Firenze University Press Aisthesis www.fupress.com/aisthesis

The idea of substantive arts

Citation: D. Alvargonzález (2021) The idea of substantive arts. Aisthesis 14(1): David Alvargonzález 135-151. doi: 10.36253/Aisthesis-11912 University of Oviedo (Spain) Copyright: © 2021 D. Alvargonzález. This [email protected] is an open access, peer-reviewed arti- cle published by Firenze University Press (http://www.fupress.com/aisthe- Abstract. The Spanish Gustavo Bueno coined the expression “substantive sis) and distributed under the terms of arts” to refer to those arts that do not serve any immediate, mundane or practical pur- the Creative Commons Attribution pose. In this paper, I briefly present this idea and put forward a definition of the sub- License, which permits unrestricted stantive arts as an alternative to those used until now. Starting from the assumption use, distribution, and reproduction that since the end of the 18th century there has been a set of arts that have their own in any medium, provided the original substantivity, I expound on certain criteria widely used as distinctive features to define author and source are credited. the substantive arts. I subsequently put forward an alternative intensional criterion to Data Availability Statement: All rel- characterize the substantive arts. To end, I draw some corollaries following from the evant data are within the paper and its application of this criterion. Supporting Information files. Keywords: fine arts, definition, substantive arts, distinctive features. Competing Interests: The authors have declared that no competing inter- ests exist.

INTRODUCTION

In this paper, I make the supposition that the idea of ​​substan- tive arts emerged at the end of the 18th century and in the first half of the 19th century to designate arts that ceased to serve practical worldly interests external to them. Having reached their own auton- omy, they apparently would have no other meaning than the aes- thetic enjoyment of their own content. Such art has been called fine art, noble art, pure art, useless art, aesthetic art, contemplative art and superfluous art. I prefer “substantive arts”, coined by the Span- ish philosopher Gustavo Bueno (Bueno [2000a]), since it best reflects the fact that these arts no longer conceive of themselves as servants of some other cultural institution – thus ceasing to be deemed as adjective arts – but are self-understood as endowed with their own substantivity.

In the first section, I take up Paul Oskar Kristeller’s thesis that the emancipation of these arts came at the end of a long histori- cal process that did not culminate until the 18th century (Kristel- ler [1951], [1952]). The arts began as adjective arts serving the pur-

Aisthesis. Pratiche, linguaggi e saperi dell'estetico 14(1): 135-151, 2021 ISSN 2035-8466 (online) | DOI: 10.36253/Aisthesis-11912 136 David Alvargonzález poses of religion, politics, the army, the interests In the third section, I draw certain corollaries of specific social classes, morality and entertain- following the proposed criteria to characterize the ment, and were gradually emancipated from these substantive arts. adjective functions. Theories of art in antiquity, the Middle Ages and the Renaissance sought to understand the arts in historical moments insofar 1. THE IDEA OF SUBSTANTIVE ARTS as they were adjectives serving other institutions, Paul Oskar Kristeller argued that the fine arts but they ceased to be applicable once emancipat- are recent in origin, which he located in 18th-cen- ed, since their autonomy enabled expansion in tury Western Europe (Kristeller [1951], [1952]). unforeseen directions. I will comment briefly on As his thesis goes, in classical antiquity and the some of the most influential theories in the arts Middle Ages the aesthetic qualities of artworks that have been put forward to account for the new were not separated from other practical functions reality of the substantive arts. This review does typical of the techniques also sustaining that the not intend to make a detailed critique of all such artworks that today we place within the group of theories, but simply to place my definition within fine arts were dispersed and classified in highly the context of the others. heterogeneous groups. Poetry, grammar and rhet- oric appeared together, whereas music was always The second section lays out an alternative pro- accompanied by mathematics and astronomy and posal that starts by recognizing that an intensional the visual arts were considered purely technical definition of the arts is possible. While extensional and artisanal: painters were associated with phar- definitions list everything falling under the defi- macists, sculptors with goldsmiths and architects nition by enumerating the extension of the set, with masons and carpenters. In the Renaissance, intensional definitions specify the necessary and the visual arts were linked with geometry, per- sufficient conditions to fall under such definition spective and anatomy, and were championed so by indicating the internal content of the defined that painters, sculptors and architects could be concept. The set A = (1, 3, 5, 7, 9) can be defined emancipated from artisans and grouped into what either by listing the items (extensionally) or by Vasari called arti del disegno. The development giving its distinctive characteristic (intension- of modern sciences in the 17th and 18th centu- ally): “odd natural numbers less than ten”. In this ries led to a progressive separation of the sciences paper, I hold that the substantive arts are a species (geometry, optics, astronomy) from the arts, pav- within the genus of techniques that have certain ing the way for the appearance of the modern pre- special distinctive characteristics. Contrary to for- Romantic system of the arts, such as Batteux’s five malist theories, I argue that artwork and art per- fine arts (1746): music, poetry, painting, sculpture formances can never achieve total disconnection and dance. For Batteux, architecture and elo- from other parts of the world and that the purpose quence were “mixed arts” since they pursue both of the substantive arts is not autonomous or self- utility and aesthetic pleasure (Kristeller [1951], referential, but depends on that connection with [1952]). the world external to the arts. This connection is first genetic and then structural since it supposes According to Wilcox and Murphy, in the early that there is a more or less close analogy between 19th century Benjamin Constant, Victor Cousin works of art and these other parts of the world. and Théophile Gautier first used the formula of If so, based on the theory of analogy proposed “art for art’s sake”, albeit with different meanings, by David Alvargonzález, the substantive arts ful- contending that the arts have no other purpose fill the two functions typical of analogies: to ana- than their very own cultivation and that all pur- lyze this analogous world and to explore ways to poses pervert art (Wilcox [1953]; Murphy [2018]). extend and vary it freely (Alvargonzález [2020]). The idea of substantive arts 137

The arts were defined as an end in themselves, as The expansion of the substantive arts invali- “pure art”, as the free, independent, autonomous dated the classical ideas used to characterize the construction of specific works, as superfluous, adjective arts as a way to understand the now non-useful, non-utilitarian, contemplative arts emancipated arts. Characterizing substantive removed from the contingencies of everyday life. works of art as bearers of positive aesthetic val- In my view, as introduced by the Spanish philos- ues (what we could call the “aestheticist” theory of opher Gustavo Bueno (Bueno [2000a]), the label art) ceased to be effective for three reasons. First- “substantive arts” has the advantage of focusing ly, because aesthetic values, especially beauty, are on the difference between the arts understood as also present in many artifacts and performances serving other institutions and pursuing practical of human etiology having immediate practical purposes external to them (“adjective arts”) and utility. Aesthetic values do​​ not then serve as a dis- the arts self-conceived as sovereign, independent, tinctive feature of the substantive arts since the autonomous and therefore endowed with their deliberate search for aesthetic values ​​can occur own substantivity. My preference for the label in both substantive and servile works of art. Sec- “substantive arts” rests on the drawbacks carried ondly, because aesthetic values ​​also appear as by other alternative denominations. These sub- predicated aesthetic values ​​(not constructed or stantive arts do not always embody the value of acted upon), insofar as we predicate them on the beauty (they are not, therefore, “fine arts”) and works of nature which, however, are not works of may be neutral from an aesthetic point of view substantive art. Thirdly, in some cases the newly (they are not, therefore, always “aesthetic arts”). emancipated substantive arts claimed to culti- Their usefulness can only be evaluated ex post vate negative aesthetic values ​​(deformed, dispro- facto, with which they are not adequately coined portionate, gloomy, grotesque, dirty, disgusting, as “useless”, “contemplative” or “superfluous” arts. rude, clumsy, vulgar, imperfect and incomplete, Nor are they activities to be characterized as more to cite but a few), as Karl Rosenkranz (1853) stud- “noble” or “purer” than others. ied in Aesthetics of Ugliness. On the other hand, the existence of artworks with neutral aesthetic 1.1. Limitations of classical and medieval aesthetic theories values ​​must also be taken into account: Marcel when characterizing the substantive arts Duchamp considered readymades to be appear- ances being beyond good and bad taste. During the long period in which the arts ful- filled adjective functions, there were fundamental- As “mimicry” or “naturalism”, the theory of ly three philosophies accompanying them: art as an imitation or recreation of nature also 1. The idea of ​the arts as bearers of positive aes- reached its limits when it came to the new sub- thetic values: beauty, grace, serenity, pleasure, stantive arts once they entered the field of abstract intensity, balance, virtuosity. This theory was art and tried to cut off any reference to the ordi- defended by , Alberti, and Moses Men- nary figurative world (Osborne [1979]). Futurism, delssohn. surrealism, Dadaism, minimalism and conceptu- 2. The conception of the arts as an imitation of alism are ways of making art that test the classical nature. This theory was formulated by doctrine of imitation. and by Leonardo da Vinci. At the same time as With their emphasis on the participation of the emancipation of what he called “fine arts” specific divine attributes (beauty, truth, good- began, Batteux defined art as the imitation of ness), the metaphysical theories about art found nature selecting the beautiful (Batteux [1746]) their raison d’être in times when the arts were 3. The metaphysical conceptions that the arts adjectives of religion, but they fell from grace once reflected specific attributes of GodSumma ( the arts were emancipated from those liturgical Theologica I, q.5). functions and from such a transcendent genesis. 138 David Alvargonzález

Agnostics, atheists, materialists, positivists and the existence of substantive arts (1) and those that nihilists rejected such metaphysical theories since affirm their existence but deny the possibility of they did not need transcendent hypotheses to jus- defining them (2). Positions (3-6) put forward var- tify the existence of the arts. ious criteria to define them (historical, subjective, aesthetic, formal, metaphysical). To end, position 1.2. A brief consideration of theories about art following (7) includes specific disjunctive definitions and the constitution of the substantive arts position (8) accounts for definitional pluralism, defending that there are different definitions for The arts’ emancipation from their earlier various contexts. The purpose of this classifica- adjective functions generated new proposals tion is not to make an exhaustive analysis of such which sought to characterize this new group of theories, but rather to place the theory advanced fine arts, now understood as substantive, autono- in the second section within a dialectical context mous and removed from any practical purpose to make it intelligible. beyond the cultivation of art itself. While not exhaustively, I will briefly refer to A. Evolutionism and functionalism certain theories that deal with the definition of Evolutionary theories argue that the arts what I call substantive arts. Table 1 includes eight arose in the Paleolithic as a consequence of the situations. The first two deal with those that deny biological evolution leading to the appearance of

Table 1. Definitions of substantive arts.

identification label of the type of definition core thesis authors theory Dissanayake Miller Evolutionism A. There is no All the arts are adjectives and fulfill adaptive, Eibl-Eibesfeldt Cultural and social substantive arts cultural or ideological functions Mattick functionalism Clowney Ziff B. Definition is not We know how to use the word “art” in Skepticism Weitz possible certain contexts Goodman Levinson Historicism Historical definition: connection with Carney C. Extensional previous arts Dickie definition Institutional definition: group of experts Fokt Institutionalism Danto Tolstoi Author’s expression Ducasse D. Intensional, Expressivism Author’s intention Collingwood subjetual definition Experiencism Spectator’s aesthetic experience Croce Beardsley Hanslick, E. Intensional, formal Exclusive consideration of pure aesthetic Formalism Bell, Greenberg, definition forms Zamoyski Novalis The realization of freedom Schopenhauer Schiller F. Intensional, The apprehension of noumenon Hegel Metaphysical theories trascendent definition The phases of the dialectic of the spirit Art as “bringing-into-being” Heidegger Souriau G. Disjunctive Tatarkiewicz, Gaut, Andreev & Kuznetsova Cluster theories C v D v E v ... definition Davies H. Definitional Contextualism A different definition for each context Uidhir & Magnus pluralism The idea of substantive arts 139

Homo sapiens. Since all cultures have practices B. Skepticism and products that we recognize as artistic, evolu- Paul Ziff contended that we must renounce a tionists infer that aesthetic preferences, interests definition of art as a set of characteristics that pro- and capacities are innate and result from natural vides a suite of adequate conditions and settle for and sexual selection (Dissanayake [1992]; Miller reference to some paradigmatic or characteristic [2000]: 258-92). “clear cases” of what is considered a “work of art”. Functionalist theories of art share the com- Ziff highlights the differences between the various mon objective of determining the function of arts, especially between poetry and the visual arts, the arts in each society, culture and historical arguing that the uses of the expression “work of moment so as to explain their origin and their art” are changing, especially in the times of artistic persistence. Ethological and ethnological func- revolutions, and no aesthetician is an oracle capable tionalism studied the role of arts in the pre- of anticipating the future of art. Furthermore, such state societies of our primitive contemporaries: uses, like so many others, depend on the context in Irenaus Eibl-Eibesfeldt argued that the artistic which the expression “work of art” is determined. components of those cultures serve to enhance He concludes that no definition can ever account myths, legends, beliefs and rituals (Eibl-Eibes- for all these heterogeneous uses (Ziff [1953]). feldt [1988]). When applied to historical socie- Morris Weitz argued that the question «What ties, functionalist theories connect the arts to is the nature of art?» cannot be defined in any social, political and economic factors. According manner since a definition of art is logically to Paul Mattick, the institution of the autono- impossible. Taking cues from Wittgenstein, Weitz mous fine arts typical of Western societies in the concluded that there is no set of common prop- last two centuries has a social function as well: erties of art, but only a number of similarities, museums and concert halls are the reliquaries since “art” is an open concept and its conditions where these societies keep the material perfor- of application are amendable and correctable. Art mances of their higher self (Mattick [2003]: 133). is subject to changes, expansions, novel creations, For Clowney, the autonomous fine arts fulfill innovations and originalities. Only in logic and a purely ideological function consisting of dif- mathematics is it possible to establish the condi- ferentiating the domain of the “intellectual” – tions necessary for the application of a concept along with law, morality and philosophy – from (Weitz [1956]). The analytic philosopher Nelson the productive forces of ordinary everyday life Goodman also formulated an anti-essentialist (Clowney [2011]: 316). claim with respect to art. Ordinary knowledge, Evolutionism and functionalism are rel- sciences and the arts are systems of symbols con- evant insofar as they gain an understanding of tributing to understanding the world and requir- the external purposes of the arts in their adjec- ing interpretation in line with various syntactic tive function, as they study pre-state societies and semantic rules (Goodman [1968]; Good- and the uses of the arts prior to the 19th-century man and Elgin [1988]). His attempt to specify in Europe. Their understanding of modern arts the “symptoms of the aesthetic” is not distinctive assumes that their unity or similarity is limited since he recognizes that a work of art can occur to their merely adjective function at the service in which these “symptoms” do not appear (Good- of the sexual selection or the ideology of specific man [1978]: 67-68). Contrary to this position, in elites, whilst undervaluing the production pro- this article I defend that it is possible to propose cesses of ordinary consumer goods. On the con- an intensional definition of the substantive arts. trary, without denying the adjective origin of the arts, in this paper I defend the existence of sub- C. Historicism stantive arts. From a historicist perspective, Jerrold Levin- son also recognized that modern art has no spe- 140 David Alvargonzález cific purpose and «is purely historically consti- ist since, for him, art is an imaginary experience tuted practice» (Levinson [1993]: 414). Historicist through which we express our emotions (Colling- positions argue that the only way to characterize wood [1958]: 142). In Benedetto Croce’s philoso- art is through its connection with other artwork phy, aesthetic intuition grounds all other mental of the past (Levinson [1979], [1989], [1993], [2002]; activity, although intuition cannot be analyzed in Carroll [1988], [1997], Stecker [1990], [2000]). parts. Ordinary intuition is no different than the James Carney advocates for a historicism centered artwork-based intuition, although artists are able on the study of the various styles so as to under- to express their intuitions. Furthermore, artwork- stand the causal influence of the past on the pre- based intuition is created within the spectator’s sent (Carney [1994]: 114). mind. Arts are expressive and thus proximate to Stephen Davies calls this recursive way of human languages (Croce​​ [1902]). The analytic phi- defining substantive art the «cladistic theory of losopher Monroe Beardsley defined a work of art art» due to the resemblance to cladistic theories of based on its capacity to afford an aesthetic expe- biological species (Davies [2012]: 379) and advo- rience (1982, 299), and Richard Kamber defined cates for its utility, while still recognizing that this art as a kind of technique whose intent is to aes- type of theory is indeed incomplete as a definition thetically construct interesting objects, events and of art (Davies [1997], [2004], [2010], [2015]). designs (Kamber [1993]: 316, 319). John Dewey also A theory adjacent to this historicist approach located the core of the idea of art in the idea of is the theory of art as a cultural institution. Once experience and emphasized the continuity between it has been established that the present-day fine everyday experience and the fine arts (Dewey arts have no clear purpose, the only practical way [2005]). Wary that Dewey’s idea of experience was to know what art is would be by reference to what not precise enough to explain the nature of art, an authorized elite or some culturally competent Richard Shusterman recalled that Dewey himself person labels, dubs and honors as art. Applying considered the aesthetic experience to be impos- this criterion, Duchamp’s readymades and War- sible to define (Shusterman [1994]). Following hol’s Brillo Boxes clearly qualify as art. (Dickie Dewey, Mark Johnson has defended that all expe- [1974]; Fokt [2014], [2017]). In this vein, Arthur C. riences, and not just those that have to do with the Danto’s concept of “artword” underlies an institu- arts, have aesthetic dimensions and are, therefore, tionalist theory of art (Danto [1973], [1998]) “aesthetic” (Johnson [2007]). In my view, Johnson As with functionalists, historicist, cladistic and Dewey’s arguments are highly compelling, but and institutionalist interpretations also deny that they imply that the idea of aesthetic experience the modern arts have an objective purpose of does not serve as a distinctive feature to character- their own. To characterize the arts they resort to ize the substantive arts. recursive procedures and deictic, extensional defi- Harold Osborne has argued that the idea of nitions, pointing to institutions either as historical aesthetic experience is a vague and ambiguous processes or as social groups. As already stated, I notion (Osborne [1981], 10). Regarding expres- will defend that an intensional definition of arts is sivism, Osborne considers that, on the one hand, possible. many works of art are neither more nor less expressive than many of the things we do or cre- D. Expressivism and experiencialism ate and, on the other hand, there are many things Leo Tolstoy (1897) formulated the idea of ​​art that express and evoke emotions that we never as an expression of emotions and as the language would classify as works of art (Osborne [1981]: 9). of feelings, and Curt J. Ducasse (1929) worked this idea out, defining aesthetic arts as a skilled E. Formalism objectification, a language of feelings. In a differ- Under the label of formalism, I refer to a ent sense, Collingwood’s idea of ​​art is expressiv- group of authors postulating that everything nec- The idea of substantive arts 141 essary to understanding a work of art is within idea of beauty as divine essence and the imitative itself and, specifically, in its forms, its elements and emanative nature of arts. In the late 5th and and its relationships in space and time. The issues early 6th century CE, Pseudo-Dionysios posited relating to the author, viewers and historical, cul- that truth and beauty coincide and are the cause tural and social contexts are secondary. Eduard of anything beautiful that exists. Hanslick found that music has no content exter- explicitly asserted that the source of all beauty is nal to itself because it is only «tonally moving God and derived the primary standards of beau- forms» (Hanslick [1986]: 29). Similarly, Clive Bell ty (actuality, radiance, proportion and integrity) defined the essence of art as “significant form”, from the mystery of the Trinity. arguing that in painting the only relevant things In the Renaissance, Michelangelo believed are the relationships and harmonies of lines and that visible beauty was the path by which the soul colors (Bell 1913). Clement Greenberg defined reached immortal Beauty, which is the reflection painting as a combination of «flatness, pigment of God himself since the source of all beauty is and shape» (Greenberg [1986]: 86-87). divine. In the 20th century, the stream of art crit- Novalis conceived of art as the vision of God ics grouped under the label of “New Criticism” in Nature, and Schopenhauer elaborated a phi- shared this conception about the disinterested losophy of music in which the arts were pure nature of art and advocated for a pure, autono- forms since they express no specific passion, but mous art freed from any purpose and any exter- rather their general forms. Schiller defined beau- nal influence. Artists such as the writer and paint- ty as freedom and autonomy in appearance and er Stanislav I. Witkiewicz and the sculptor August deemed freedom as something noumenal. In this Zamoyski formulated a formalist theory of art vein, Hegel stated that the distinctive function of (Witkiewicz [1992], Zamoyski [1975]). the arts is to provide a sensuous, individual mani- Arthur Danto has been one of the most inci- festation of the freedom of absolute spirit. Hegel’s sive critics of formalism. For Danto, the aesthetic philosophy of art constitutes the first sub-sec- value of an artwork depends largely on the con- tion of the third part of his philosophy of spirit, text and, therefore, form alone does not make which is devoted to the absolute spirit (the other a work of art. Marcel Duchamp’s readymades sub-sections being about religion and philoso- and Warhol’s Brillo Boxes are examples of “mere phy). Art is the lowest phase in the development things” that, introduced in a specific context, may of the absolute spirit: in an ascendant trajectory, constitute artworks (Danto [1973], [1998]). It is the absolute spirit reaches its self-understanding impossible for Walton to correctly adjudge an art- and spiritual freedom through figurative objects work in the correct categories if we do not know in the arts, through images of faith in religion anything about its origins or its historical context and through pure concepts in philosophy. Far since aesthetic properties do not only depend on removed from Hegelian idealism, in the philoso- shapes, colors or rhythms (Walton 1970). Con- phy of George W. Bertram, the characterization versely, in contexts far from the substantive arts, of the arts as “a practice of freedom” is enigmatic, engineers and illustrators themselves make arti- since such “freedom” seems to reside in the nou- facts implying forms (Osborne [1981]: 9). menal background of the artist’s will (Bertram [2019]: ch. 4). F. Metaphysical theories Étienne Souriau compared the artist to Leib- Metaphysical theories about art, in which the niz’s God, who chooses from among all possi- ideal of beauty pursued by the arts was considered ble worlds to create a concrete and singular work to be of divine origin, were prevalent in Antiq- the existence of which is sufficient for itself and uity and the Middle Ages. Such is the case of the constitutes its own purpose (Souriau [1947]: 50; philosophy of Plotinus (3rd century CE), with his 56). The arts constitute the human experience of 142 David Alvargonzález

God’s “ontogonical” activity since the sculptor, More recently, Andreev and Kuznetsova high- the painter, the poet and the musician perform lighted the main components of art as a complex a task of divine creation (Souriau [1947]: 62-64). conceptual system. The aesthetic attitude includes This not being sufficient, Souriau affirms that the the following: arts, through the sensitive qualia of certain physi- cal bodies, lead us towards an impression of tran- spiritual specificity; semiotic trait; a system of features scendence (Souriau [1947]: 96). In the same vein, associated with usual forms of the social organization Martin Heidegger defined art as “bringing-into of artistic culture; the system of psychological charac- being”, even though such “being” will never be teristics (art as a sphere of personal perception, art as completely revealed (Heidegger [2008]) figurative thinking); nature of activity in art (art as a fundamentally innovative, non-algorithmic activ- Another example of a metaphysical theory of ity); and, finally, a technical attribute, the tendency art is Ayn Rand’s theory whereby art is the rec- to reduce art to a fixed, traditional set of techniques: reation or concretization, in an aesthetic micro- pictorial, sculptural, technique of organizing verbal cosm, of the author’s metaphysical value-judg- texts, etc. (Andreev and Kuznetsova [2019]: 72). ments, the expression and emotional resonance of a “sense of life” that in turn defines as «a pre-con- In my view, the dichotomy between the “sin- ceptual equivalent of metaphysics» (Rand [1975]: gle criterion” and the cluster account is false. The 25). characterization based on genus and difference always makes use of a plurality of criteria, most of G. Eclecticism which are generic (such as criteria I-VIII in Gaut’s The definition of art put forward by Wla- cluster). I do not deny that Gaut’s ten criteria can dyslaw Tatarkiewicz may serve as an illustration be predicated on the arts, but, except for IX and of a disjunctive definition. For Tatarkiewicz, «art X, they are all generic. Irrespective, the disjunc- is a conscious human activity of either reproduc- tive definitions imply the recognition of the lack of ing things, or constructing forms, or expressing unity in the concept of art, of its “equivocity”. This experiences if the product of this reproduction, theory borders on the aforementioned skepticism. construction, or expression is capable of evok- In the second section, I will put forward an inten- ing delight, or emotion, or shock» (Tatarkiewicz sional definition of substantive arts that challenges [1971]: 150). The disjunctive structure of his for- this equivocity; if this proposal is successful, the mula is evident: either imitation, or construction limits of cluster theories can be better appreciated. or expression. Berys Gaut (Gaut [2000], [2005]) held that H. Contextualism art cannot be defined, since the concept of art is Christy M. Uidhir and P.D. Magnus compare a “cluster concept”, and put forward ten criteria the concept of art with the species concept in counting towards an object’s being deemed art: biology: just as there are various concepts (pheno- typic, biological, taxonomic, phylogenetics), they (i) possessing positive aesthetic qualities […]; (ii) propose the formulation of various art concepts, being expressive of emotion; (iii) being intellectually each serving different purposes and useful in spe- challenging; (iv) being formally complex and coherent; cific contexts. Specifically, they put forward four (v) having a capacity to convey complex meanings; (vi) exhibiting an individual point of view; (vii) being concepts of art: an exercise of creative imagination; (viii) being an Historical art: Those artifacts emerging from, artifact or performance that is the product of a high belonging to, embedded in, art-historical tradi- degree of skill; (ix) belonging to an established artis- tions or narratives […], productive for historical tic form; and (x) being the product of an intention to inquiries. make a work of art. (Gaut [2005]: 274) Conventional art: Those artifacts recognized, accepted, targeted, governed by artworld conven- The idea of substantive arts 143 tions, institutions, and practices […], productive tion of the environment in order to accomplish for sociological and anthropological inquiries (as specific purposes Metaphysics( 1033a ff., Nicoma- well as for legal and economic issues). chean Ethics 1140a ff., Physics 192b ff.). The trait Aesthetic art: Those artifacts satisfying some that makes it possible to distinguish a specific aesthetic function; for example, affording some technique from others is always the objective aim aesthetic attitude, experience, interest, value […], pursued: medical techniques seek to cure the productive for value inquiry and certain cognitive infirm, the goal of aeronautical techniques is to inquiries involving perception. transport air cargo, the military techniques aim Communicative art: Those artifacts that are to win wars, and so on. In this paper, I hold that (act as) vehicles for the communication of certain the substantive arts also have purposes and that contents; «for example, representational, semantic, the feature that enables them to be distinguished or expressive content […], productive for certain from the other techniques is precisely the objec- cognitive inquiries involving learning and emo- tive aim that they pursue. Irrespective, I retain tions, as well as for moral evaluation.» (Uidhir the label “substantive arts” since I am interested and Magnus [2011]: 91-92). As with the definitions in underlining that those arts are not adjective constructed using the disjunction of features, the arts. Even though they organize themselves based disjunction of concepts is proof of the inexistence on aims, those aims are not external to them- of a univocal concept. In previous paragraphs, I selves, as psychological, political, religious, mili- have already made some considerations about the tary, social, economic, entertainment and other scope of institutional, historical, and aesthetic def- purposes are. Rather, it is my view that the fine initions. arts can be deemed “substantive” since they have As regards the aesthetics of hermeneutics their very specific aims. My proposal is directly (Adorno [1970], Gadamer [1986]), it is widely opposed to theories positing that arts have no def- accepted that it is not directly focused either on inite purpose (that are “purposiveless”), running categorizing the nature of art or on proposing a from Kant to Dipert (Kant [1790]: §44; Dipert concept of art; rather, it looks to deepen the con- [1993]: 187). templation of specific works for the sake of phe- When talking about aims, the distinction nomenological engagement. must be made between objective aims (finis oper- is) and subjective aims (finis operantis). This dis- tinction appears explicitly formulated in Aquinas 2. THE SUBSTANTIVE ARTS AS A VARIETY OF and in . In Aquinas, the finis operis TECHNIQUES (translated as the aim of the action performed) is 2.1. All techniques and technologies follow objective aims. also called the “natural aim” and is the ultimate The distinction between objective and subjective aims inherent end or goal of human action or output, it is the inner constructive aim. Any act or out- In this section, I assume that we approximate- put always entails a finis operis. Thefinis operan- ly know the extension of the set of substantive tis (translated as the aim of the moral agent) is arts and put forward an intensional definition of also called the “willing aim” and is the subjective the substantive arts that bears the classic format motive, purpose or willing intention of a human of the generus proximus and the specific or dis- agent in acting. Scholastics applied this distinc- tinctive difference. I defend that the substantive tion to the study of human moral actions and arts are a product of human doing and making concluded that bad subjective motives cannot and, therefore, belong to the genus of techniques change a good finis operis, as in the case of the (in which I include technologies). Following Aris- person who gives money to the poor in search of totle’s philosophy, I characterize the techniques as vainglory. Conversely, good subjective motives human practices involving a violent transforma- cannot change a bad finis operis, as in the case 144 David Alvargonzález of compassion-based euthanasia, since God alone 2.2. Proposal for a distinctive intensional criterion of the can dispose of human lives. substantive arts When referring to a historical institution The demarcation criterion that I put forward such as modern substantive art, it seems reason- to differentiate what we call techniques and tech- able to suspect that, if that institution has stayed nologies from what we call substantive arts is alive for several centuries, it must have some as follows: substantive works of art always have objective aims (finis operis), some objective inter- analog contents with respect to other configura- ests that are above the will of certain individual tions and processes of reality, and these analogies subjects. Additionally, if substantive arts can be always imply certain objective exploratory or ana- extensionally differentiated from other proximate lytical purposes. The substantive arts take their institutions (techniques, crafts, decoration, sci- forms from the real world, from the categories of ence, philosophy), it seems possible to hypothesize being (the categories of the natural sciences) and that they should have certain distinctive objective of doing and making (the categories of poiesis and aims. In my view, the idea of “proper function”, human praxis). In the substantive arts, the anal- proposed by Ruth G. Millikan (1987) and applied ogy can affect either the work of art as a whole or by Beth Preston to human-made artifacts (1998: its formal parts. This proposal entails a recogni- 237-38), refers mainly to these distinctive finis tion that the essence of the substantive arts is ulti- operis. Anthropological and historical function- mately cognitive, be it exploratory or analytical. alism is a methodology based on the assumption that there cannot be durable human institution The theory put forward here makes use of the separated from objective aims. Should those aims theory of analogy formulated by Alvargonzález disappear, the institution may be maintained by (Alvargonzález [2020]) whereby the distinctive inertia for a certain time but, if it is not co-opted characteristics of any analogy are as follows: for other aims, it will tend to become a survival of 1. There must be a certain asymmetry between mere archaeological interest, similarly to vestigial the analogues. This asymmetry means that analo- organs in biological evolution. Once the particu- gies can have various purposes depending on the lar aims of the arts disappear as they existed in directionality of the relationship: analogies aim at their adjective moment (religious, military, politi- extrapolation or exploration when moving from cal aims, etc.), those arts now conceived of as sub- a familiar source to a relatively unknown tar- stantive are seen in the need to co-opt new spe- get; their purpose is to analyze reality when they cific aims. make use of specific characteristics of an invented In this paper, insofar as I propose a specific analogue, partially known, to shed light on the finis operis for the substantive arts, I do not mean real source. to say that this purpose excludes the other sub- In an “extrapolative” analogy, the analogy jective aims, which may continue to be present: starts from the most familiar source to the least the artist very often needs to sell his work to live, known target. In the 19th century, physicists drew and whoever finances him pursues other ends. an analogy between the relatively well-known However, this does not exclude the existence of flow of a liquid and the unfamiliar flow of an distinctive or characteristic objective aims in the electric current, to explore the structure of the lat- substantive arts, even though these distinctive ter. Scientists did not know exactly what an elec- purposes may occur in the context of and even tric current was, but they imagined it as liquid through subjective ends. The finis operis may exist flow, such that voltage was aligned with flow pres- without the artist being distinctly conscious of it sure. In the common law system, the familiar pri- and without being able to express it in words. or cases are frequently used in deciding the new ones. The idea of substantive arts 145

The function of an analogy is deemed “ana- and its rejection of external associative connec- lytical” when the less familiar part of the analogy tions, is purely intentional since concepts are also is used to identify and analyze the relevant con- constructions made in the reality external to the stituents of a familiar domain since the former is arts. easier to manipulate or to understand. The experi- In their extrapolative or exploratory role, art- mentation with scale model planes in wind tun- ists start with specific real-world configurations, nels or the maps of a given terrain may serve as whether natural or human, and attempt to explore illustrations of analogies done with an analytical new compositions of parts and morphologies. In purpose. this task, they need not adhere to any special con- 2. The relationship between analogues must be straints, beyond those set by the material determi- on the same level: either it goes from the particu- nants of their art (the canvas in painting, gravity lar to the particular or goes from the general to and the conditions of static balance in architec- the general. The substantive arts do not establish ture and sculpture, and tonality in music). This general or universal principles or theorems since exploratory sense stands out when it is affirmed they are concrete products of human doing. Since that works of substantive art open new worlds (or the analogues always have to be at the same level universes, as is sometimes said). As already stat- of generality, it will be necessary to consider that ed, works of art cannot be segregated from the the works of substantive art are particular con- rest of existing realities as separate, self-referen- structions that present a specific analogy with tial “worlds” or “universes”, and this designation other particular constructions or situations occur- (“worlds”, “universes”) should be understood as ring outside these arts. a hyperbolic way of referring to the exploratory 3. Analogues can be relationships, operations function of the arts. or terms. The analogy between the map and the The exploratory and analytical functions of terrain, like the analogy of realistic painting, is the arts also make it possible to provide positive mainly an analogy of terms and relations, while content to the demand for novel works of art, the analogy between the flight simulator and the since the mere repetition of works based on tradi- real airplane also implies an analogy of opera- tional norms means that these functions are lost. tions, as also happens in the analogy of the theat- The argument that substantive works of art, er or the cinema regarding real life. with their analogical structure with respect to other parts of reality, fulfill an analytical or Leonardo da Vinci indirectly advocated for exploratory objective aim does not imply the the analytical function of the arts insofar as he reciprocal argument that all analogy is a substan- asserted that the purpose of sculpture and paint- tive work of art. The use of analogies is frequent ing was none other than “knowing how to see”. in techniques, in technologies, in the sciences, in Works of art that are allegorical such as a por- philosophy, in law, in religions, in ethical, politi- trait, sculpture, painted landscape or literary work cal and moral practice, in rhetoric, in war and in always involve an analysis of the reality to which many other contexts (Alvargonzález [2020]). In they refer. Frequent is the argument that paint- such contexts, the exploratory and analytical pur- ing supposes a level of analysis of painted reality poses of analogies serve other aims: the aim of the much higher than that of photography, without technical artifact, the purpose of warfare, etc. prejudice to the fact that the latter may, in certain Artifacts and performances that are substan- aspects, be more precise. Connections of external tive art involve analogies with other parts of real- reality to art can include human actions and psy- ity that lie outside the artwork. This is always so chological processes. I defend that the anti-refer- since no artwork is completely self-referential. As entialist ideology accompanying conceptual art, already stated, following functionalism, I suppose with its idea that works of art are self-referential that there can be no enduring, specific human 146 David Alvargonzález institution without objective finality (finis operis). fying demon and Laplace’s demon. For materialist Substantive works of art lack an immediate prac- philosophy, the gods in the Egyptian, Greek and tical purpose in everyday life (and the finis ope- Roman pantheon are fictional entities, but they rantis of the artists are not distinctive of the arts), are not constructions whose essence is a substan- but, insofar as they bear an analogical compo- tive art. Those fictions pursue other aims, such as nent, they must consequently retain the objective the construction of scientific theorems and princi- purposes typical of analogies. Insofar as we have ples, and the operation of the States. already stripped all possible practical purposes and made them autonomous and free of practical 2.3. The difference between the theory of analogy and other commitments, they still have the objective pur- theories of art pose (finis operis) of being analogies since that purpose cannot be shed (they would only lose it if The aforementioned theory of analogy draws they were transcendent works made by God out- away from the theory that puts the essence of art side the world). in the imitation of the works of nature or God. Substantive works of art are realities of human Firstly, it states that the substantive arts occur in etiology. Not having to fulfill an immediate prac- continuity with other highly heterogeneous tech- tical purpose and bearing an exclusively objective niques and technologies the nature of which is not exploratory or analytical function, the activity of always imitative. Secondly, analogy is not imita- the arts is constrained by reality to a much less- tion, but rather a reasoned comparison of config- er extent than in the rest of the techniques and urations and processes used in various contexts to technologies. Accordingly, the formal parts of explore new territories and analyze reality (Alva- the work of art can be chosen, varied and com- rgonzález [2020]). Thirdly, the analogies built by posed with a great deal of freedom. Thus, works the substantive arts do not only take entities in of art conform a “depicted reality” that is always nature (the categories of being) as analogues, but a function of reality, just as a dream relates to also the things and processes made by humans – wakefulness. In this “depicted world” (be it pic- categories that we could call anthropic. torial, sculptural, narrative or cinematographic), The proposed theory acknowledges the pres- the agent does not operate on reality: the depict- ence of positive and negative aesthetic values in ed lion – sculpted, narrated – does not bite. It is the arts, but those same values can be present as a puppet handled by the author, and the depicted constructed values in other human techniques. processes do not have efficient causality: depicted Furthermore, as I have already said, we discern fire does not burn, pistols in cinema do not kill those values as predicated values in the works of and a tempest in music does not drench. nature. At any rate, although this “depicted world” is The proposed theory on substantive arts a sui generis, weak mode of reality, this does not seeks to understand the distinctive features of mean that it can also be the cause of real process- the autonomous arts, but can be retrospectively es. Such is the case of legal fiction, fake news and applied to understanding the artistic content of counterfeits such as the famous Donation of Con- the adjective arts prior to the 18th century. At no stantine. Parallelly, works of art, even if they are time do I deny the phylogenetic relationships of fiction, can have effects, such as the propaganda works of art of any historical moment with their effects in Guernica and Battleship Potemkin. predecessors. Rather, this empirical, historical In any case, the characteristic that works of manner of defining a work of art is purely indica- art (portraits, sculptures, novels, etc.) are fic- tive, deictic and extensional, even though it can tions is not a distinctive feature since it does not be very useful in many contexts. imply that all fictions are artistic fictions. There The philosophy of the substantive arts put for- are also fictions in the sciences: Maxwell’s classi- ward herein is also wholly removed from subjec- The idea of substantive arts 147 tivism since it assumes that works of art are made of being rational, open, human practices embed- from things that are outside and that the work of ded in tradition with many other non-artistic art itself is an intersubjective, external object or activities, such as political, economic, technical, performance. Arts are not conceived of as com- technological and scientific activities, among oth- municative devices, as varieties of languages ​​the ers. Thus, Bertram’s criteria are not distinctive to function of which is representational or expres- substantive arts. The criterion proposed by Alva sive, such as systems of communication (Dilworth Noë, who considers that artworks’ main aims are [2005]). Countering Ayn ​​Rand ([1975]: 25), even confrontation, intervention, subversion and re- though art inevitably involves the viewer, the arts organization, is not distinctive either, although are not sufficiently defined as an act of contempla- it may be constitutive (Noë [2015]: 29). Again, it tion, since many things and processes, both natu- can be argued that political activity can meet all ral and artificial, that are not works of art are also of those purposes without being considered a sub- contemplated. stantive art. Noë puts forward certain similarities Also running counter to formalism, the art- between the arts and philosophy (as «reorgani- analogy theory assumes that works of art are not zational practices») but he does not establish dis- self-referential for two reasons: one, since they tinctive features to understand their differences. necessarily imply reference to the world outside On the contrary, his characterization of artworks the artwork to which they are genealogically and as strange tools to study ourselves and to investi- analogically connected, and two, since they can- gate what makes us human (Noë [2015]: 30; 101) not be understood apart from the anthropic, pur- is excessively restrictive and anthropocentric since sued objective aims and, therefore, apart from it must be taken into account the existence of art- the author and spectators. Following Gadamer, works that have no direct anthropic reference, the nature of works of art is interrogative and analogy or meaning, and contribute to investigate appellative, and their contents could be partially things and processes other than ourselves. enigmatic and open to interpretation (Gadamer [1986]). The theory presented also lies far from Ayn 3. SOME COROLLARIES OF THE PROPOSED Rand’s philosophy, which considers the work of art THEORY as an aesthetic microcosm representing, recreating 3.1. On the uselessness of the theory about the essence of or concretizing a metaphysical view (Rand [1975]: the arts 20, 25). Rather, the artist’s metaphysical value- judgments may be reflected in certain works of art, Making or commenting on a work of art but they are not a distinctive and necessary essen- does not require a proportionate aesthetic theo- tial content of the arts, for there are many works ry about what art is. Knowledge of the objective of art in which such contents are not present. aims of the arts can be completely irrelevant and George W. Bertram defined arts as ration- even detrimental to the artist and the critic. Art- al, human, self-determined, unassured prac- ists whose finis operantis are the inspiration of tices embedded in tradition and related to an God or the ascent to the Absolute Spirit through open future (Bertram [2019]: chp.4). Undoubt- their art may be more motivated for their work edly, substantive arts are rational, open practices than those possessing a non-metaphysical phi- embedded in tradition, but it is not as clear that losophy of art. Critics skeptical about the pos- they are “self-determined practices”, since they sibility of defining art can make many interest- have to be embedded in specific material condi- ing considerations about a particular work of art tions (for example, they depend on the state of while the philosophy of art I have defended here techniques and technologies at each historical could inhibit them from making many of those moment). In any case, arts share the characteristic insightful comments. 148 David Alvargonzález

3.2. If the arts are technical, then it is worth drawing dis- earlier geometric, biological, technical, technologi- tinctions between the arts of poiesis and the arts of praxis cal and other forms. Irrespective, it is interesting to note that there If we take into account the distinction are arts that do not admit the variety of “abstract between techniques of praxis (agere) and poie- art”. Relatively speaking, sculpture, painting, sis (facere), we could also speak by extension of music and dance may lose references to specific practical arts and poietic or productive arts. There morphologies external to the artwork and may are substantive arts requiring the actual execu- lead to abstract sculpture, painting and (non- tion of a process by one or more interpreters, as vocal) music. Literature, theater, vocal music and in theater, music and dance, while there are oth- cinema cannot reach this disconnection. The er arts that give rise to a product that separates function of the works of abstract art will have to itself from its possible interpreters, as in painting, be understood to a greater extent as an explora- sculpture, architecture and literature. Further- tory function such that the substantive work more, this criterion shows us the internal con- of art appears as a construction that invites us nection between the substantive arts and the ser- to explore it, as also happens so often with the vile arts or the earlier adjective arts. Slaves and abstract structures in the formal sciences that lack servants cultivated the servile arts by developing any application in other areas. technical skills, both in the realm of praxis and poiesis. Free men cultivated the liberal arts so as to become wise and virtuous. The substantive arts 3.4. The analogy can affect terms, relationships, and opera- are genetically connected with the servile arts tions: a reinterpretation of Lessing’s criterion and techniques (painting, sculpture, architecture, In Laocoon, Lessing classified the arts based music, dance and theater), for no one considers a on the role that time plays. There are certain wise and virtuous man to be a work of substan- exclusively static arts (plastic arts, especially tive art. Servile arts were also adjective arts since painting) in which time does not play a major they served certain external purposes (religious, role since it is about perceiving a fixed image. On political, military, social, economic, etc.). the contrary, in other arts (singularly, poetry and theater) the succession of the parts of the work is 3.3. If the arts are techniques, then they involve various a constituent part thereof: they are arts that have degrees of destruction and reconstruction of reality to manage time and, therefore, are somehow “nar- rative arts”. In Laocoon, he refers to poetry, but The techniques can be classified based on it seems that the proposed criterion would put the degree of destruction and violence that they music, dance and cinema together with poetry produce in reality, which ranges from absolute and not painting (Lessing [1762]: 66). destruction (hunting, war) to the mere harnessing Lessing’s criterion relates to the procedural of natural processes (a sailing ship, a wind power nature of the work of art. When the process of its station) (Bueno [2000b]). reception is governed only by the viewer, the situ- Works of art can always be broken into for- ation is different than when that process is nar- mal parts such that there is no abstract art in the ratively guided by the artist. In my view, the fun- strict sense. Even the so-called abstract works, damentals of Lessing’s distinction are as follows. where the degree of deconstruction is maximal, In painting and sculpture, the understanding of cannot be made without forms, even though these analogies only requires the consideration of the forms are parts of the result of the destruction of similarities between terms and relations. In litera- the real at various scales, and even if these formal ture, dance and music, it is essential to also keep parts are strangely combined. All arts suppose the in mind the similarities between the operations of analogy, more or less recombined and varied, of the subjects involved (musicians, dancers, narra- The idea of substantive arts 149 tors, dramatic characters) since those arts include Alvargonzález, D., 2020: Proposal of a classification the deployment of a narrative time. of analogies, “Informal Logic”, 40 (1), pp. 109- 137. 3.5. The psychagogical function of the processual arts Andreev, A.L., Kuznetsova, T.V., 2019: How to define art?, “Voprosy Filosofii”, 8, pp. 72-79. In certain arts, the artist leads the viewer to Batteux, C. 1746: The Fine Arts Reduced to a Sin- see, hear and read at all times what the author gle Principle, Oxford University Press, Oxford, imposes. The spectator or reader agrees to be 2015. guided, to be exposed at all times to the stimuli Beardsley, M. C., 1982: The Aesthetic Point of View, that the author wants, to be led by the hand. The Cornell University Press, Ithaca (NY). author manages the audience’s emotions, awak- Bell, C. 1913: Art, Oxford University Press, ens and dulls their desires and alters their feelings Oxford, 1987. and passions, building a narration given in time. Bertram, G. W., 2019: Art as Human Practice. An The author acts a psychagogist, a conductor or Aesthetics, Bloomsbury Academic, London. guider of souls. Bueno, G., 2000a: Estética y filosofía del arte, in The question that should be discussed is Pelayo G. (ed.) Diccionario filosófico, pp. 649- whether or not the psychagogical function of the 677, Pentalfa, Oviedo. arts turns these arts into servile arts at the ser- Bueno, G. 2000b: Televisión: apariencia y verdad, vice of that sentimental drive. On the contrary, it Gedisa, Barcelona. can be defended that they remain substantive arts Carney, J. D., 1994: Defining Art Externally, “The attempting to explore subjective and social con- British Journal of Aesthetics”, 34, pp. 114–23. tents so as to carry out this liberating catharsis, Carrol, N., 1988: Art, practice, and narrative, “Aes- which allows us to take some distance from that thetics and the History of Arts”, 71 (2), pp. psychological and social world. 140-156. The psychagogical function of the arts is a Carrol, N., 1997: Danto’s new definition of art and specification of the aforementioned analytical and the problem of art theories, “British Journal of exploratory functions where the understanding Aesthetics”, 37 (4), pp. 386-392. of specific analogies requires not only consider- Clowney, D., 2011: Definitions of art and fine art’s ing the similarities between terms and relations historical origins, “Journal of Aesthetics and but also between the operations of the involved Art Criticism”, 69 (3), pp. 309-320. subjects. In painting and sculpture, we mostly Collingwood, R. G., 1958: Principles of Art, have terms and relationships and, consequently, Oxford University Press, Oxford. their psychagogical effect is comparatively weak, Croce, B., 1902: Aesthetics as Science of Expression whereas in the narrative arts we have to take and General Linguistic, Macmillan Company, into account the analogy of operations and their New York, 1909. unfolding in time. Accordingly, in those proces- Danto, A. C., 1973: Artworks and Real Things, sual arts, the psychagogical effect is inescapable. “ Th e o r i a”, 39, pp. 1-17. Danto, A. C., 1998: The end of the art: A philo- sophical defense, “History and Theory”, 37 (4), REFERENCES pp. 127-143. Davies, S., 1997: First art and art’s definition. “South- Adajian, T., 2003: On the Cluster Account of Art, ern Journal of Philosophy”, 35 (1), pp. 19-34. “British Journal of Aesthetics”, 43, pp. 379-385. Davies, S., 2004: The cluster theory of art, “British Adorno, T.W., 1970: Aesthetic Theory, transl. by R. Journal of Aesthetics”, 44 (3), pp. 297-300. Hullot-Kentor, University of Minnesota Press, Davies, S., 2010: Philosophical Perspectives on Art, Minneapolis, 1997 Oxford University Press, Oxford. 150 David Alvargonzález

Davies, S., 2015: Defining art and artworks, “Jour- Hanslick, E. 1986: On the Musically Beautiful, nal of Aesthetics and Arts Criticism”, 73 (4), Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis (IN). pp. 375-384. Hegel, G.W.F., 1818-1829: Aesthetics. Lectures on Dewey, J., 1932: Art as Experience, Perigee, New Fine Art, transl. by T.M. Knox, 2 vols., Claren- York, 2005. don Press, Oxford, 1975. Dickie, G., 1974: Art and the Aesthetic: An Insti- Heidegger, M., 1935-36: The origin of the work of tutional Analysis, Cornell University Press, art, in Basic Writings, transl. by D. F. Krell, Ithaca (NY). Harper, New York, 2008, pp. 139-212. Dipert, R. R., 1993: Artifacts, Art Works, and Johnson, M., 2007: The Meaning of the Body: Aes- Agency, Temple University Press, Philadelphia thetics of Human Understanding, University of (PA). Chicago Press, Chicago (IL). Dissanayake, E., 1992: Homo Aestheticus: Were Art Kamber, R., 1993: A Modest Proposal for Defining Comes From and Why, Free Press, New York. a Work of Art, “The British Journal of Aesthet- Ducasse, C. J., 1929: The Philosophy of Art, The ics”, 33, pp. 313–20. Dial Press, New York. Kant, I., 1790: Critique of the Power of Judgement, Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I., 1988: The Biological Founda- Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2000. tions of Aesthetics, in Rentschler, I., Herz- Kristeller, P. O., 1951: The Modern System of the berger, B. and Epstein, D. (eds.) Beauty and the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics, I., Brain: Biological Aspects of Aesthetics, Birkhäu- “Journal of the History of Ideas”, 12 (4), pp. ser, Basel, Switzerland, pp. 29-68. 496-527. Fokt, S., 2014: The Cluster Account of Art: A His- Kristeller, P. O., 1952: The Modern System of the torical Dilemma, “Contemporary Aesthetics”, Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics, II., 12 (1), pp. 1-14. “Journal of the History of Ideas”, 13 (1), pp. Fokt, S., 2017: The cultural definition of art, “Met- 17-46. aphilosophy”, 48 (4), pp. 404-429. Levinson, J., 1979: Defining Art Historically, “The Gaut, B., 2000: “Art” as a Cluster Concept, in Car- British Journal of Aesthetics”, 19, pp. 232-250. roll, N. (ed.), Theories of Art Today, University Levinson, J., 1989: Refining art historically, “Jour- of Wisconsin Press, Madison (WI), pp. 25-44. nal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism”, 47 (1), pp. Gaut, B., 2005: The Cluster Account of Art Defend- 21-33. ed, “The British Journal of Aesthetics”, 45, pp. Levinson, J., 1993: Extending Art Historically, 273–88. “Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism”, 51, Gadamer, H. G.. 1967 and 1977: The relevance of pp. 411–423. the beautiful, in The Relevance of the Beautiful Levinson, J. 2002: The Irreductible Historicality of and other Essays, transl. by N. Walker, Cam- the Concept of Art, “British Journal of Aesthet- bridge University Press, Cambridge, 1986. ics”, 42 (4), pp. 367-379. Goodman, N., 1968: Languages of Art: An Lessing, G. E., 1762-66: Laocoon: or, The Limits of Approach to a General Theory of Symbols, Poetry and Painting, Ridgeway, London, 1836. Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis (IN). Mattick, P., 2003: Art in Its Time: Theories and Goodman, N., 1978: Ways of Worldmaking, Hack- Practices of Modern Aesthetics, Routledge, Lon- ett Publishing Company, Indianapolis (IN). don. Goodman, N., Elgin, C. Z., 1988: Reconceptions in Miller, G., 2000: The Mating Mind: How Sexual Philosophy and Other Arts and Sciences, Rout- Choice Shaped the Evolution of Human Nature, ledge, London. Doubleday, New York. Greenberg, C. 1986: The Collected Essays and Crit- Millikan, R. G., 1987: Language, Thought, and oth- icism, University of Chicago Press, Chicago er Biological Categories: New foundations for (IL). Realism, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA) The idea of substantive arts 151

Murphy, M., 2018: Pure art, pure desire: Changing Tatarkiewicz, W., 1971: What is art? The problem definitions of l’art pour l’art from Kant to Gau- of definition today, “The British Journal of Aes- tier, “Studies in Romanticism”, 47 (2), pp. 147- thetics”, 11 (2), pp. 134-153. 160. Tolstoy, L., 1897: What is art?, Penguin, London, Noë, A., 2015: Strange Tools: Art and Human 1995. Nature, Hill and Wang, New York. Uidhir, C. M., Magnus, P. D., 2011: Art concept Novalis (Georg Friedrich Philipp von Harden- pluralism, “Metaphilosophy”, 42 (1-2), pp. berg), 1802-1846: “Logological Fragments I”. In 83-97. Philosophical Writings, ed. and transl. by M. M. Walton, K.L., 1970: Categories of Art, “The Philo- Stoljar, Suny Press, Albany (NY), 1997. sophical Review”, 79 (3), pp. 334–367. Novalis (Georg Friedrich Philipp von Harden- Weitz, M., 1956: The Role of Theory in Aesthet- berg), 1802-1846: Notes for a Romantic Ency- ics, “Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism”, clopaedia (Das Allgemeine Brouillon), ed. and 15, pp. 27-35. transl. by D. W. Wood, Suny Press, Albany Wilcox, J., 1953: The beginnings of L’art pour l’art, (NY), 2007. “Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism”, 11, Osborne, H., 1979: Abstraction and Artifice in pp. 360-377. Twentieth-Century Art, Clarendon Press, Witkiewicz, S. I., 1992: New forms in painting and Oxford. the misunderstandings arising therefrom, in D. Osborne, H., 1981: What is a work of art?, “The Gerould, (ed.), The Witkiewicz Reader, North- British Journal of Aesthetics”, 21 (1), pp. 3-11. western University Press, Evanston (IL). Preston, B., 1998: Why Is a Wing Like a Spoon? A Zamoyski, A., 1954: “Art and substance”. Lecture Pluralist Theory of Function, “The Journal of delivered at the Philosophical International Philosophy”, 95 (5), pp. 215-254. Congress. Sáo Paulo, in Zamoyski, A. (french Rand, A., 1969-1975: The Romantic Manifesto: transl.), Au-delà du formisme, Collection Slav- A Philosophy of Literature, New American ica-Écrits sur l’art 4, Editions L’Age d’homme, Library, New York. Lausanne, 1975, pp. 11 -197. Rosenkranz, K., 1853: Aesthetics of Ugliness, Ziff, P., 1953: The Task of Defining a Work of Art, Bloomsbury Academic, London, 2015. “Philosophical Review”, LXII, pp. 58-78. Schiller, F., 1795: Letters on the Aesthetic Educa- tion of Man, transl. by Snell R., Dover, Boston (MA), 2004. Schopenhauer, A., 1819: The World as Will and Representation, transl. by R. Aquila, Pearson, New York, 2007. Shusterman, R., 1994: Dewey on experience: Foun- dation or reconstruction?, “The Philosophical Forum”, 26, pp. 137-148. Souriau, E., 1947 : La correspondence des arts. Élé- ments d’esthetique comparée, Flammarion, Par- is. Stecker, R., 1990: The boundaries of art, “British Journal of Aesthetics”, 30, pp. 266-272. Stecker, R., 2000: Is it reasonable to attempt to define art?, in Carroll N. (ed.), Theories of Art, University of Wisconsin Press, Madison (WI), pp. 45-64.