Iterated Generalized Half-Dominance and Global Game Selection∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Iterated Generalized Half-Dominance and Global Game Selection∗ Iterated Generalized Half-dominance and Global Game Selection∗ Ryota Iijimay May 3, 2015 Abstract We offer an equilibrium characterization of a general class of global games with strategic complementarities. The analysis highlights a form of acyclicity in the interim belief structure of global games, which allows us to formalize a selection cri- terion, iterated generalized half-dominance. This criterion is shown to be a unique global game selection when noise distributions satisfy a regularity condition. A sim- ilar logic also applies to the perfect foresight dynamics of Matsui and Matsuyama (1995); an iterated generalized half-dominant equilibrium is a unique globally sta- ble state when agents are patient enough. The criterion is especially useful for games with more than two asymmetric players, and can be easily applied to local interaction games with an arbitrary network structure. 1 Introduction Many games admit multiple Nash equilibria, and there is now a vast body of literature that aims to select a unique equilibrium from them. The theory of global games is one of the leading approaches and has been used in various applications.1 The global game approach extends a complete information game by allowing payoffs to depend on an unobservable state, where each player privately observes a noisy signal about the state. Carlsson and van Damme (1993) study 2 × 2 games and show that as the noise level parameter goes to zero, the set of rationalizable actions in a global game shrinks to the risk-dominant action in the complete information game at each state. The key mechanism behind equilibrium selection is driven by the structure of interim beliefs held by \threshold types," who are indifferent between two actions upon receiving a signal. Under symmetric payoffs and binary actions, a threshold type has a Laplacian belief, whereby opponents' actions are uniformly distributed (Morris and Shin, 2003). This property leads to a tractable characterization of equilibrium selection that is easily applicable to various applications. In this paper we allow for many asymmetric players and actions. While this gener- alization is clearly important for applications, its characterization is not fully developed in the literature, because one has to deal with more complicated belief structures that ∗I am grateful to Mira Frick, Drew Fudenberg, Jonathan Libgober, Satoru Takahashi, the audience at Harvard, the editor, three anonymous referees, and to Stephen Morris and Daisuke Oyama in particular for their helpful advice and comments. yDepartment of Economics, Harvard University, e-mail: [email protected]. 1See Morris and Shin (2003) for a survey. Some recent papers incorporate endogenous information, which can prevent unique selection (e.g., Angeletos and Pavan, 2013). 1 involve multiple threshold types. Our analysis uncovers a general logic underlying global game selection by highlighting a form of acyclicity in pairwise comparison of players' in- terim beliefs. This inspires us to propose a equilibrium selection criterion of generalized half-dominance (GH-dominance). It requires each player's action to be strictly optimal if she believes that each marginal probability of her opponent choosing the equilibrium 1 2 action is more than 2 . As opposed to the p-dominance criterion that we will discuss shortly, this criterion is only concerned with beliefs about each opponent's action sepa- rately and does not involve beliefs about opponents' collective action profiles. To illustrate the intuition behind why this reasoning about each opponent's separate action is relevant in global game selection, we consider the following example. It shows that, when a GH- dominant equilibrium exists, players cannot coordinate on multiple equilibrium actions using payoff-irreverent private signals similar to a global-game type information structure. Example 1. Fix a complete information game, and suppose that there is a GH-dominant ∗ equilibrium, where ai denotes the equilibrium action of player i. We endow this game with a payoff-irrelevant state variable θ that follows the (improper) uniform prior over R; Each player i privately observes signal ti = θ + ηi, where each ηi is i.i.d noise with a positive ∗ ¯ density. Consider threshold strategies in which each player i chooses ai if ti < ti, and another action if ti > t¯i. We argue that such a strategy profile cannot be an equilibrium. ∗ Note that in such an equilibrium, i should be indifferent between choosing ai and another ∗ ∗ action at signal ti = t¯i. Take an agent i with t¯i∗ = mini t¯i. If i observes signal ti∗ = t¯i∗ , ∗ ¯ 1 she believes that for any i 6= i , ti < ti holds with probability greater than 2 . That is, she ∗ 1 believes that each opponent i's marginal probability of choosing ai is more than 2 . Since ∗ ¯ ai∗ is a GH-dominant action, she has a strict incentive to choose it at signal ti∗ , which is a contradiction. Figure 1: Threshold types The example illustrates how the \contagion" argument forces GH-dominant actions to be played at all interim types of players if these actions are known to be chosen at low enough signals. A key feature in this example is the existence of an extremal threshold type t¯i∗ who believes each opponent's signal ti to be less than its threshold ¯ 1 ti with marginal probability more than 2 . As we will see, the conclusion carries over beyond i.i.d noises, as long as we impose a natural restriction on noise distributions (weak stochastic transitivity), which is satisfied under most applied global game settings in the literature.3 In Section 3, we study general global games with strategic complementarities (Frankel et al., 2003), and show that a GH-dominant equilibrium is selected under the 2This generalizes the notion of half-dominance (Morris et al., 1995), which is defined for symmetric two-player games. 3This condition rules out a form of cyclical interim beliefs and ensures the existence of an extremal threshold type as t¯i∗ in the above example. 2 stochastic transitivity condition. Moreover, the selection result holds more generally with an iterated version of GH-dominant equilibrium, which is especially relevant when there are many actions. In Section 3.1, we also obtain a noise-independent selection result by appropriately strengthening the GH-dominance condition. The GH-dominance criterion is particularly useful for studying games with many asym- metric players, and we illustrate this point using games on networks (Section 2.1). We show that, if there is an (iterated) half-dominant action in a component game, then it is an (iterated) GH-dominant equilibrium of a network game wherein every player chooses it. Because this claim is true for any network with any population size, an analyst does not need to know the network structure in order to obtain this prediction. The analysis of global games with asymmetric players has been mostly limited to par- ticular classes of games.4 A general class of global games with strategic complementarities ∗ is studied by Frankel et al. (2003). For a nonnegative vector p, an action profile (ai )i2N is a p-dominant equilibrium (Kajii and Morris, 1997) if each player i has a strict incen- tive to follow the equilibrium action whenever she believes that a joint probability of the opponents following the equilibrium action profile is more than pi. Frankel et al. (2003) P show that a p-dominant equilibrium with i pi < 1 is selected in global games under any noise distributions. p-dominance is theoretically motivated by the \critical path lemma" of Kajii and Morris (1997), which is applicable to general incomplete information games.5 On the other hand, the GH-dominance selection result exploits the belief structure that is specific to global games; as a consequence, GH-dominance can be easily applied to games P with many players while the p-dominance condition with i pi < 1 cannot. The key logic of GH-dominance selection in global games carries over to the perfect foresight dynamics, which is introduced by Matsui and Matsuyama (1995).6 In this model, there is a continuum population of forward-looking agents and each one is committed to an action for a stochastic length of time. Each agent's flow payoff depends on an aggregate action distribution in the population. We show that iterated GH-dominance is also selected by this model, that is, the population state in which every agent adopts an iterated GH-dominant action is a unique state that is globally stable (in a sense that will be formalized later). Following Takahashi (2008), we can describe the perfect foresight dynamics (with patient agents) by a variant of global games that satisfy weak stochastic transitivity. Thus the coincidence of the GH-dominance selection results highlight the shared feature of the strategic beliefs of the two models (see Section 4 for details). 2 Iterated GH-dominance Consider a normal form game G =< N; (Ai; ui)i2N >. N = f1; 2; :::; ng is a set of players. Each Ai is a finite set of actions of player i 2 N, and each ui : AN ! R is a payoff 4Corsetti et al. (2004) introduced a large trader into a population of small agents. Guimaraes and Morris (2007) allow for heterogeneous payoffs in a model of currency attack. Sakovics and Steiner (2012) generalize the Laplacian belief property in a class of binary-action games of regime change with heterogeneous payoffs. 5 P That is, if i pi < 1 and an event E occurs with a high ex-ante probability (under a common prior), then there exists a high ex-ante probability event E0 ⊆ E on which E is common p-believed. Kajii and P Morris (1997) use this property to show that a p-dominant equilibrium with i pi < 1 is robust against general incomplete information perturbations.
Recommended publications
  • Prophylaxy Copie.Pdf
    Social interactions and the prophylaxis of SI epidemics on networks Géraldine Bouveret, Antoine Mandel To cite this version: Géraldine Bouveret, Antoine Mandel. Social interactions and the prophylaxis of SI epi- demics on networks. Journal of Mathematical Economics, Elsevier, 2021, 93, pp.102486. 10.1016/j.jmateco.2021.102486. halshs-03165772 HAL Id: halshs-03165772 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-03165772 Submitted on 17 Mar 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Social interactions and the prophylaxis of SI epidemics on networkssa G´eraldineBouveretb Antoine Mandel c March 17, 2021 Abstract We investigate the containment of epidemic spreading in networks from a nor- mative point of view. We consider a susceptible/infected model in which agents can invest in order to reduce the contagiousness of network links. In this setting, we study the relationships between social efficiency, individual behaviours and network structure. First, we characterise individual and socially efficient behaviour using the notions of communicability and exponential centrality. Second, we show, by computing the Price of Anarchy, that the level of inefficiency can scale up to lin- early with the number of agents.
    [Show full text]
  • Statistical GGP Game Decomposition Aline Hufschmitt, Jean-Noël Vittaut, Nicolas Jouandeau
    Statistical GGP Game Decomposition Aline Hufschmitt, Jean-Noël Vittaut, Nicolas Jouandeau To cite this version: Aline Hufschmitt, Jean-Noël Vittaut, Nicolas Jouandeau. Statistical GGP Game Decomposition. Computer Games - 7th Workshop, CGW 2018, Held in Conjunction with the 27th International Con- ference on Artificial Intelligence, IJCAI 2018, Jul 2018, Stockholm, Sweden. pp.79-97, 10.1007/978- 3-030-24337-1_4. hal-02182443 HAL Id: hal-02182443 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02182443 Submitted on 15 Oct 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. In Proceedings of the IJCAI-18 Workshop on Computer Games (CGW 2018) Statistical GGP Game Decomposition Aline Hufschmitt, Jean-No¨elVittaut, and Nicolas Jouandeau LIASD - University of Paris 8, France falinehuf,jnv,[email protected] Abstract. This paper presents a statistical approach for the decompo- sition of games in the General Game Playing framework. General game players can drastically decrease game search cost if they hold a decom- posed version of the game. Previous works on decomposition rely on syn- tactical structures, which can be missing from the game description, or on the disjunctive normal form of the rules, which is very costly to compute.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Belief Foundations of Global Games∗
    Common Belief Foundations of Global Games Stephen Morris Hyun Song Shin Muhamet Yildiz Princeton University Bank of International Settlements M.I.T. January 2015 Abstract Complete information games– i.e., games where there is common certainty of payoffs– often have multiple rationalizable actions. What happens if the common certainty of payoffs assumption is relaxed? Consider a two player game where a player’spayoff depends on a payoff parameter. Define a player’s"rank belief" as the probability he assigns to his payoff parameter being higher than his opponent’s. We show that there is a unique rationalizable action played when there is common certainty of rank beliefs, and we argue this is the driving force behind selection results in the global games literature. We consider what happens if players’payoff parameters are derived from common and idiosyncratic terms with fat tailed distributions, and we approach complete information by shrinking the distribution of both terms. There are two cases. If the common component has a thicker tails, then there is common certainty of rank beliefs, and thus uniqueness and equilibrium selection. If the idiosyncratic terms has thicker tails, then there is approximate common certainty of payoffs, and thus multiple rationalizable actions. 1 Introduction Complete information games often have many equilibria. Even when they have a single equilibrium, they often have many actions that are rationalizable, and are therefore consistent with common This paper incorporates material from a working paper of the same title circulated in 2009 (Morris and Shin (2009)). We are grateful for comments from seminar participants at Northwestern on this iteration of the project.
    [Show full text]
  • Essays on Supermodular Games, Design, and Political Theory
    Selection, Learning, and Nomination: Essays on Supermodular Games, Design, and Political Theory Thesis by Laurent Mathevet In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy California Institute of Technology Pasadena, California 2008 (Defended May 15th, 2008) ii c 2008 Laurent Mathevet All Rights Reserved iii For my parents, Denise and Ren´eMathevet iv Acknowledgements Many people have helped me along the way. Christelle has been a source of happiness, and without her uncompromising support and faith in me, I would have been miserable. My parents, to whom this dissertation is dedicated, have shown continual and unconditional support despite the distance. They are a constant source of inspiration. I also wish to thank my advisors, Federico Echenique and Matthew Jackson, for their help and encouragement. Federico has spent numerous hours advising me, meeting with me nearly every week since my second year as a graduate student. He has endeavored to extract the most out of me, discarding unpromising thoughts and results, reading my drafts countless times and demanding (countless!) rewrites. Most importantly, he found the right words in those difficult times of a PhD graduate student. Matt has also been a wonderful advisor, available, demanding, and encouraging. I have benefited greatly from his comments, which are the kind that shapes the core of a research project. Matt has funded me for several years, which allowed me to concentrate on research. I also thank him for his invitation to spend a term at Stanford to further my research. I am indebted to Preston McAfee, whose personality, charisma, and sharpness have made meetings with him among the most fruitful and enjoyable.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory for Signal Processing in Networks
    Game Theory for Signal Processing in Networks Giacomo Bacci, Samson Lasaulce, Walid Saad, and Luca Sanguinetti Abstract In this tutorial, the basics of game theory are introduced along with an overview of its most recent and emerging applications in signal processing. One of the main features of this contribution is to gather in a single paper some fundamental game-theoretic notions and tools which, over the past few years, have become widely spread over a large number of papers. In particular, both strategic-form and coalition-form games are described in details while the key connections and differences betweenthemareoutlined.Moreover,aparticularattention is also devoted to clarify the connections between strategic-form games and distributed optimization and learning algorithms. Beyond an introduction to the basic concepts andmainsolutionapproaches,severalcarefullydesigned examples are provided to allow a better understanding of how to apply the described tools. I. INTRODUCTION game theory (GT) is a branch of mathematics that enables the modeling and analysis of the interactions between several decision-makers (called players) who can have conflicting or common objectives. A game is a situation in which the benefit or cost achieved by each player from an interactive situation depends, not only on its own decisions, but also on those taken by the other players. For example, the time a car driver needs to get back home generally depends not only on the route he/she chooses but also on the decisions taken by the other drivers. Therefore, in a game, the actions and objectives of the players are tightly coupled.Untilveryrecently,GThas been used only marginally in signal processing (SP), with notable examples being some applications in robust detection and estimation [1] as well as watermarking [2] (in which the watermarking problem is seen as a game between the data embedder and the attacker).
    [Show full text]
  • Convergence to Approximate Nash Equilibria in Congestion Games†
    Convergence to Approximate Nash Equilibria in Congestion Games† Steve Chien‡ Alistair Sinclair§ Abstract We study the ability of decentralized, local dynamics in non-cooperative games to rapidly reach an approximate Nash equilibrium. For symmetric congestion games in which the edge delays satisfy a “bounded jump” condition, we show that convergence to an ε-Nash equilibrium occurs within a number of steps that is polynomial in the number of players and ε−1. This appears to be the first such result for a class of games that includes examples for which finding an exact Nash equilibrium is PLS-complete, and in which shortest paths to an exact equilibrium are exponentially long. We show moreover that rapid convergence holds even under only the apparently minimal assumption that no player is excluded from moving for arbitrarily many steps. We also prove that, in a generalized setting where players have different “tolerances” εi that specify their thresholds in the approximate Nash equilibrium, the number of moves made by a player before equilibrium is reached depends only on his associated εi, and not on those of the other players. Finally, we show that polynomial time convergence still holds even when a bounded number of edges are allowed to have arbitrary delay functions. 1 Introduction The emerging field of algorithmic game theory has led to a fundamental re-examination, from a computational perspective, of the classical concept of Nash equilibrium [20]. Much of this activity has focused on understanding the structure of Nash equilibria (as expressed, notably, in the “price of anarchy,” see e.g. [22, 25, 24]) and the computational complexity of finding them (see, e.g., [10, 7, 4]).
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Rationality in Keynesian Beauty Contests: a Lesson for Central Bankers?
    Vol. 14, 2020-16 | June 04, 2020 | http://dx.doi.org/10.5018/economics-ejournal.ja.2020-16 Bounded rationality in Keynesian beauty contests: a lesson for central bankers? Felix Mauersberger, Rosemarie Nagel, and Christoph Bühren Abstract The great recession (2008) triggered an apparent discrepancy between empirical findings and macroeconomic models based on rational expectations alone. This gap led to a series of recent developments of a behavioral microfoundation of macroeconomics combined with the underlying experimental and behavioral Beauty Contest (BC) literature, which the authors review in this paper. They introduce the reader to variations of the Keynesian Beauty Contest (Keynes, The general theory of employment, interest, and money, 1936), theoretically and experimentally, demonstrating systematic patterns of out-of-equilibrium behavior. This divergence of (benchmark) solutions and bounded rationality observed in human behavior has been resolved through stepwise reasoning, the so-called level k, or cognitive hierarchy models. Furthermore, the authors show how the generalized BC function with limited parameter specifications encompasses relevant micro and macro models. Therefore, the stepwise reasoning models emerge naturally as building blocks for new behavioral macroeconomic theories to understand puzzles like the lacking rise of inflation after the financial crisis, the efficacy of quantitative easing, the forward guidance puzzle, and the effectiveness of temporary fiscal expansion. (Published in Special Issue Bio-psycho-social foundations of macroeconomics) JEL E12 E13 E7 D80 D9 C91 Keywords Beauty Contest game; expectation formation; equilibration; level k reasoning; behavioral macroeconomics; game theory; experimental economics Authors Felix Mauersberger, University of Bonn, Germany Rosemarie Nagel, ICREA-UPF Barcelona GSE, Spain, [email protected] Christoph Bühren, Clausthal University of Technology, Germany Citation Felix Mauersberger, Rosemarie Nagel, and Christoph Bühren (2020).
    [Show full text]
  • Efficiency of Mechanisms in Complex Markets
    EFFICIENCY OF MECHANISMS IN COMPLEX MARKETS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Vasileios Syrgkanis August 2014 ⃝c 2014 Vasileios Syrgkanis ALL RIGHTS RESERVED EFFICIENCY OF MECHANISMS IN COMPLEX MARKETS Vasileios Syrgkanis, Ph.D. Cornell University 2014 We provide a unifying theory for the analysis and design of efficient simple mechanisms for allocating resources to strategic players, with guaranteed good properties even when players participate in many mechanisms simultaneously or sequentially and even when they use learning algorithms to identify how to play and have incomplete information about the parameters of the game. These properties are essential in large scale markets, such as electronic marketplaces, where mechanisms rarely run in isolation and the environment is too complex to assume that the market will always converge to the classic economic equilib- rium or that the participants will have full knowledge of the competition. We propose the notion of a smooth mechanism, and show that smooth mech- anisms possess all the aforementioned desiderata in large scale markets. We fur- ther give guarantees for smooth mechanisms even when players have budget constraints on their payments. We provide several examples of smooth mech- anisms and show that many simple mechanisms used in practice are smooth (such as formats of position auctions, uniform price auctions, proportional bandwidth allocation mechanisms, greedy combinatorial auctions). We give algorithmic characterizations of which resource allocation algorithms lead to smooth mechanisms when accompanied by appropriate payment schemes and show a strong connection with greedy algorithms on matroids.
    [Show full text]
  • Signaling in a Global Game: Coordination and Policy Traps
    Signaling in a Global Game: Coordination and Policy Traps George-Marios Angeletos Massachusetts Institute of Technology and National Bureau of Economic Research Christian Hellwig University of California, Los Angeles Alessandro Pavan Northwestern University This paper introduces signaling in a global game so as to examine the informational role of policy in coordination environments such as currency crises and bank runs. While exogenous asymmetric in- formation has been shown to select a unique equilibrium, we show that the endogenous information generated by policy interventions leads to multiple equilibria. The policy maker is thus trapped into a We are grateful to the editor, Nancy Stokey, and two anonymous referees for suggestions that greatly helped us improve the paper. For comments we thank Daron Acemoglu, Andy Atkeson, Philippe Bacchetta, Gadi Barlevy, Marco Bassetto, Olivier Blanchard, Ricardo Caballero, V. V. Chari, Eddie Dekel, Glenn Ellison, Paul Heidhues, Patrick Kehoe, Robert Lucas Jr., Narayana Kocherlakota, Kiminori Matsuyama, Stephen Morris, Bala`zs Szentes, Jean Tirole, Muhamet Yildiz, Iva´n Werning, and seminar participants at Athens University of Economics and Business, Berkeley, Carnegie-Mellon, Harvard, Iowa, Lausanne, London School of Economics, Mannheim, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Northwestern, Stanford, Stony Brook, Toulouse, University of California at Los Angeles, University of Pennsylvania, the Federal Reserve Banks of Boston, Cleveland, and Minneapolis, the 2002 annual meeting of the Society for Economic Dynamics, the 2002 Universita´PompeuFabra workshop on coordination games, the 2003 Centre for Economic Policy Research Euro- pean Summer Symposium in International Macroeconomics, and the 2003 workshop of the Stanford Institute for Theoretical Economics. We also thank Emily Gallagher for excellent editing assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Interests, Evidence and Games Brian Weatherson
    Interests, Evidence and Games Brian Weatherson Pragmatic encroachment theories have a problem with evidence. On the one hand, the arguments that knowledge is interest-relative look like they will generalise to show that evidence too is interest-relative. On the other hand, our best story of how interests affect knowledge presupposes an interest-invariant notion of evidence. The aim of this paper is to sketch a theory of evidence that is interest-relative, but which allows that ‘best story’ to go through with minimal changes. The core idea is that the evidence someone has is just what evidence a radical interpreter says they have. And a radical interpreter is playing a kind of game with the person they are interpreting. The cases that pose problems for pragmatic encroachment theorists generate fascinating games between the interpreter and the interpretee. They are games with multiple equilibria. To resolve them we need to detour into the theory of equilibrium selection. I’ll argue that the theory we need is the theory of risk- dominant equilibria. That theory will tell us how the interpreter will play the game, which in turn will tell us what evidence the person has. The evidence will be interest- relative, because what the equilibrium of the game is will be interest-relative. But it will not undermine the story we tell about how interests usually affect knowledge. 1 Encroachment, Reduction and Explanation I will start with an argument for a familiar disjunctive conclusion: either knowledge is interest-relative, or scepticism is true. The argument will resemble arguments to the same disjunctive conclusion in Hawthorne (2004) and Fantl and McGrath (2009).
    [Show full text]
  • Common Belief Foundations of Global Games∗
    Common Belief Foundations of Global Games Stephen Morris Hyun Song Shin Muhamet Yildiz Princeton University Bank for International Settlements M.I.T. April 2015 Abstract This paper makes two related contributions to the study of Global Games. First, for general type spaces, it characterizes rationalizable actions in terms of the properties of the belief hierarchies and shows that there is a unique rationalizable action played whenever there is approximate common certainty of rank beliefs, defined as the probability the players assign to their payoff parameters being higher than their opponents’. We argue that this is the driving force behind selection results for the specific type spaces in the global games literature. Second, applications of global games often assume players’payoff parameters are derived from common and idiosyncratic terms with normal distributions. This paper analyzes the alternative case that these terms have fat-tailed distributions. If the common component has a thicker tails, then there is common certainty of rank beliefs, and thus uniqueness and equilibrium selection. If the idiosyncratic terms has thicker tails, then there is approximate common certainty of payoffs, and thus multiple rationalizable actions. 1 Introduction Complete information games often have many equilibria. Even when they have a single equilibrium, they often have many actions that are rationalizable, and are therefore consistent with common certainty of rationality. The inability of theory to make a prediction is problematic for economic applications of game theory. Carlsson and van Damme (1993) suggested a natural perturbation of complete information that gives rise to a unique rationalizable action for each player. They introduced the idea of “global games”–where any payoffs of the game are possible and each player observes the true payoffs of the game with a small amount of noise.
    [Show full text]
  • Selfish Routing and Wavelength Assignment Strategies with Advance
    Computer Communications 35 (2012) 366–379 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Computer Communications journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/comcom Selfish routing and wavelength assignment strategies with advance reservation in inter-domain optical networks ⇑ Francesco Palmieri a, , Ugo Fiore b, Sergio Ricciardi c a Seconda Università degli Studi di Napoli, Dipartimento di Ingegneria dell’Informazione, Via Roma 29, 81031 Aversa (CE), Italy b Università degli Studi di Napoli Federico II, CSI, Complesso Universitario Monte S. Angelo, Via Cinthia, 80126 Napoli, Italy c Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya (UPC), Departament d’Arquitectura de Computadors (DAC), Carrer Jordi Girona 1–3, 08034 Barcelona, Catalunya, Spain article info abstract Article history: The main challenge in developing large data network in the wide area is in dealing with the scalability of Received 1 February 2011 the underlying routing system. Accordingly, in this work we focus on the design of an effective and scal- Received in revised form 28 July 2011 able routing and wavelength assignment (RWA) framework supporting advance reservation services in Accepted 13 October 2011 wavelength-routed WDM networks crossing multiple administrative domains. Our approach is moti- Available online 20 October 2011 vated by the observation that traffic in large optical networks spanning several domains is not controlled by a central authority but rather by a large number of independent entities interacting in a distributed Keywords: manner and aiming at maximizing their own welfare. Due to the selfish strategic behavior of the involved Wavelength-routing entities, non-cooperative game theory plays an important role in driving our approach. Here the domi- RWA Multi-commodity network congestion nant solution concept is the notion of Nash equilibria, which are states of a system in which no partici- games pant can gain by deviating unilaterally its strategy.
    [Show full text]