The Evolution of Imitation Without Cultural Transmission

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Evolution of Imitation Without Cultural Transmission The Evolution of Imitation Without Cultural Transmission Lee Altenberg∗1, Susanne Still1, and Christopher J. Watkins2 1University of Hawai`i at M¯anoa 2Royal Holloway University of London July 22, 2021 Abstract The evolution and function of imitation in animal learning has always been associated with its crucial role in cultural transmission and cultural evolution. Can imitation evolve in the absence of cultural transmission? We investigate a model in which imitation is unbundled from cultural transmission: an organism's adult phenotype is plastically altered by its juvenile experiences of genetically determined juvenile traits within its co- hort, and the only information transmitted between generations is genetic. Transmission of phenotypic information between generations is precluded by the population being semelparous with discrete, non-overlapping gen- erations. We find that during a period of directional selection towards a phenotypic optimum, natural selection favors modifiers which cause an organism to bias its plastic phenotype in the direction opposite to the mean phenotype of the population. As the population approaches the phenotypic optimum and shifts into stabilizing selection, selection on the modifier reverses and favors strong imitation of the population mean. Imitation can become so strong that it results in \genotype-phenotype disengagement" (Gonzalez et al., 2017) or even \hyper-imitation"|where the adult phenotype overshoots the mean phenotype. Hyper-imitation produces an evolutionary pathology, where the phenotype is driven away from the optimum, resulting in a drop in mean fitness, and the collapse of imitation. Repeated cycles of hyper-imitation and its collapse are observed. Genetic constraints on hyper-imitation will prevent these cycles. In a model of purifying selection for an extreme phenotype, selection for anti-imitation continues even at a arXiv:2107.09761v1 [q-bio.PE] 20 Jul 2021 mutation-selection balance. These theoretical outcomes are all novel evolutionary and biological phenomena, and we discuss their implications. Keywords: anti-imitation, cliff-edged fitness function, frequency- dependent selection, modifier gene, phenotypic plasticity, social learning ∗[email protected] 1 1 Introduction Imitation is regarded as the core capability that enables cultural transmission and evolution, and conversely, cultural transmission is regarded as the principal function of imitation. Imitation can be considered as a form of phenotypic plasticity in which the development of an organism's phenotype is sensitive to the phenotypes of other organisms. Imitation, in order to evolve as an adaptation, needs to confer a selective advantage upon the imitator. The question arises as to why it would be adaptive to imitate the states of other organisms. The classical proposed mechanisms are (1) the imitator can discriminate in the choice of models or behaviors to imitate, and can select the more adaptive among them (selective transmission), or (2) imitation is of conspecifics who have undergone individual learning in their development, which makes their behaviors more adaptive than the imitator's default state (adaptive learning), and thus imitation can avoid costs of trial-and- error learning (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman, 1973; Richerson and Boyd, 1978; Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman, 1983). This nearly universal bundling of imitation with the other processes of se- lective transmission and individual learning puts it in a box which limits our understanding of exactly what imitation is capable of doing in evolutionary dy- namics. The way to develop a more full understanding of imitation is to go outside the box and break it out of this bundle. Gonzalez et al. (2017) have initiated this unbundling by asking whether selective transmission and adaptive learning are necessary for the evolution of imitation. They investigate whether imitation could evolve in the absence of selective transmission and adaptive learning. They find a counterexample in a model where (1) imitators choose without bias the model individual to imitate, and (2) their imitated phenotype remains unimproved through any kind of learning during their lifetime. Under specific population dynamic conditions (a Moran model with oblique cultural transmission and strong viability selection) imitation evolves with high likeli- hood in the absence of selective transmission or adaptive learning. Additionally, they find that when cultural transmission evolves, it irreversibly displaces ge- netic information as the dominant mode of inheritance. In the current work, we unbundle imitation even further by removing cultural transmission from the dynamics. As in Gonzalez et al. (2017) we suppose that there is neither selective transmission nor adaptive individual learning. Their model instantiates cultural transmission through oblique transmission (Cavalli- Sforza and Feldman, 1981) in which juveniles imitate the phenotypes of adults and then exhibit phenotypes which can themselves be imitated by later gen- erations. This makes the adult phenotype a channel of transmission separate from the genotype. Here, we strip away cultural transmission by preventing any imitation of phenotypes that were themselves imitations. Imitation is restricted to one-shot sampling of genetically determined phenotypes of juveniles by ju- veniles. The adult phenotypes that result from imitation cannot themselves be further imitated; it is \acquired variation", but not culturally transmitted (Boyd and Richerson, 1983). This eliminates the phenotype as a pool of transmitted information separate from the genotype. The only communication between gen- erations is genetic transmission. A common term used almost synonymously with imitation is social learn- ing, where the focal phenotype is behavior. Because there is nothing in our 2 treatment that restricts the phenotype to behavior, we will not speak of so- cial learning specifically here, but it should be understood that it is included within the more general category of phenotypic plasticity. It should also be understood that under the umbrella of \imitation" we include copying and em- ulation. Charbonneau and Bourrat (2021) point out that these distinctions depend on the level of course-graining applied to behavior. Our simple model here considers the phenotype at the most coarse-grained level where no inner structure is distinguished. We make no assumptions at all about the perceptual or cognitive level at which imitation occurs. Imitation in our model could be considered (Matthew Zefferman, personal communication) to be horizontal transmission (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman, 1981) in that juveniles collect information on other organisms in their gen- erational cohort, and this information affects their phenotype. We preclude this horizontally transmitted information from being transmitted to future genera- tions | it is terminal | so it cannot produce cultural evolution. This removal of horizontal transmission from its usual context of cultural transmission is therefore another unbundling to be found in our model. Lastly, we do not provide imitation as a ready-made form of genetic variation. To do so would be to create a form of mutational bias (Yampolsky and Stoltzfus, 2001) that could artefactually boost the evolvability of the trait. Imitation in nature involves multiple chains of information processing from sensory systems to effector systems (with the possible exception of prions, in which folding could be considered to be direct imitation). For a single mutation to produce an offspring with fully formed imitation from a parent with no imitation seems biologically unlikely. Instead, we here assume that: 1. an organism receives a perceptual signal about the phenotypes of its con- specifics; 2. this perceived signal is used by the organism's developmental system to plastically shape its adult phenotype, 3. this plastic shaping is drawn from a set of genetically determined pheno- typic plasticity functions; and 4. mutation in the space of these possible functions is incremental and not biased toward imitation. The phenotypic plasticity function is modeled as a quantitative trait parameter that may range over a continuum going from no effect, to imitation, to what we call \anti-imitation", in which the perceptual signal received by the organism causes its phenotype to develop in the opposite direction the phenotype that produced the signal. It should be clarified here that anti-imitation is not analogous to anti- conformism (Boyd and Richerson, 1985; Liberman et al., 2020; Denton et al., 2020). Conformism and anti-conformism are defined as forms of frequency- dependent transmission bias. Anti-imitation is unrelated to transmission bias, being the phenotypic response to a model, not the choice of the model. Anti- conformism is a form of imitation where there is transmission bias toward im- itating less-frequent phenotypes. Anti-imitation, in contrast, is a response of the organism to a model wherein it plastically alters its metric phenotype in a direction opposite to that of the model. 3 We suppose that organisms have a quantitative genetic trait which is ex- pressed early in development. Juvenile organisms gather sensory information about the quantitative trait as expressed by the juveniles in their cohort. A phenotypic plasticity function then combines the organism's own juvenile quan- titative trait with this population information to determine the organism's adult phenotype. Natural selection acts only on this adult phenotype after all plas- tic development
Recommended publications
  • The Evolution of Dispersal in Random Environments and the Principle of Partial Control
    The Evolution of Dispersal in Random Environments and The Principle of Partial Control Lee Altenberg [email protected] Abstract If a genotype is distributed in space and its fitness varies with location, then selection will McNamara and Dall (2011) identified novel relationships change the spatial distribution of the genotype between the abundance of a species in different environ- through its effect on population demography. ments, the temporal properties of environmental change, This process can accumulate genotype members and selection for or against dispersal. Here, the mathemat- in locations to which they are well suited. This ics underlying these relationships in their two-environment accumulation by selection is the multiplier effect. model are investigated for arbitrary numbers of environ- ments. The effect they described is quantified as the It is possible, they discover, for the `multiplier effect’ to fitness-abundance covariance. The phase in the life cycle reverse | for there to be an excess of the population in where the population is censused is crucial for the impli- the worst habitats | when there is very rapid environ- cations of the fitness-abundance covariance. These rela- mental change. The environmental change they model tionships are shown to connect to the population genetics is a Markov process where are large number of patches literature on the Reduction Principle for the evolution of switch independently between two environments that pro- genetic systems and migration. Conditions that produce duce different growth rates for a population of organ- selection for increased unconditional dispersal are found to isms. They find that for moderate rates of environmental be new instances of departures from reduction described change, populations will have higher asymptotic growth by the \Principle of Partial Control" proposed for the evo- rates if they reduce their rate of unconditional disper- lution of modifier genes.
    [Show full text]
  • Implications of the Reduction Principle for Cosmological Natural Selection
    Implications of the Reduction Principle for Cosmological Natural Selection Lee Altenberg Associate Editor of BioSystems; Ronin Institute; [email protected] Smolin (1992) proposed that the fine-tuning problem for parameters of the Standard Model might be accounted for by a Darwinian process of universe reproduction — Cosmological Natural Selection (CNS) — in which black holes give rise to offspring universes with slightly altered parameters. The laws for variation and inheritance of the parameters are also subject to CNS if variation in transmission laws occurs. This is the strategy introduced by Nei (1967) to understand genetic transmission, through the evolutionary theory of modifier genes, whose methodology is adopted here. When mechanisms of variation themselves vary, they are subject to Feldman’s (1972) evolutionary Reduction Principle that selection favors greater faithfulness of replication. A theorem of Karlin (1982) allows one to generalize this principle beyond biological genetics to the unknown inheritance laws that would operate in CNS. The reduction principle for CNS is illustrated with a general multitype branching process model of universe creation containing competing inheritance laws. The most faithful inheritance law dominates the ensemble of universes. The Reduction Principle thus provides a mechanism to account for high fidelity of inheritance between universes. Moreover, it reveals that natural selection in the presence of variation in inheritance mechanisms has two distinct objects: maximization of both fitness and faithful inheritance. Tradeoffs between fitness and faithfulness open the possibility that evolved fundamental parameters are compromises, and not local optima to maximize universe production, in which case their local non-optimality may point to their involvement in the universe inheritance mechanisms.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolvability Suppression to Stabilize Far-Sighted Adaptations
    Evolvability Suppression to Stabilize Lee Altenberg Information and Computer Sciences Far-Sighted Adaptations University of Hawai’i at Manoa Honolulu, HI [email protected] Abstract The opportunistic character of adaptation through natural Keywords selection can lead to evolutionary pathologies—situations in which traits Evolvability, metapopulation, hierarchies, evolve that promote the extinction of the population. Such cheats, far-sighted pathologies include imprudent predation and other forms of habitat overexploitation, or the tragedy of the commons, adaptation to temporally unreliable resources, cheating and other antisocial behavior, infectious pathogen carrier states, parthenogenesis, and cancer, an intraorganismal evolutionary pathology. It is known that hierarchical population dynamics can protect a population from invasion by pathological genes. Can it also alter the genotype so as to prevent the generation of such genes in the first place, that is, suppress the evolvability of evolutionary pathologies? A model is constructed in which one locus controls the expression of the pathological trait, and a series of modifier loci exist that can prevent the expression of this trait. It is found that multiple evolvability checkpoint genes can evolve to prevent the generation of variants that cause evolutionary pathologies. The consequences of this finding are discussed. 1 Introduction Adaptation through natural selection is an opportunistic process, in that it is driven by the selective forces of the immediate moment upon the individual organism. Yet traits that provide immediate advantage to the individual may be detrimental to the population or species, or detrimental over longer time scales. This has been understood since Darwin. Conversely, traits may impose an immediate disadvantage to the individual, yet be advantageous to the population or species, or advantageous over longer time scales.
    [Show full text]
  • G. P. Wagner and L. Altenberg, Complex Adaptations and The
    Perspective: Complex Adaptations and the Evolution of Evolvability Gunter P. Wagner; Lee Altenberg Evolution, Vol. 50, No. 3. (Jun., 1996), pp. 967-976. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0014-3820%28199606%2950%3A3%3C967%3APCAATE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-T Evolution is currently published by Society for the Study of Evolution. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ssevol.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Mar 17 12:37:59 2008 EVOLUTION INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF ORGANIC EVOLUTION PUBLISHED BY THE SOCIETY FOR THE STUDY OF EVOLUTION Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Editorial Commentaries on a Selection of Marc Feldman’S TPB Papers Lee Altenberg A, Nicole Creanza B, Laurel Fogarty C, Lilach Hadany D, Oren Kolodny E, Kevin ∗ N
    Theoretical Population Biology 129 (2019) 4–8 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Theoretical Population Biology journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/tpb Commentary Some topics in theoretical population genetics: Editorial commentaries on a selection of Marc Feldman's TPB papers Lee Altenberg a, Nicole Creanza b, Laurel Fogarty c, Lilach Hadany d, Oren Kolodny e, Kevin ∗ N. Laland f, Laurent Lehmann g, Sarah P. Otto h, Noah A. Rosenberg e, , Jeremy Van Cleve i, John Wakeley j a Information and Computer Sciences, University of Hawai`i at Manoa,¯ Honolulu, HI 96822, USA b Department of Biological Sciences, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, TN 37232, USA c The UCL Centre for Computation, Mathematics and Physics in the Life Sciences and Experimental Biology, University College London, London, WC1E 6BT, United Kingdom d Department of Molecular Biology & Ecology of Plants, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv, 6997801, Israel e Department of Biology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, USA f School of Biology, University of St. Andrews, St. Andrews, Fife KY16 9TH, United Kingdom g Department of Ecology and Evolution, Université de Lausanne CH-1015, Switzerland h Department of Zoology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC V6T 1Z4, Canada i Department of Biology, University of Kentucky, Lexington, KY 40506, USA j Department of Organismic and Evolutionary Biology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138, USA article info a b s t r a c t Article history: This article consists of commentaries on a selected group of papers of Marc Feldman published in Theoret- Received 22 February 2018 ical Population Biology from 1970 to the present. The papers describe a diverse set of population-genetic Available online 26 December 2018 models, covering topics such as cultural evolution, social evolution, and the evolution of recombination.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolvability and Robustness in Artificial Evolving
    Evolvability and Robustness in Artificial Evolving Systems: Three Perturbations ∗ June 2, 2014 Guest Editor: Lee Altenberg, Senior Fellow, The KLI, Klosterneuburg, Austria [email protected] This special issue focuses on two emergent properties of artificial evolutionary sys- tems: evolvability and robustness. The three papers presented here expand the subject in distinct directions—two dealing with robustness, and one with evolvability. Short- and long-term evolution depends on the variational properties of the sys- tems: how changes to their structure map to changes in their behavior. Robustness and evolvability are key variational properties that themselves show evolutionary dynam- ics. This journal’s focus is on artificial evolutionary systems that are active—which take inputs from their environment and act on them to produce their behavior. Active systems are an especially rich domain for the evolution of robustness and evolvability because the size and structure of their data objects are often open-ended. Evolvability and robustness were never part of the classical ‘Modern Synthesis’ which melded Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection with Mendel’s theory of heredity. The reason that evolvability was not an issue was because it was presumed at the outset: empirical experiences with quantitative genetics and selective breeding produced a consensus that phenotypic variation was effectively like a gas which could flow into any selective bottle; e.g. as Francisco Ayala wrote in 1978, “The fact that ar- tificial selection works almost every time it is attempted indicates there is genetic vari- ation in populations for virtually every characteristic of the organism” [3]. It was with the advent of evolutionary computation—the attempt to solve engineering problems by mimicking Darwinian evolution and Mendelian genetics—that it became widely clear that evolvability could not be taken for granted, but was in fact the primary design challenge for evolutionary algorithms.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution in Changing Environments: Modifiers of Mutation, Recombination, and Migration
    Evolution in changing environments: Modifiers of mutation, recombination, and migration Oana Carjaa,1, Uri Libermanb, and Marcus W. Feldmana,1 aDepartment of Biology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305-5020; and bSchool of Mathematical Sciences, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel Contributed by Marcus W. Feldman, September 13, 2014 (sent for review June 20, 2014; reviewed by Lee Altenberg and Lilach Hadany) The production and maintenance of genetic and phenotypic di- because, when the selective environment varies between positive versity under temporally fluctuating selection and the signatures and negative epistasis, the linkage disequilibrium is often of the of environmental changes in the patterns of this variation have opposite sign to the current epistasis. This lag between epistasis been important areas of focus in population genetics. On one hand, and linkage disequilibrium leads to a mismatch between hap- periods of constant selection pull the genetic makeup of popula- lotypes that are most fit and those that are more common, and tions toward local fitness optima. On the other, to cope with recombination should be favored because it breaks apart the cur- changes in the selection regime, populations may evolve mecha- rently maladapted allele combinations and combines alleles that nisms that create a diversity of genotypes. By tuning the rates at might constitute a fitter haplotype in the future (14, 17, 22, 23). which variability is produced—such as the rates of recombination, Environmental fluctuations can also affect the evolution of the mutation rate. In bacteria, stress can increase the mutation rate mutation, or migration—populations may increase their long-term by inducing mutagenic mechanisms such as the SOS transcrip- adaptability.
    [Show full text]
  • AI-Generating Algorithms, an Alternate Paradigm for Producing General Artificial Intelligence
    AI-GAs: AI-generating algorithms, an alternate paradigm for producing general artificial intelligence Jeff Clune Uber AI Labs, University of Wyoming Abstract Perhaps the most ambitious scientific quest in human history is the creation of general artificial intelligence, which roughly means AI that is as smart or smarter than humans. The dominant approach in the machine learning community is to attempt to discover each of the pieces that might be required for intelligence, with the implicit assumption that at some point in the future some group will com- plete the Herculean task of figuring out how to combine all of those pieces into an extremely complex machine. I call this the “manual AI approach.” This paper describes another exciting path that ultimately may be more successful at produc- ing general AI. It is based on the clear trend from the history of machine learning that hand-designed solutions eventually are replaced by more effective, learned solutions. The idea is to create an AI-generating algorithm (AI-GA), which it- self automatically learns how to produce general AI. Three Pillars are essential for the approach: (1) meta-learning architectures, (2) meta-learning the learning algorithms themselves, and (3) generating effective learning environments. While work has begun on the first two pillars, little has been done on the third. Here I argue that either the manual or AI-GA approach could be the first to lead to gen- eral AI, and that both are worthwhile scientific endeavors irrespective of which is the fastest path. Because both approaches are roughly equally promising, and be- cause the machine learning community is mostly committed to the engineered AI approach currently, I argue that our community should shift a substantial amount of its research investment to the AI-GA approach.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolutionary Reduction Principle for Linear Variation in Genetic
    The Evolutionary Reduction Principle for Linear Variation in Genetic Transmission Lee Altenberg ∗ University of Hawai‘i at Manoa † October 24, 2018 Abstract The evolution of genetic systems has been analyzed through the use of modifier gene models, in which a neutral gene is posited to control the transmission of other genes under selection. Analysis of modifier gene models has found the manifesta- tions of an “evolutionary reduction principle”: in a population near equilibrium, a new modifier allele that scales equally all transition probabilities between different genotypes under selection can invade if and only if it reduces the transition prob- abilities. Analytical results on the reduction principle have always required some set of constraints for tractability: limitations to one or two selected loci, two alleles per locus, specific selection regimes or weak selection, specific genetic processes being modified, extreme or infinitesimal effects of the modifier allele, or tight link- age between modifier and selected loci. Here, I prove the reduction principle in the absence of any of these constraints, confirming a twenty-year old conjecture. The proof is obtained by a wider application of Karlin’s Theorem 5.2 (1982) and its extension to ML-matrices, substochastic matrices, and reducible matrices. Keywords: evolution; evolutionary theory; modifier gene; recombination rate; mu- tation rate; spectral analysis; reduction principle; Karlin’s theorem; ML-matrix; essentially non-negative matrix. arXiv:0806.2181v1 [q-bio.PE] 13 Jun 2008 1 Introduction Darwinian evolution occurs through the interaction of two fundamental processes: (1) natural selection, i.e. differential survival and reproduction; and (2) genetic transforma- tion, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • The Principle of Partial Control in Reaction-Diffusion Models for the Evolution of Dispersal
    Manuscript submitted to Website: http://AIMsciences.org AIMS' Journals Volume X, Number 0X, XX 200X pp. X{XX THE PRINCIPLE OF PARTIAL CONTROL IN REACTION-DIFFUSION MODELS FOR THE EVOLUTION OF DISPERSAL Lee Altenberg Abstract. Studies using reaction-diffusion models for the evolution of disper- sal have classified their behavior in terms of the categories of conditional vs. unconditional dispersal, and the operators of diffusion, nonlocal diffusion, ad- vection, and spatial heterogeneity of growth rates. Recent results on resolvent positive operators reveal a different basis to classify their behavior: it focuses on the form of variation in the operators rather than the form of the opera- tors themselves. When the variation consists of equal scaling of all dispersal and advection operators, selection favors reduced dispersal. But other forms of variation in the operators may select for increased dispersal. When variation has only partial control over the operators it may act effectively as though it were directed toward fitter habitats. The principle of partial control provides a heuristic for variation that favors increased dispersal. While some results for the classification of variation that produces departure from reduction have been obtained for finite matrices, the general classification problem remains open for both finite and infinite dimensional spaces. 1. Introduction. A great deal of progress has been made recently in understand- ing the selective forces that shape the evolution of dispersal in heterogeneous en- vironments over continuous space. Dispersal on continuous space is modeled by reaction-diffusion equations. The evolution of dispersal is analyzed in reaction- diffusion models by examining the fate of genetic variation for the dispersal op- erators.
    [Show full text]
  • Canalization and Robustness - Evolutionary Biology - Oxford Bibliog
    Canalization and Robustness - Evolutionary Biology - Oxford Bibliog... http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-978019994... Canalization and Robustness Thomas Flatt, Günter Wagner LAST MODIFIED: 27 JUNE 2018 DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780199941728-0109 Introduction Canalization describes the phenomenon whereby particular genotypes exhibit reduced phenotypic sensitivity or variation (i.e., increased robustness) in response to mutations and/or to environmental changes relative to other genotypes. Canalization is a variational property of genotypes: it implies a reduced potential or propensity of the phenotype, produced by this genotype, to vary in response to genetic or environmental change. The terms “canalization,” “robustness” and “buffering” are typically used interchangeably; today, “robustness” is perhaps more commonly used than “canalization.” The concept of canalization was first introduced by Conrad Hal Waddington in the 1940s; around the same time, Ivan Ivanovich Schmalhausen came up with essentially the same concept (see Books and Early History of the Canalization Concept). Their main conjecture was the existence of a special kind of stabilizing selection, so-called canalizing selection, which favors genotypes that deviate least from the trait optimum (e.g., the fitness optimum), by selecting for genetic mechanisms that suppress phenotypic variation caused by mutations (genetic canalization) or by environmental perturbations or changes (environmental canalization). The concept of canalization is closely related to the phenomenon of genetic assimilation, that is, the idea that previously hidden, cryptic genetic variants can become phenotypically expressed following an environmental or genetic perturbation and increase in frequency by selection. General Overviews Early experimental evidence for the existence of canalization and genetic assimilation is reviewed in depth by Scharloo 1991, the first comprehensive review paper in the field.
    [Show full text]
  • Modularity in Evolution: Some Low-Level Questions ∗
    Modularity in Evolution: Some Low-Level Questions ∗ Lee Altenberg Information and Computer Sciences University of Hawai‘i at Manoa Honolulu, HI U.S.A. Internet: [email protected] Copyright c 2004 by Lee Altenberg Abstract Intuitive notions about the advantages of modularity for evolvability run into the problem of how we parse the organism into traits. In order to resolve the “question of multiplicity”, there needs to be a way to get the human observer out of the way, and define modularity in terms of physical processes. I will offer two candidate ideas towards this resolution: • the dimensionality of phenotypic variation, and • the causal screening off of phenotypic variables by other phenotypic variables. With this framework, the evolutionary advantages that have been attributed to mod- ularity do not derive from modularity per se. Rather, they require that there be an “alignment” between the spaces of phenotypic variation, and the selection gradients that are available to the organism. Modularity may facilitate such alignment, but it is not sufficient; the appropriate phenotype-fitness map in conjunction with the genotype- phenotype map is also necessary for evolvability. 1 The Question of Multiplicity A good deal of work in recent years has shown that the structure of the genotype-phenotype map is of fundamental importance to the process of evolution. The variational properties ∗Chapter 5 in Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Complex Natural Systems, Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, editors. MIT Press, 2005. 1 2 Lee Altenberg of the genotype-phenotype map—how genetic variation maps to phenotypic variation (Al- tenberg, 1994a, 1995; Wagner & Altenberg, 1996)—largely determine whether mutations and recombination can generate the sequence of phenotypes with increasing fitness that produce adaptation.
    [Show full text]