisting of λ-generated objects and every object of K has only a set of strong quotients.
    [Show full text]
  • Categories of Modules for Idempotent Rings and Morita Equivalences
    Master's Thesis Categories of Modules for Idempotent Rings and Morita Equivalences I Leandro Marm 1997 t Department of Mathematics University of Glasgow University Gardens Glasgow, G12 8QW ProQuest Number: 13834261 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a com plete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest ProQuest 13834261 Published by ProQuest LLC(2019). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States C ode Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC. 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106- 1346 10$ af 7 En resolucion, el se enfrasco tanto en su lectura, que se le pasaban las noches leyendo de claro en claro, y los dias de turbio en turbio; y asi, del poco dormir y del mucho leer se le seco el celebro 1 de manera, que vino a perder el juicio. M iguel de C ervantes Sa a v e d r a : El Ingenioso Hidalgo don Quijote de la Mancha. 1In modern Spanish this word is written ”cerebro” C ontents Chapter 1, Introduction 4 Chapter 2. Categories of Modules for Rings I 7 1. Noncommutative Localization 7 2. The Construction of the Categories 11 3. The Equivalence of the Categories 24 4. The Independence of the Base Ring 28 Chapter 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Category of Sheaves Is a Topos Part 2
    The category of sheaves is a topos part 2 Patrick Elliott Recall from the last talk that for a small category C, the category PSh(C) of presheaves on C is an elementary topos. Explicitly, PSh(C) has the following structure: • Given two presheaves F and G on C, the exponential GF is the presheaf defined on objects C 2 obC by F G (C) = Hom(hC × F; G); where hC = Hom(−;C) is the representable functor associated to C, and the product × is defined object-wise. • Writing 1 for the constant presheaf of the one object set, the subobject classifier true : 1 ! Ω in PSh(C) is defined on objects by Ω(C) := fS j S is a sieve on C in Cg; and trueC : ∗ ! Ω(C) sends ∗ to the maximal sieve t(C). The goal of this talk is to refine this structure to show that the category Shτ (C) of sheaves on a site (C; τ) is also an elementary topos. To do this we must make use of the sheafification functor defined at the end of the first talk: Theorem 0.1. The inclusion functor i : Shτ (C) ! PSh(C) has a left adjoint a : PSh(C) ! Shτ (C); called sheafification, or the associated sheaf functor. Moreover, this functor commutes with finite limits. Explicitly, a(F) = (F +)+, where + F (C) := colimS2τ(C)Match(S; F); where Match(S; F) is the set of matching families for the cover S of C, and the colimit is taken over all covering sieves of C, ordered by reverse inclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monomorphism Monomorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In the context of abstract algebra or universal algebra, a monomorphism is an injective homomorphism. A monomorphism from X to Y is often denoted with the notation . In the more general setting of category theory, a monomorphism (also called a monic morphism or a mono) is a left-cancellative morphism, that is, an arrow f : X → Y such that, for all morphisms g1, g2 : Z → X, Monomorphisms are a categorical generalization of injective functions (also called "one-to-one functions"); in some categories the notions coincide, but monomorphisms are more general, as in the examples below. The categorical dual of a monomorphism is an epimorphism, i.e. a monomorphism in a category C is an epimorphism in the dual category Cop. Every section is a monomorphism, and every retraction is an epimorphism. Contents 1 Relation to invertibility 2 Examples 3 Properties 4 Related concepts 5 Terminology 6 See also 7 References Relation to invertibility Left invertible morphisms are necessarily monic: if l is a left inverse for f (meaning l is a morphism and ), then f is monic, as A left invertible morphism is called a split mono. However, a monomorphism need not be left-invertible. For example, in the category Group of all groups and group morphisms among them, if H is a subgroup of G then the inclusion f : H → G is always a monomorphism; but f has a left inverse in the category if and only if H has a normal complement in G.
    [Show full text]
  • Classifying Categories the Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorems for Abelian Categories
    U.U.D.M. Project Report 2018:5 Classifying Categories The Jordan-Hölder and Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorems for Abelian Categories Daniel Ahlsén Examensarbete i matematik, 30 hp Handledare: Volodymyr Mazorchuk Examinator: Denis Gaidashev Juni 2018 Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Classifying Categories The Jordan-Holder¨ and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems for abelian categories Daniel Ahlsen´ Uppsala University June 2018 Abstract The Jordan-Holder¨ and Krull-Schmidt-Remak theorems classify finite groups, either as direct sums of indecomposables or by composition series. This thesis defines abelian categories and extends the aforementioned theorems to this context. 1 Contents 1 Introduction3 2 Preliminaries5 2.1 Basic Category Theory . .5 2.2 Subobjects and Quotients . .9 3 Abelian Categories 13 3.1 Additive Categories . 13 3.2 Abelian Categories . 20 4 Structure Theory of Abelian Categories 32 4.1 Exact Sequences . 32 4.2 The Subobject Lattice . 41 5 Classification Theorems 54 5.1 The Jordan-Holder¨ Theorem . 54 5.2 The Krull-Schmidt-Remak Theorem . 60 2 1 Introduction Category theory was developed by Eilenberg and Mac Lane in the 1942-1945, as a part of their research into algebraic topology. One of their aims was to give an axiomatic account of relationships between collections of mathematical structures. This led to the definition of categories, functors and natural transformations, the concepts that unify all category theory, Categories soon found use in module theory, group theory and many other disciplines. Nowadays, categories are used in most of mathematics, and has even been proposed as an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics.[Law66] Due to their general nature, little can be said of an arbitrary category.
    [Show full text]
  • Toposes Are Adhesive
    Toposes are adhesive Stephen Lack1 and Pawe lSoboci´nski2? 1 School of Computing and Mathematics, University of Western Sydney, Australia 2 Computer Laboratory, University of Cambridge, United Kingdom Abstract. Adhesive categories have recently been proposed as a cate- gorical foundation for facets of the theory of graph transformation, and have also been used to study techniques from process algebra for reason- ing about concurrency. Here we continue our study of adhesive categories by showing that toposes are adhesive. The proof relies on exploiting the relationship between adhesive categories, Brown and Janelidze’s work on generalised van Kampen theorems as well as Grothendieck’s theory of descent. Introduction Adhesive categories [11,12] and their generalisations, quasiadhesive categories [11] and adhesive hlr categories [6], have recently begun to be used as a natural and relatively simple general foundation for aspects of the theory of graph transfor- mation, following on from previous work in this direction [5]. By covering several “graph-like” categories, they serve as a useful framework in which to prove struc- tural properties. They have also served as a bridge allowing the introduction of techniques from process algebra to the field of graph transformation [7, 13]. From a categorical point of view, the work follows in the footsteps of dis- tributive and extensive categories [4] in the sense that they study a particular relationship between certain finite limits and finite colimits. Indeed, whereas distributive categories are concerned with the distributivity of products over co- products and extensive categories with the relationship between coproducts and pullbacks, the various flavours of adhesive categories consider the relationship between certain pushouts and pullbacks.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 395: Category Theory Northwestern University, Lecture Notes
    Math 395: Category Theory Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Written by Santiago Can˜ez These are lecture notes for an undergraduate seminar covering Category Theory, taught by the author at Northwestern University. The book we roughly follow is “Category Theory in Context” by Emily Riehl. These notes outline the specific approach we’re taking in terms the order in which topics are presented and what from the book we actually emphasize. We also include things we look at in class which aren’t in the book, but otherwise various standard definitions and examples are left to the book. Watch out for typos! Comments and suggestions are welcome. Contents Introduction to Categories 1 Special Morphisms, Products 3 Coproducts, Opposite Categories 7 Functors, Fullness and Faithfulness 9 Coproduct Examples, Concreteness 12 Natural Isomorphisms, Representability 14 More Representable Examples 17 Equivalences between Categories 19 Yoneda Lemma, Functors as Objects 21 Equalizers and Coequalizers 25 Some Functor Properties, An Equivalence Example 28 Segal’s Category, Coequalizer Examples 29 Limits and Colimits 29 More on Limits/Colimits 29 More Limit/Colimit Examples 30 Continuous Functors, Adjoints 30 Limits as Equalizers, Sheaves 30 Fun with Squares, Pullback Examples 30 More Adjoint Examples 30 Stone-Cech 30 Group and Monoid Objects 30 Monads 30 Algebras 30 Ultrafilters 30 Introduction to Categories Category theory provides a framework through which we can relate a construction/fact in one area of mathematics to a construction/fact in another. The goal is an ultimate form of abstraction, where we can truly single out what about a given problem is specific to that problem, and what is a reflection of a more general phenomenom which appears elsewhere.
    [Show full text]
  • Protomodular Aspect of the Dual of a Topos
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector ARTICLE IN PRESS Advances in Mathematics 187 (2004) 240–255 http://www.elsevier.com/locate/aim Protomodular aspect of the dual of a topos Dominique Bourn Centre Universitaire de la Mi-voix, Lab. d’Analyse, Ge´ome´trie et Alge`bre, Universite´ du Littoral, 50 rue Ferdinand Buisson, BP699, 62228 Calais Cedex, France Received 3 March 2003; accepted 15 September 2003 Communicated by Ross Street Abstract The structure of the dual of a topos is investigated under its aspect of a Barr exact and protomodular category. In particular the normal monomorphisms in the fibres of the fibration of pointed objects are characterized, and the change of base functors with respect to this same fibration are shown to reflect those normal monomorphisms. r 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. MSC: 18B25; 18D30; 08B10 Keywords: Topos; Fibrations; Mal’cev and protomodular categories 0. Introduction It is well known that, given a topos E; the subobject classifier O is endowed with an internal structure of Heyting Algebra, and that consequently the contravariant ‘‘power-set’’ functor OðÞ : Eop-E takes its values in the category HeytE of internal Heyting algebras in E: But the category Heyt of Heyting Algebras shares with the categories Gp of groups or Rg of rings the property of being protomodular. This property [3] says that the fibration of pointed objects p : PtC-C; whose fibre at X is the category PtX C of split epimorphisms with codomain X; has its change of base functors conservative (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Show That in the Catgeory Abgroups of Abelian Groups, A
    PROBLEMS SET 5 SOLUTIONS OF SOME EXERCISES 1.{ Show that in the catgeory AbGroups of abelian groups, a morphism is a monomorphism if and only if it is injective, and a morphism is an epi- morphism if and only if it is surjective (the latter needs a little more care). Show that the same holds in the category FGAbGroups of finitely generated abelian groups (the same proof should work). Solution: Since two morphisms of groups f1; f2 : G1 ! G2 are equal if and only if they are equal as maps of sets, we see immediately that a morphism of groups which is a monomorphism (resp. an epimorphism) as map of sets is a monomorphism (resp. an epimorphism) as map of groups. Since in the category of sets, injective=mono, surjective=epi, an injective morphism of group is a monomorphism, a surjective morphism of groups is an epimorphism. Let's prove the two converses. If f : G1 ! G2 is a morphism of abeian groups, which is not injective. Then consider two maps i; z : ker f ! G1, defined as follows: i is the canonical inclusion, z is the zero map. Since ker f 6= 0, one has i 6= z. Yet f ◦ i = f ◦ z since both are the zero map: ker f ! G2. Hence f is not a monomorphism If f : G1 ! G2 is a morphism of abelian groups, which is not surjective. Since G2 is abelian, imf is a normal subgroup of G2 and one can consider the factor group G2=imf, which is not the zero group since imf 6= G2.
    [Show full text]
  • ON COMPARABILITY in a TOPOS Then E Has COMP
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 98, Number 3. November 1986 ON COMPARABILITYIN A TOPOS RADU DIACONESCU Dedicated to EJA Abstract. While studying the category of "finite" sets associated to a nonstandard model of arithmetic [4], it became apparent that the law of trichotomy plays an important role in that context. The object of this note is to point out the strength of the obvious variants of trichotomy in a general topos. At it turns out even its mildest form (COMP) is quite restrictive, the usual variants (M-COMP, E-COMP) force the topos to be equivalent to a category of sets with AC. Definition. A topos E satisfies comparability (COMP) if for any two objects A, B there is a morphism A -» B or B -* A. Observations, a. If E satisfies COMP, so does any full subcategory of E, in particular SHj(E) for some topology j, and EG, the topos of coalgebras for an idempotent left exact cotriple G. b. Any filtered colimit of toposes with COMP has COMP. c. In a topos with COMP the lattice of subobjects of 1 is totally ordered. d. COMP is not stable (S, the category of sets with AC, has COMP, but S/A doesn't). Proposition 1. If supports split in E and the subobjects of 1 are totally ordered, then E has COMP. Proof. Given A, B we have epimorphisms to their supports A -» o(A), B -» a(B), also their splittings going in the opposite direction, as well as, say o(A) >-»a(B), thus by composition, a morphism from A to B.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Category Theory
    Introduction to Category Theory David Holgate & Ando Razafindrakoto University of Stellenbosch June 2011 Contents Chapter 1. Categories 1 1. Introduction 1 2. Categories 1 3. Isomorphisms 4 4. Universal Properties 5 5. Duality 6 Chapter 2. Functors and Natural Transformations 8 1. Functors 8 2. Natural Transformations 12 3. Functor Categories and the Yoneda embedding 13 4. Representable Functors 14 Chapter 3. Special Morphisms 16 1. Monomorphisms and Epimorphisms 16 2. Split and extremal monomorphisms and epimorphisms 17 Chapter 4. Adjunctions 19 1. Galois connections 19 2. Adjoint Functors 20 Chapter 5. Limits and Colimits 23 1. Products 23 2. Pullbacks 24 3. Equalizers 26 4. Limits and Colimits 27 5. Functors and Limits 28 Chapter 6. Subcategories 30 1. Subcategories 30 2. Reflective Subcategories 31 3 1. Categories 1. Introduction Sets and their notation are widely regarded as providing the “language” we use to express our mathematics. Naively, the fundamental notion in set theory is that of membership or being an element. We write a ∈ X if a is an element of the set X and a set is understood by knowing what its elements are. Category theory takes another perspective. The category theorist says that we understand what mathematical objects are by knowing how they interact with other objects. For example a group G is understood not so much by knowing what its elements are but by knowing about the homomorphisms from G to other groups. Even a set X is more completely understood by knowing about the functions from X to other sets, f : X → Y . For example consider the single element set A = {?}.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Category Theory
    Notes on Category Theory Mariusz Wodzicki November 29, 2016 1 Preliminaries 1.1 Monomorphisms and epimorphisms 1.1.1 A morphism m : d0 ! e is said to be a monomorphism if, for any parallel pair of arrows a / 0 d / d ,(1) b equality m ◦ a = m ◦ b implies a = b. 1.1.2 Dually, a morphism e : c ! d is said to be an epimorphism if, for any parallel pair (1), a ◦ e = b ◦ e implies a = b. 1.1.3 Arrow notation Monomorphisms are often represented by arrows with a tail while epimorphisms are represented by arrows with a double arrowhead. 1.1.4 Split monomorphisms Exercise 1 Given a morphism a, if there exists a morphism a0 such that a0 ◦ a = id (2) then a is a monomorphism. Such monomorphisms are said to be split and any a0 satisfying identity (2) is said to be a left inverse of a. 3 1.1.5 Further properties of monomorphisms and epimorphisms Exercise 2 Show that, if l ◦ m is a monomorphism, then m is a monomorphism. And, if l ◦ m is an epimorphism, then l is an epimorphism. Exercise 3 Show that an isomorphism is both a monomorphism and an epimor- phism. Exercise 4 Suppose that in the diagram with two triangles, denoted A and B, ••u [^ [ [ B a [ b (3) A [ u u ••u the outer square commutes. Show that, if a is a monomorphism and the A triangle commutes, then also the B triangle commutes. Dually, if b is an epimorphism and the B triangle commutes, then the A triangle commutes.
    [Show full text]