Catena Operations for Unified Dependency Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Catena Operations for Unified Dependency Analysis Catena Operations for Unified Dependency Analysis Kiril Simov and Petya Osenova Linguistic Modeling Department Institute of Information and Communication Technologies Bulgarian Academy of Sciences Bulgaria {kivs,petya}@bultreebank.org Abstract to its syntactic analysis. On the other hand, a uni- fied strategy of dependency analysis is proposed The notion of catena was introduced origi- via extending the catena to handle also phenomena nally to represent the syntactic structure of as valency and other combinatorial dependencies. multiword expressions with idiosyncratic Thus, a two-fold analysis is achieved: handling the semantics and non-constituent structure. lexicon-grammar relation and arriving at a single Later on, several other phenomena (such means for analyzing related phenomena. as ellipsis, verbal complexes, etc.) were The paper is structured as follows: the next formalized as catenae. This naturally led section outlines some previous work on catenae; to the suggestion that a catena can be con- section 3 focuses on the formal definition of the sidered a basic unit of syntax. In this paper catena and of catena-based lexical entries; sec- we present a formalization of catenae and tion 4 presents different lexical entries that demon- the main operations over them for mod- strate the expressive power of the catena formal- elling the combinatorial potential of units ism; section 5 concludes the paper. in dependency grammar. 2 Previous Work on Catenae 1 Introduction The notion of catena (chain) was introduced in Catenae were introduced initially to handle lin- (O’Grady, 1998) as a mechanism for representing guistic expressions with non-constituent structure the syntactic structure of idioms. He shows that and idiosyncratic semantics. It was shown in a for this task there is need for a definition of syntac- number of publications that this unit is appropri- tic patterns that do not coincide with constituents. ate for both - the analysis of syntactic (for exam- He defines the catena in the following way: The ple, ellipsis, idioms) and morphological phenom- words A, B, and C (order irrelevant) form a chain ena (for example, compounds). One of the impor- if and only if A immediately dominates B and C, tant questions in NLP is how to establish a connec- or if and only if A immediately dominates B and B tion between the lexicon and the text dimension in immediately dominates C. an operable way. At the moment most investiga- In recent years the notion of catena revived tions focus on the representation and analysis of again and was applied also to dependency rep- the text dimension. resentations. Catenae have been used success- We first employed catenae when modeling mul- fully for the modelling of problematic language tiword expressions in Bulgarian within the relation phenomena. (Gross 2010) presents the problems lexicon - text (Simov and Osenova, 2014). En- in syntax and morphology that have led to the couraged by the promising results, we continued introduction of the subconstituent catena level. our research on how to exploit catenae as a uni- Constituency-based analysis faces non-constituent fied strategy for dependency analysis. In the paper structures in ellipsis, idioms, verb complexes. we use examples mostly from Bulgarian and to a Apart from the linguistic modelling of language lesser extend from English, but our approach is ap- phenomena, catenae have been used in a number plicable to other languages, as well. of NLP applications. (Maxwell et al., 2013), for In this piece of research we pursue both issues example, presents an approach to Information Re- mentioned above. On the one hand, we show in a trieval based on catenae. The authors consider formal way how the lexicon representation maps the catena as a mechanism for semantic encoding 320 Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Dependency Linguistics (Depling 2015), pages 320–329, Uppsala, Sweden, August 24–26 2015. root iobj con. conj In order to model the variety of phenomena subj det and characteristics encoded in a dependency gram- cc mar we extend the catena with partial arc and John bought and ate an apple node labels. We follow the approach taken in rootC rootC rootC CoNLL shared tasks on dependency parsing repre- conj senting for each node its word form, lemma, part det cc of speech, extended part of speech, grammatical John bought and ate an apple features (and later – semantics). This provides a flexible mechanism for expressing the combinato- Figure 1: A complete dependency tree and some rial potential of lexical items. In the following def- of its catenae. inition all grammatical features are represented as POS tags. Let us have the sets: LA — a set of POS tags1, which overcomes the problems of long-distance LE — a set of lemmas, WF — a set of word paths and elliptical sentences. The employment of forms, and a set of dependency tags D (ROOT catenae in NLP applications is additional motiva- ∈ D). Let us have a sentence x = w , ..., w .A tion for us to use it in the modelling of the interface 1 n is a directed tree T = between the treebank and the lexicon. tagged dependency tree (V, A, π, λ, ω, δ) where: Terminology note: an alternative term for catena is treelet. It has been used in the area of ma- 1. V = 0, 1, ..., n is an ordered set of nodes chine translation as a unit for translation transfer { } that corresponds to an enumeration of the (see (Quirk et al., 2005)). Their definition is equiv- words in the sentence (the root of the tree has alent to the definition of catena. Also (Kuhlmann, index 0); 2010) uses treelet for a node and its children (if any). In the paper we resort to the term catena 2. A V V is a set of arcs. For each node ⊆ × because it is closer to the spirit of the issues dis- i, 1 i n, there is exactly one arc in A: ≤ ≤ cussed here. i, j A, 0 j n, i = j. There is h i ∈ ≤ ≤ 6 exactly one arc i, 0 A; 3 Formal Definition of Catena h i ∈ In this section we define the formal presentation 3. π : V 0 LA is a total labelling func- − { } → 2 of the catena as it is used in syntax and in the tion from nodes to POS tags . π is not de- lexicon. Here we follow the definition of catena fined for the root; provided by (O’Grady, 1998) and (Gross, 2010): 4. λ : V 0 LE is a total labelling func- a catena is a word or a combination of words − { } → tion from nodes to lemmas. λ is not defined directly connected in the dominance dimension. for the root; In reality this definition of catena for dependency trees is equivalent to a subtree definition. Fig. 1 5. ω : V 0 WF is a total labelling func- depicts a complete dependency tree and some of − { } → tion from nodes to word forms. ω is not de- its catenae. Notice that the complete tree is also fined for the root; a catena itself. With “rootC ” we mark the root of the catena. It might be the same as the root of 6. δ : A D is a total labelling function for → the complete tree, but also might be different as arcs. Only the arc i, 0 is mapped to the label h i in the cases of “John” and “an apple”. Following ROOT ; (Osborne et al., 2012) we prefer to use the notion of catena to that of dependency subtree or treelet 7. 0 is the root of the tree. as mentioned above. We aim to utilize the notion 1In the formal definitions here we use tags as entities, but of catena for several purposes: representation of in practice they are sets of grammatical features. words and multiword expressions in the lexicon, 2In case when we are interested in part of the grammatical their realization in the actual trees expressing the features encoded in a POS tag we could consider p as a set of different mappings for the different grammatical features. It analysis of sentences as well as for representation is easy to extend the definition in this respect, but we do not of derivational structure of compounds in the lexi- do this here. 321 We will hereafter refer to this structure as a form like in: “they spilled the beans” and “he spills parse tree for the sentence x. The node 0 does the beans”. Thus, the catena in the lexicon will not correspond to a word form in the sentence, but be underspecified with respect to the grammatical plays the role of a root of the tree. features and word form for the verb. Let T = (V, A, π, λ, ω, δ) be a tagged root dependency tree. A directed tree G = dobj (VG,AG, πG, λG, ωG, δG) is called dependency clitic catena of T if and only if there exists a mapping Vpi Pp Nc ψ : V V 3 such that: G → – си очите 1. A A, the set of arcs of G; затварям си око G ⊆ shut one’s eyes 2. π π is a partial labelling function from G ⊆ nodes of G to POS tags; Realization 1: 3. λ λ is a partial labelling function from root G ⊆ C nodes to lemmas; dobj iobj pobj 4. ω ω is a partial labelling function from clitic G ⊆ nodes to word forms; Nc Pp Vpi R Nc Очите си затваряха пред фактите 5. δG δ is a partial labelling function for arcs. око си затварям пред факт ⊆ eyes one’s shut at facts A directed tree G = (VG,AG, πG, λG, ωG, δG) is a dependency catena if and only if there exists Realization 2: a dependency tree T such that G is a dependency root subj catena of T .
Recommended publications
  • Gapping: in Defense of Deletion
    Gapping: In Defense of Deletion Elizabeth Coppock Northwestern University 1 Introduction Gapping refers to the following type of construction: (1) [α John likes caviar] and [γ Mary beans]. Typically, Gapping involves two such conjoined clauses, where the second clause contains no pronounced verbal material, as in (1). Following usual terminology, I call the missing material the Gap, the first clause (e.g. α) the antecedent clause, the second clause (e.g. γ) the gapped clause, and the pronounced elements of the gapped clause remnants. Assuming that the Gap is present somehow in the syntax, we have three potential analyses, depending on the nature of the Gap. We may interpret it as (i) a null pro-form, (ii) a deleted element, or (iii) a trace of movement. I immediately rule out possibility (i), following Hankamer and Sag (1976), who argue that Gaps are Surface Anaphors as opposed to Deep Anaphors (i.e. null pro-forms), based on their Island sensitivity and the fact that they require a linguistic antecedent. The second idea (deletion) is as old as the term Gapping. The first detailed investigation of the phenomenon was in Rosss 1967 dissertation, where he coined its name, and gave a deletion analysis. In 1976, Sag suggested that the remnants A'-move out of the gapped clause before deletion, preserving the hypothesis that operations (such as deletion) affect entire constituents. My proposal is essentially Sags, differing significantly only in the assumption that remnants adjoin to VP, rather than at the sentence level, as in (2).1 (2) John likes caviar, and [VP Mary1 [VP beans2 [VP t1 likes t2 ] ] ]].
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting and Defining Connections in Dependency Structures Sylvain Kahane
    Interpreting and defining connections in dependency structures Sylvain Kahane To cite this version: Sylvain Kahane. Interpreting and defining connections in dependency structures. 5th international conference on Dependency Linguistics (Depling), Aug 2019, Paris, France. hal-02291673 HAL Id: hal-02291673 https://hal.parisnanterre.fr//hal-02291673 Submitted on 19 Sep 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Interpreting and defining connections in dependency structures Sylvain Kahane Modyco, Université Paris Nanterre & CNRS [email protected] Abstract This paper highlights the advantages of not interpreting connections in a dependency tree as combina- tions between words but of interpreting them more broadly as sets of combinations between catenae. One of the most important outcomes is the possibility of associating a connection structure to any set of combinations assuming some well-formedness properties and of providing a new way to define de- pendency trees and other kinds of dependency structures, which are not trees but “bubble graphs”. The status of catenae of dependency trees as syntactic units is discussed. 1 Introduction The objective of this article is twofold: first, to show that dependencies in a dependency tree or a similar structure should not generally be interpreted only as combinations between words; second, to show that a broader interpreta- tion of connections has various advantages: It makes it easier to define the dependency structure and to better under- stand the link between different representations of the syntactic structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – a Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1
    Thomas Groß Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – A Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1 Abstract The Modern Hebrew (MH) desiderative construction must obey four conditions: 1. A subordinate clause headed by the clitic še= ‘that’ must be present. 2. The verb in the subordinate clause must be marked with future tense. 3. The grammatical properties genus, number, and person tend to be specified, i.e. if the future tense affix is underspecified, material tends to appear that aids specification, if contextual recovery is unavailable. 4. The units of form that make up the constructional meaning of the desiderative must qualify as a catena. A catena is a dependency-based unit of form, the parts of which are immediately continuous in the vertical dimension. The description of the individual parts of the desiderative must address trans-, pre-, and suffixes, and cliticization. Catena-based morphology is representational, monostratal, dependency-, construction-, and piece-based. 1. Purpose, means and claims The main purpose of this paper is to analyze the Hebrew desiderative construction. This construction is linguistically interesting and challenging for a number of reasons. 1. It is a periphrastic construction, with fairly transparent compositionality. 2. It is transclausal, i.e. some parts of the construction reside in the main clause, and others in the subordinated clause. The complementizer is also part of the construction. 3. The construction consists of more than one word, but it does not qualify as a constituent. Rather the construction cuts into words. 4. Two theoretically 1 I want to thank Outi Bat-El (Tel Aviv University) and three anonymous reviewers for their help and advice.
    [Show full text]
  • Clitics in Dependency Morphology
    Clitics in Dependency Morphology Thomas Groß Aichi University, Nagoya, Japan [email protected] tured in much the same fashion as sentences was Abstract proposed first in Williams (1981), and further discussed in the famous “head-debate” between Clitics are challenging for many theories of grammar Zwicky (1985a) and Hudson (1987). In contem- because they straddle syntax and morphology. In most porary morphological theories that attempt to theories, cliticization is considered a phrasal pheno- inform syntax (predominantly within the genera- menon: clitics are affix-like expressions that attach to tive framework) such as Di Sciullo (2005) and whole phrases. Constituency-based grammars in par- the theory of Distributed Morphology (Halle and ticular struggle with the exact constituent structure of such expressions. This paper proposes a solution Marantz 1993, Embick and Noyer 2001, 2007, based on catena-based dependency morphology. This Harley and Noyer 2003, Embick 2003), words theory is an extension of catena-based dependency are now seen as hierarchically structured items. syntax. Following Authors et.al. (in press), a word or Seen in the light of this development, it is time a combination of words in syntax that are continuous for dependency grammar (DG) to make up for its with respect to dominance form a catena. Likewise, a neglect of morphological matters. The assess- morph or a combination of morphs that is continuous ment by Harnisch (2003) that the development of with respect to dominance form a morph catena. Em- a dependency-based morphology requires imme- ploying the concept of morph catena together with a diate attention is accurate.
    [Show full text]
  • An Asymmetry in Voice Mismatches in VP-Ellipsis and Pseudogapping
    An asymmetry in voice mismatches in VP-ellipsis and pseudogapping Jason Merchant University of Chicago [email protected] Final revision for Linguistic Inquiry, March 29, 2007 VP-ellipsis and pseudogapping in English show a previously unnoticed asymmetry in their tolerance for voice mismatch: while VP-ellipsis allows mismatches in voice between the elided VP and its antecedent, pseudogap- ping does not. This difference is unexpected under current analyses of pseu- dogapping, which posit that pseudogapping is a kind of VP-ellipsis. I show that this difference falls out naturally if the target of deletion in the two cases differs slightly: in VP-ellipsis, a node lower than Voice is deleted, while in pseudogapping a node containing Voice is deleted. This analysis further- more accounts for a new observation concerning the distribution of floated quantifiers in these two constructions as well.1 1Thanks to Kirsten Gengel, Kyle Johnson, and the two LI reviewers for very helpful comments. 1 1 Voice mismatches It is well known that VP-ellipsis in English tolerates mismatches between the voice of the elided constituent and that of its antecedent, in both directions. Typical examples are those in (1) and (2) (the (a) examples from Kehler 2002:53; see also Sag 1976:17, 75, Dalrymple et al. 1991, Hardt 1993, Johnson 2001, and Arregui et al. to appear for further examples, discussion, and qualifications). (1) Passive antecedent, active ellipsis a. This problem was to have been looked into, but obviously nobody did. <look into this problem> b. The system can be used by anyone who wants to.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting and Defining Connections in Dependency Structures
    Interpreting and defining connections in dependency structures Sylvain Kahane Modyco, Université Paris Nanterre & CNRS [email protected] Abstract This paper highlights the advantages of not interpreting connections in a dependency tree as combina- tions between words but of interpreting them more broadly as sets of combinations between catenae. One of the most important outcomes is the possibility of associating a connection structure to any set of combinations assuming some well-formedness properties and of providing a new way to define de- pendency trees and other kinds of dependency structures, which are not trees but “bubble graphs”. The status of catenae of dependency trees as syntactic units is discussed. 1 Introduction The objective of this article is twofold: first, to show that dependencies in a dependency tree or a similar structure should not generally be interpreted only as combinations between words; second, to show that a broader interpreta- tion of connections has various advantages: It makes it easier to define the dependency structure and to better under- stand the link between different representations of the syntactic structure. We will focus on the possible syntactic combinations (what combines with what), without considering the fact that combinations are generally asymmetric, linking a governor to a dependent. We use the term connection to denote a dependency without the governor-depen- dency hierarchy. Section 2 presents the notions of combination and connection, which are based on the notion of catena (Osborne et al. 2012). The properties of the set of catenae are studied and used to define an equivalence relation on the set of combinations, which is used to define the connections.
    [Show full text]
  • What VP Ellipsis Can Do, and What It Can't, but Not Why*
    What VP Ellipsis Can Do, and What it Can’t, * but not Why Kyle Johnson University of Massachusetts Amherst VP Ellipsis is the name given to instances of anaphora in which a missing predicate, like that marked by “)” in (2), is able to find an antecedent in the surrounding discourse, as (2) does in the bracketed material of (1). (1) Holly Golightly won’t [eat rutabagas]. (2) I don’t think Fred will ), either. We can identify three sub-problems which a complete account of this phenomenon must solve. (3) a. In which syntactic environments is VP Ellipsis licensed? b. What structural relation may an elided VP and its antecedent have? c. How is the meaning of the ellipsis recovered from its antecedent? These tasks tend to run together, as we shall see; but there is no immediate harm in treating them separately. 1. LICENSING THE ELLIPSIS The first of the problems presents itself with pairs such as (4). (4) I can’t believe Holly Golightly won’t eat rutabagas. a. I can’t believe Fred won’t ), either. b. *I can’t believe Fred ), either. These contrasts are typically thought to involve licensing conditions that the environment to the left of the ellipsis invoke. The contrast between (4a) and (4b), for instance, indicates that the ellipsis site must be in construction with, or perhaps governed by, a member of “Aux,” where these can be understood to be just those terms that are able occupy the highest of the functional projections which clauses are made up of. The modal, won’t, is an Aux, as is the infinitival to and the auxiliaries have, be and do in (5).
    [Show full text]
  • The Syntax of Comparative Constructions : Operators, Ellipsis
    Julia Bacskai-Atkari The Syntax of Comparative Constructions Operators, Ellipsis Phenomena and Functional Left Peripheries Universitätsverlag Potsdam Julia Bacskai-Atkari The syntax of comparative constructions Julia Bacskai-Atkari The syntax of comparative constructions Operators, ellipsis phenomena and functional left peripheries Universitätsverlag Potsdam Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.dnb.de/ abrufbar. Universitätsverlag Potsdam 2014 http://verlag.ub.uni-potsdam.de/ Am Neuen Palais 10, 14469 Potsdam Tel.: +49 (0)331 977 2533 / Fax: 2292 E-Mail: [email protected] Zugl.: Potsdam, Univ., Diss., 2014 Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Gisbert Fanselow, Department Linguistik, Universität Potsdam Prof. Dr. István Kenesei, Department English Studies, University of Szeged Datum der Disputation: 25.02.2014 Dieses Werk ist unter einem Creative Commons Lizenzvertrag lizenziert: Namensnennung 4.0 International Um die Bedingungen der Lizenz einzusehen, folgen Sie bitte dem Hyperlink: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/de/ Online veröffentlicht auf dem Publikationsserver der Universität Potsdam URL http://pub.ub.uni-potsdam.de/volltexte/2014/7125/ URN urn:nbn:de:kobv:517-opus-71255 http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:kobv:517-opus-71255 Zugleich gedruckt erschienen im Universitätsverlag Potsdam ISBN 978-3-86956-301-5 Acknowledgements This dissertation could not have been written without the funding pro- vided by the DFG (Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft) through the Collaborative Research Centre SFB-632 (Information structure: The linguistic means for structuring utterances, sentences and texts) at the Linguistics Department at University of Potsdam, where I held a short- term PhD scholarship in 2012/2013 (working in project A1 in Potsdam and partially also in B4 at the Humboldt University of Berlin), and where I am currently employed as a research fellow (project Z).
    [Show full text]
  • Gapping and Stripping
    Gapping and Stripping Gapping and Stripping Kyle Johnson The Oxford Handbook of Ellipsis Edited by Jeroen van Craenenbroeck and Tanja Temmerman Print Publication Date: Dec 2018 Subject: Linguistics, Morphology and Syntax Online Publication Date: Jan 2019 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198712398.013.24 Abstract and Keywords The chapter looks at the main attempts to model two constructions: gapping and strip­ ping. It reviews the ways in which these constructions are similar, exploring the thesis that they both stem from the same underlying process. One of those shared properties is their restriction to coordinations—a restriction that is not found elsewhere in the menagerie of ellipsis constructions. Methods of tying this restriction to the similarly gap­ ping/stripping-specific constraint against embedding the ellipsis or its antecedent are ex­ amined. The chapter focuses on the shortcomings of previous attempts to explain these conditions, and their counter-examples, and points to new directions of analysis that seem promising. Keywords: gapping, stripping, ellipsis, coordination, movement, small conjuncts, large conjuncts 23.1 Introduction THIS chapter looks at two constructions which are sometimes characterized as involving ellipsis. One is known as gapping, a name Ross (1970) suggested. And the other is vari­ ously known as stripping or Bare Argument Ellipsis.1 An example of gapping is (1), and stripping is illustrated by (2). (1) (2) The second conjunct of (1) is understood to have the same verb that the first conjunct has: likes. Similarly, in the second conjunct of (2), there is understood to be both a verb and a subject, each identical to those found in the first conjunct: Jones likes.
    [Show full text]
  • Defining Dependencies (And Constituents)
    Gerdes K., Kahane S. (2013) Defining dependency (and constituency), in K. Gerdes, E. Hajičová, L. Wanner (éds.), Computational Dependency Linguistics, IOS Press. Defining dependencies (and constituents) a b Kim GERDES and Sylvain KAHANE a LPP, Sorbonne Nouvelle, Paris b Modyco, Université Paris Ouest Nanterre Abstract. The paper proposes a mathematical method of defining dependency and constituency provided linguistic criteria to characterize the acceptable fragments of an utterance have been put forward. The method can be used to define syntactic structures of sentences, as well as discourse structures for texts, or even morphematic structures for words. Our methodology leads us to put forward the notion of connection, simpler than dependency, and to propose various representations which are not necessarily trees. We also study criteria to refine and hierarchize a connection structure in order to obtain a tree. Keywords. Connection graph, dependency tree, phrase structure, syntactic representation, syntactic unit, catena Introduction Syntacticians generally agree on the hierarchical structure of syntactic representations. Two types of structures are commonly considered: Constituent structures and dependency structures (or mixed forms of both, like headed constituent structures, sometimes even with functional labeling, see for example Tesnière’s nucleus [34], Kahane’s bubble trees [21], or the Negra corpus’ trees [6]). However, these structures are often rather purely intuition- based than well-defined and linguistically motivated, a point that we will illustrate with some examples. Even the basic assumptions concerning the underlying mathematical structure of the considered objects (ordered constituent tree, unordered dependency tree) are rarely motivated (why should syntactic structures be trees to begin with?). In this paper, we propose a definition of syntactic structures that supersedes constituency and dependency, based on a minimal axiom: If an utterance can be separated into two fragments, we suppose the existence of a connection between these two parts.
    [Show full text]
  • 8 Ellipsis in Construction Grammar 8.1 Introduction
    8 Ellipsis in Construction Grammar Adele E. Goldberg and Florent Perek 8.1 Introduction Ellipsis constructions are formal patterns in which certain syntactic structure that is typically expressed is omitted. Some of the most commonly discussed ellipsis constructions along with an attested example of each are provided in Table 8.1. All examples in quotes within and following Table 8.1 come from the Corpus of Contemporary American English (COCA) (Davis 2008). Table 8.1 Commonly discussed constructions that involve ellipsis Verb phrase ellipsis ‘French kids eat spinach and ours can too.’ Sluicing ‘He said that I was “different.” He didn’t say how.’ Gapping A: ‘You made me what I am today.’ B: ‘And you me.’ Stripping ‘George Greenwell was a patriot but not a fool.’ Comparatives ‘His front teeth seemed to protrude more than Henry remembered.’ Every language balances the need to be expressive with the need to be sufficiently easy to produce. These two major functional principles (described by Goldberg 1995: 67 1 as Maximize Expressive Power and Maximize Economy) give rise to different networks of learned constructions in different languages via general processes of grammaticalization or constructionization (Paul 1889; Hopper and Traugott 2003; Traugott 2014; Bybee et al. 1994; Fried 2009). This chapter emphasizes the shared communicative motivation of ellipsis constructions that leads to cross-linguistic similarities and certain predictable functional constraints (section 8.2), while we also emphasize the fact that ellipsis is licensed by a system of motivated constructions; i.e., learned pairings of form and function. Specific constructions readily capture a range of restrictions on form and function, including those related to semantics, discourse context, register, genre, and dialect.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Types of Ellipsis∗
    Three types of ellipsis∗ Jason Merchant Abstract The term ‘ellipsis’ can be used to refer to a variety of phenomena: syntactic, semantic, and pragmatic. In this article, I discuss the recent comprehensive survey by Stainton 2006 of these kinds of ellipsis with respect to the analysis of nonsententials and try to show that despite his trenchant criticisms and insightful proposal, some of the criticisms can be evaded and the insights incorporated into a semantic ellipsis analysis, making a ‘divide-and-conquer’ strategy to the properties of nonsententials feasible after all. 1. Introduction A character in Carlos Fuentes’s 2002 novel The Eagle’s Throne (trans. Kristina Cordero; Random House: New York, 2006) says with self-disdain and melan- choly (p. 93): Did you know I’ve learned to speak like an Anglo-Saxon, without articles or context? “Exactly.” “Done.” “Nothing.” “Careful.” “Perfect.” ∗This paper owes an enormous debt to a large number of people over the years since I first began working on it, but special mention must be made of Rob Stainton, whose work was the original impetus for it and whose comments at Rutgers and in Paris in 2007 led to numerous improvements. Thanks also to Ernie Lepore, François Recanati, Jason Stanley, and the participants in the Leverhulme Foundation workshop organized by Laurence Goldstein at Canterbury in 2008. “Warned.” “Face consequences.” I say these things, nothing else. As it turns out, such seemingly telegraphic speech is by no means limited to the Anglo-Saxon world. The question is just what such utterances could and do mean ‘without context’ and with, and what exactly a speaker who utters such phrases says, means, and conveys.
    [Show full text]