Henry More, 1614-1687 Archives Internationales D'histoire Des Idees

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Henry More, 1614-1687 Archives Internationales D'histoire Des Idees HENRY MORE, 1614-1687 ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDEES INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HIS TORY OF IDEAS 185 HENRY MORE, 1614-1687 A Biography of the Cambridge Platonist by Robert Crocker Founding Directors: P. Dibont (Paris) and R.H. Popkin (Washington University, St. Louis & UeLA) Director: Sarah Hutton (Middlesex University, United Kingdom) Associate-Directors: J.E. Force (Lexington); J.c. Laursen (Riverside) Editorial Board: M.J.B. Allen (Los Angeles); J.R. Armogathe (Paris); A. Gabbey (New York); T. Gregory (Rome); J. Henry (Edinburgh); J.D. North (Oxford); J. Popkin (Lexington); G.A.J. Rogers (Keele); Tb. Verbeek (Utrecht) HENRY MORE, 1614-1687 A BIOGRAPHY OF THE CAMBRIDGE PLATONIST by ROBERT CROCKER University of Australia SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A c.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is availab1e from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-6373-1 ISBN 978-94-017-0217-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-0217-1 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2003 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2003 No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exc1usive use by the purchaser of the work. Dedicated to the memory of my parents, Sir Walter Crocker (1902-2002) and Claire Crocker (1919-2000) Henry More: Frontispiecefrom The Theological Works (London, 1708) CONTENTS Acknowledgements xiii Abbreviations xv Introduction xvii Chapter 1: Early Life and Education 1 1. Grantham, Eton and Cambridge 1 2. Conversion to Platonism 4 3. Early Influences: Gell and Castellio 8 Chapter 2: Psychozoia and the Life ofthe Soul 17 1. The 'Divine Life' and its Goal 17 2. The Allegory ofthe Spiritual Journey 20 Chapter 3: Metaphysics, Psychology and Natural Philosophy in the Psychodia Platonica 29 1. The 'Ogdoas' or Chain ofBeing 29 2. The Psychology of Illumination 34 3. Arguing from Nature 37 Chapter 4: Enthusiasm and the Light Within 45 1. 'A Full but False Persuasion' 45 2. 'Philosophical Enthusiasm' 48 3. 'Political Enthusiasm' 54 X CONTENTS Chapter 5: Plato Democritans: the Ancient Cabbala Revived 63 1. Some Ear1y Discip1es and Friends 63 2. P1atonism and Cartesianism 66 3. Innate Ideas and Incorporea1 Things 70 Chapter 6: The Cupri-Cosmits and the Latitude-Men 79 1. 'The Cupri-Cosmits' 79 2. The Restoration in Cambridge 84 3. Some 'Ru1es to Judge Opinions by' 86 Chapter 7: The Apology ofDr Henry More 93 1. The Grounds for Authority 93 2. The Intelligibi1ity of Doctrine 99 3. The Coherence of Prophecy 104 Chapter 8: The Preexistence of the Soul 111 1. 'A Most Like1y Hypothesis' 111 2. The Reaction against Preexistence 115 3. Preexistence and Providence 119 Chapter 9: A Natural History of the World of Spirits 127 1. A 'True History ofSpirits' 127 2. The Webster-More Debate 133 Chapter 10: The Limits ofMechanism and the Experimental Philosophy of the Royal Society 143 1. The Two Keys ofProvidence 143 2. The Threat of "Nullibism" 145 3. Henry Stubbe and the Royal Society 151 4. Robert Boy1e and the Spirit ofNature 157 Chapter 11: Hylozoism and the Nature ofMaterial Substance 167 1. G1isson's 'Energetic Substance' 167 2. The 'Psychopyrism' of Richard Baxter 170 3. Errant Discip1e: John Finch and his Treatise 176 CONTENTS XI Chapter 12: The Kabbalah and the Quakers: F.M. van Helmont, Anne Conway, van Helmont, and Knorr von Rosenroth 183 1. The Jewish and 'Greek' Cabbalas 183 2. More, Anne Conway and the Quakers 190 Conclusion 199 Bibliography 205 1. Primary Sources 205 2. Secondary Sources 221 Appendix: The Correspondence of Henry More 239 Index 269 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I have been very fortunate to have benefited from the knowledge and advice of some remarkable scholars during the course of my research for this book. Firstly, I owe much to the many kindnesses, wealth of understanding and exemplary scholarship of my former supervisor at Oxford, Charles Webster. It was he who first introduced me to More, and supervised the doctoral thesis out of which this book has developed. I also owe much to the work and friendship of another remarkable scholar, Sarah Hutton. Her kind and persistent encouragement as editor of this series, International Archives of the History of Ideas, led me to pick up, further deve10p and complete this project after several lengthy interruptions. Her growing body of work relating to Anne Conway and the Cambridge Platonists, much of it cited here, has greatly contributed to my understanding of More. To these two long-term influences, I should add my thanks to the following friends and fellow travellers, whose generous conversation and friendship, scholarship and knowledge I have benefited from at various stages along the way, and who have themselves all worked on various projects related to the subject of this book: Stuart Brown, David Dockrill, James Force, Alan Gabbey, John Henry, Scott Mandelbrote, Maggie Pelling, John Rogers, Luisa Simonutti and John Spurr. I must also acknowledge my friends and colleagues in the University of South Australia, who generously funded a sabbatical in 2000, so that I might bring the project to completion. To these names I would also like to thank my wonderful family, and particularly my wife, Meredith, whose love and support has sustained me and given me the confidence to complete what I had begun. ABBREVIATIONS Works by More or his Contemporarie! AA More, An Antidote against Atheisme (1652) Adam & Tannery Adam, Tannery (eds) Oeuvres de Descartes (1964-1974) Apology More, The Apologie of Dr Henry More (1664) Bullough G. Bullough (ed), The Poems of Henry More (1931) CC More, Conjectura Cabbalistica (1653) CSPW More, A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings (1662) Discourses More, Discourses on Several Texts 0/ Scripture (1692) DD More, Divine Dialogues ... (1713: 2 vols in 1) DP More, Democritus Platonissans (1646) EE More, An Account 0/ Virtue ... (1690: trans of EE, 1667) EM More, Enchiridion Metaphysicum (1671) ET More, Enthusiasmus Triumphatus (1656) GMG More, An Explanation of the Grand Mystery of Godliness (1660) Grosart A. Grosart (ed), The Complete Poems of Dr Henry More (1876) IS More, Immortality ofthe Soul (1659) PG More, Praefatio Generalissima, in Opera Omnia (tom.2, 1679) Psychodia More, Psychodia Platonica (1642) pp More, Philosophical Poems (1647) XVI HENRY MORE Nicolson Nicolson (ed), The Conway Letters (ed, S. Hutton, Oxford, 1992) OpOm More, Opera Omnia (3 vols, London, 1675-1679) Smith John Smith, Select Discourses .. (1655) ST Joseph Glanvill, Saducismus Triumphatus, (ed More, 1681) TIS Ralph Cudworth, True Intellectual System of the Universe (1678) Two Treatises More (ed), Two Choice and Useful Treatises ... (1682) TW More, Theological Works (1708) Ward Hutton et al. (eds), Richard Ward: The Life of Henry More (2000) Worthington Diary and Correspondence. (3 vols, Manchester, 1847-86) Other Items AS Annals of Science BJHP British Journal ofthe History of Philosophy BJHS British Journal for the History of Science DNB Dictionary of National Biography (Oxford, 1997-) DSB Dictionary ofScientific Biography (New York, 1981) Hutton S. Hutton (ed), Henry More ... Tercentenary Studies (1990) JHI Journal ofthe History of Ideas JHP Journal ofthe History of Philosophy JWCI Journal ofthe Warburg and Courtauld Institutes NRRS Notes and Records ofthe Royal Society (new series) Peile J. Peile, Biographical Register of Christ's College (2 vols, 1910) PR Philosophical Review Rogers Cambridge Platonism in Philosophical Context (1997) 1 For full titles and publication details, see the Bibliography. INTRODUCTION 'Cambridge Platonism' is not a precise term in intellectual and religious his tory , referring to a broad set of religious and philosophical pre­ occupations, all more or less shared by a loose coalition of thinkers and divines based in seventeenth-century Cambridge. 1 The membership of this group, although never to be fixed with complete confidence, has usually been restricted to the well-known moralist and anti-dogmatic preacher, Benjamin Whichcote,2 his pupils, lohn Smith and Ralph Cudworth, Fellow and Master of Christ's College,3 and Henry More, also a Fellow of Christ's College for most of his life. To this very short and rather unsatisfactory list, with the benefit of hindsight, we might also add with some confidence More's pupil, George Rust, also a Fellow of Christ's and later Bishop of Dromore, and Rust's pupil, Henry Hallywell, a still rather neglected younger 'Platonist' from Christ's College, whose publications closely followed the spirit and ideas of his teachers, Rust and More.4 Further out from this narrowly defined centre were others who shared most, if not all of the ideas and interests of Whichcote, Cudworth, Smith and More. Probably because More alone has left us a fairly comprehensive sampie of his correspondence, we know of at least three men, all his close friends, colleagues and admirers, who shared much of his religious and intellectual disposition, that is lohn Worthington, Thomas Standish and William Outram, 5 whereas we know very little of those who might have played a similar role in the lives of Whichcote, Smith and even Cudworth. To the group we have named, we might also add some younger men, perhaps
Recommended publications
  • The Physician and Witchcraft in Restoration England
    THE PHYSICIAN AND WITCHCRAFT IN RESTORATION ENGLAND by GARFIELD TOURNEY THE YEAR of 1660 witnessed important political and scientific developments in England. The restoration of the monarchy and the Church of England occurred with the return of Charles II after the dissolution of the Commonwealth and the Puritan influence. The Royal Society, after informal meetings for nearly fifteen years, was established as a scientific organization in 1660 and received its Royal Charter in 1662. During the English revolution, and for a short time during the Commonwealth, interest in witchcraft mounted. Between 1645 and 1646 Matthew Hopkins acquired the reputation as the most notorious witch-finder in the history of England.I His activities in Essex and the other eastern counties led to the execution of as many as 200 witches. In Suffolk it is estimated that he was responsible for arresting at least 124 persons for witchcraft, of whom 68 were hanged. The excesses soon led to a reaction and Hopkins lost his influence, and died shortly thereafter in 1646. There then was a continuing decline in witchcraft persecutions, and an increasing scepticism toward the phenomena of witchcraft was expressed. Scepticism was best exemplified in Thomas Hobbes' (1588-1679) Leviathan, published in 1651.2 Hobbes presented a materialistic philosophy, emphasizing change occurring in motion, the material nature of mental activity, the elimination of final causes, and the rejection of the reality of spirit. He decried the belief in witchcraft and the supematural, emphasizing
    [Show full text]
  • Presidential Address
    Empowering Philosophy Christia Mercer COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY Presidential Address delivered at the one hundred sixteenth Eastern Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in Philadelphia, PA, on January 10, 2020. The main goal of my presidential address in January 2020 was to show that philosophy’s past offers a means to empower its present. I hoped to encourage colleagues to make the philosophy we teach and practice more inclusive (both textually and topically) and to adopt a more public- facing engagement with our discipline. As I add these introductory remarks to my January lecture, it is June 2020 and the need to empower philosophy has never seemed more urgent. We’ve witnessed both the tragic death of George Floyd and the popular uprising of a diverse group of Americans in response to the ongoing violence against Black lives. Many white Americans—and many philosophers—have begun to realize that their inattentiveness to matters of diversity and inclusivity must now be seen as more than mere negligence. Recent demonstrations frequently contain signs that make the point succinctly: “Silence is violence.” A central claim of my January lecture was that philosophy’s status quo is no longer tenable. Even before the pandemic slashed university budgets and staff, our employers were cutting philosophy programs, enrollments were shrinking, and jobs were increasingly hard to find. Despite energetic attempts on the part of many of our colleagues to promote a more inclusive approach to our research and teaching, the depressing truth remains:
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy, Religion, and Heterodoxy in the Philosophy of Henry More, Ralph Cudworth, and Anne Conway
    Church History Church History and and Religious Culture 100 (2020) 157–171 Religious Culture brill.com/chrc Philosophy, Religion, and Heterodoxy in the Philosophy of Henry More, Ralph Cudworth, and Anne Conway Sarah Hutton University of York, York, UK [email protected] Abstract Philosophers who hold the compatibility of reason and faith, are vulnerable to the charge of opening the way to atheism and heterodoxy. This danger was particularly acute when, in the wake of Cartesianism, the philosophy of Spinoza and Hobbes neces- sitated a resetting of the relationship of philosophy with religion. My paper discusses three English philosophers who illustrate the difficulties for the philosophical defence for religion: Henry More, Ralph Cudworth, and Anne Conway, for all of whom philo- sophical and religious truth were deeply intertwined. But each of them also subscribed to heterodox religious beliefs. This raises questions of whether there is a direct the rela- tionship between their philosophy and religious heterodoxy—whether they exemplify the charge that philosophy undermines religion, or indeed whether their defence of religion was a cover for heterodoxy. Keywords atheism – heterodoxy – Platonism – Descartes – More – Cudworth – Conway 1 Introduction Accusations of atheism occur relatively frequently in the philosophico-theo- logical polemics of the seventeenth century.1 This is particularly the case with 1 The term “atheism” itself had broader sense than it does today as a blanket term for irreligion © sarah hutton, 2020 | doi:10.1163/18712428-10002002 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the CC BY 4.0Downloaded license. from Brill.com10/01/2021 08:06:06PM via free access 158 hutton Hobbes and Spinoza, but Cartesianism was seen by many as leading to athe- ism.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry More, Richard Baxter, and Francis Glisson's Trea Tise on the Energetic Na Ture of Substance
    Medical History, 1987, 31: 15-40. MEDICINE AND PNEUMATOLOGY: HENRY MORE, RICHARD BAXTER, AND FRANCIS GLISSON'S TREA TISE ON THE ENERGETIC NA TURE OF SUBSTANCE by JOHN HENRY* The nature of the soul and its relationship to the body has always proved problematical for Christian philosophy. The source ofthe difficulty can be traced back to the efforts of the early Fathers to reconcile the essentially pagan concept of an immaterial and immortal soul with apostolic teachings about the after-life in which all the emphasis is placed upon the resurrection of the body. The tensions between these two traditions inevitably became strained during the sixteenth century when Protestant reformers insisted on a closer adherence to Scripture. Furthermore, even when leaving the problems of Scriptural hermeneutics aside, the dualistic approach to the question, in which soul (or spirit) and body are held to be categorically different in essence, had to overcome a number of intractable philosophical problems. So, it was not simply coincidence that when the new mechanical philosophy began to be formulated in a systematic way in the seventeenth century, it was couched in vigorously dualistic terms. In fact, three of the earliest fully elaborated systems of mechanical philosophy, those of Descartes, Digby, and Charleton, were explicitly intended to provide a philosophical prop for dualist theology.' Moreover, it was because of its usefulness in promoting dualism that Cartesianism was first popularized in England not by a natural philosopher but by the Cambridge Platonist and theologian, Henry More.2 *John Henry, MPhil, PhD, Wellcome Institute for the History ofMedicine, 183 Euston Road, London NWI 2BP.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Title Joseph Glanvill and Some Restoration Climates of Opinions
    Title Joseph Glanvill and Some Restoration Climates of Opinions Author(s) Rees, Simon Citation 英文学評論 (1987), 54: 26-44 Issue Date 1987-10 URL https://doi.org/10.14989/RevEL_54_26 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University 26 Joseph Glanvill and Some Restoration Climates of Opinions Simon Rees Discussing Joseph Glanvill in The Seventeenth Century Background, Basil Willey used the phrase 'the "Climate of Opinion" ', which he had adapted from a passage in Glanvill's first book, The Vanity ofDogmatizing, to describe how ideas of Reason and Nature could become confused with those of commonsense.1' Glanvill's actual phrase referred to 'the larger Souls, that have travail'd the divers Climates of Opinions', and who are 'more cautious in their resolves, and more sparing to determine'.2' Glanvill certainly included himself among these larger souls, and it is his journey through the different climates of opinions that prevailed in the years of the Restoration that is his most interesting memorial: his work is a meteorological record of the changing fashions of ideas and beliefs, habits of thought and expression, and the conduct of controversies of fact and, if not of law, of doctrine and faith. The first edition of Glanvill's most often reprinted work appeared in 1666 with the title A Philosophical Endeavour towards the Defence of the Being of Witches and Apparitions, just in time for most of the copies to be destroyed in the Great Fire, and was later incorporated into the text of an enlarged edition, Saducismus Triumphatus, published in 1681, a year after Glanvill's death.3' However, the final revision of the text did not appear in this edition, but in a collection of essays that Glanvill published in 1676, called Essays on Several Important Subjects in Philosophy and Religion, under the title 'Against Modern Sadducism in the Matter of Witches and Apparitions.
    [Show full text]
  • 83 Re-Reading De Grammatico Or Anselm's Introduction to Aristotle's
    RE-READING DE GRAMMATICO 83 MARILYN McCORD ADAMS Re-reading De grammatico or Anselm’s introduction to Aristotle’s Categories1 I. RESTORING ANSELM’S GOOD NAME In the mid-fifties, D.P. Henry began publishing a series of works2 aimed at recovering St. Anselm’s reputation as a logician from blows suffered at the hands of nineteenth century commentators. Scandalized by the apparently nonsensical opening line of De grammatico — « Whether literate is substance or quality ? » (« De grammatico ... utrum sit substantia an qualitas ? ») — Cousin, Prantl, Maurice, and Hauréau found the work ridiculous. Hastening to usher it to the margin of Anselm’s corpus (the only piece — as they thought — devoted solely to logical matters), they rushed to conclude that for Anselm theology and logic have little to do with one another3 . Inspired by F.S. Schmitt’s discovery of Anselm’s logical fragments4 , Henry found them to shed new light, not only on De Grammatico but also on Anselm’s whole literary output, revealing Anselm to be a consummate logician whose formidable technical powers lent brilliance to his writings on other topics. 1 Norman Kretzmann introduced me to D.P. Henry’s work on paronyms in the early sixties, when it first came out, and I have been worrying about it on and off ever since. More recently, I have benefitted from helpful discussions with Robert Merrihew Adams, Andrew Finch, and Calvin Normore. 2 Most notably, D. P. HENRY, The « De Grammatico » of St. Anselm : The Theory of Paronymy, Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame 1964 ; ID., The Logic of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry More’, Encyclopedia of the Bible and Its Reception, Ed
    ‘Henry More’, Encyclopedia of the Bible and its Reception, ed. Hans-Josef Klauck et al. (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2020), in press. More, Henry (1614-1687), an English philosopher, theologian and poet. The most important member of the Cambridge Platonists, a group of seventeenth century thinkers associated with the University of Cambridge. Accepting of the developments of Galilean science, Cartesianism and atomism, they sought an alternative to the faltering philosophical foundation of Aristotelianism by looking to the Platonic tradition, viewed through the framework of Renaissance perennial philosophy. More’s Christian apologetics argued for the existence of God, the immortality of the soul, and the veracity of Christian ethics in light of the atheistic, mechanistic, and fatalistic conclusions drawn from the thought of Spinoza and Hobbes. The interpretation of the Bible figures prominently in More’s defence of Christianity. He maintained Christianity’s rationality, not because it could be axiomatically or evidentially demonstrated, but because it was in accord with both human reason and Biblical revelation. For More, both Protestant enthusiasm (More 1656), and rationalistic atheism (More 1663a), threatened this rationality in mutually reinforcing error: ‘For the Atheist's pretence to Wit and natural Reason… makes the Enthusiast secure that Reason is no guide to God: And the Enthusiast's boldly dictating the careless ravings of his own tumultuous Phansy for undeniable Principles of Divine knowledge, confirms the Atheist that the whole business of Religion … is nothing but a troublesome fit of over-curious Melancholy’ (More 1656/1662: 1-2). The Bible combated both narrow reason and irrationality by communicating expanded divine reason, articulated rationally through symbolic and allegorical form.
    [Show full text]
  • A Kind Tho' Vaine Attempt, in Speaking out the Ineffable Doctor Harry More, Late of Christ's Colledge in Cambridge
    A BIBLIOGRAPHY OF HENRY MORE compiled by Robert Crocker 1: Manuscripts by, or relating to, Henry More Bibliotheca philosophica Hermetica, Amsterdam A kind tho' vaine attempt, in speaking out the Ineffable Doctor Harry More, Late of Christ's Colledge in Cambridge. That Famous Christian Phylosopher ... To the Ono.ble Sr. Robt. Southwell. at Kings weston neare Bristoll. Farley Castle, Jan. ye 14th. 1687[/8?]. This little biography of More, probably written to commemorate his death, was adapted from a manuscript by Joseph Glanvill, entitled Bensalem, which is now held in the University of Chicago Library. See below. Bodleian Library, Oxford MS Tanner Letters, 42, f. 38: Letter from More to Simon Patrick. MS Tanner Letters, 38, f.115: Letter from More to Archbishop Sancroft. British Library, London Additional MS 23,216: Letters from Henry More to Lady Anne Conway. Most of these were reproduced in Nicolson, Conway Letters. Additional MS 4279 f. 156: A letter from More to John Pell (1665). Additional MS 4276 f. 41: A letter from More to John Sharp (1680). MS Sloane. 235 f. 14-45: Henry More, "Annotationes in C. Bartholini Meta­ phys." Cambridge University Library MS. Gg.6.11.(F.) f.I-33: Correspondence between H. Hirn and Henry More. MS. Dd.12.32.(G.) f.36-55: Anonymous notes on "Dr. More's Philosophical Collection." Cambridge, Christ's College Library MS. 21: Letters to Henry More from Edmund Elys, Anne Conway, Henry Hallywell, and others. MS. 20: Continuation of Richard Ward's Life (1710) of More. Chicago University Library Bensalem, being A Description of A Catholick & Free Spirit both in Reli­ gion & Learning.
    [Show full text]
  • Anne Conway Article Final Version
    The Lost Library! of Anne Conway !Abstract: The philosopher Anne Conway (1631-1679) owned a large library, and her reading and book ownership shaped her intellectual life in distinctive ways. Until now, however, almost nothing has been known about the details of her reading or her book collection. Current scholarship assumes that her library, like that of her husband, the third Viscount Conway (c. 1623–1683), was lost or dispersed after her death. This article presents previously unrecognised evidence of Conway’s book ownership, and identifies, for the first time, the only books currently known to survive from her personal library. It traces their path to their current location in the Old Library of Jesus College, Cambridge, through the library of the soldier, book collector, and Cambridge Fellow Francis Sterling (c. 1652-1692). The article demonstrates that the newly identified books reveal previously unknown patterns of intellectual exchange amongst Conway’s family, and argues that they have significant !implications for our understanding of her early intellectual development. Keywords: Anne Conway (1631-1679), early modern philosophy, female philosophers, libraries, book ownership ! ! I. The philosopher Anne Conway (1631-1679) inhabited a painful, bookish world. The universities and institutions of learning that welcomed her male contemporaries were closed to her and, for much of her life, constant pain and her deteriorating health prevented her from travelling far from her homes in London and Warwickshire. For significant periods of time, Conway’s intellectual life was conducted through correspondence, and through reading. Her experience of philosophy, and her one philosophical work—the posthumous Principia philosophiae antiquissimae et recentissimae of 1690, translated in 1692 as The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy—were thus shaped in a distinctive way by her access to books.
    [Show full text]
  • Henry More and the Development of Absolute Time
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 54 (2015) 11e19 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Studies in History and Philosophy of Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Henry More and the development of absolute time Emily Thomas University of Groningen, Faculty of Theology & Religious Studies, Oude Boteringestraat 38, 9712 GK Groningen, Netherlands article info abstract Article history: This paper explores the nature, development and influence of the first English account of absolute time, Received 10 February 2015 put forward in the mid-seventeenth century by the ‘Cambridge Platonist’ Henry More. Against claims in Received in revised form the literature that More does not have an account of time, this paper sets out More’s evolving account 19 May 2015 and shows that it reveals the lasting influence of Plotinus. Further, this paper argues that More developed Available online xxx his views on time in response to his adoption of Descartes’ vortex cosmology and cosmogony, providing new evidence of More’s wider project to absorb Cartesian natural philosophy into his Platonic meta- Keywords: physics. Finally, this paper argues that More should be added to the list of sources that later English Henry More; e e Absolute time; thinkers including Newton and Samuel Clarke drew on in constructing their absolute accounts of Absolute space; time. Cartesianism; Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Newton When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 1. Introduction more generally. With a view to opening a path for further schol- arship, Section 4 sketches the ways that More’s account of time may In the mid seventeenth century, the ‘Cambridge Platonist’ Henry have influenced later English thinkers, including the great abso- More (1614e1687) developed the first English account of absolute lutist, Newton himself.
    [Show full text]
  • Imagination Between Physick and Philosophy Koen Vermeir
    Imagination between Physick and Philosophy Koen Vermeir To cite this version: Koen Vermeir. Imagination between Physick and Philosophy: On the Central Role of the Imagination in the Work of Henry More (1614-1687). Intellectual History Review, Taylor & Francis (Routledge), 2008, 18, pp.119-137. 10.1080/17496970701819418. halshs-00641633 HAL Id: halshs-00641633 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00641633 Submitted on 16 Nov 2011 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Vermeir, Koen. 2008. “Imagination between Physick and Philosophy. On the Central Role of the Imagination in the Work of Henry More (1614-1687).” Intellectual History Review 18: 119-137. IMAGINATION BETWEEN PHYSICK AND PHILOSOPHY On the central role of the imagination in the work of Henry More1 Koen Vermeir ‘Thus far, Madam, I have presum’d to be a physician’ Henry More to Anne Conway, April 4 1653 Abstract I argue that the imagination plays a central role in the thought of the Cambridge Platonist Henry More. First, physiological descriptions of melancholy and imagination were at the heart of his attack against enthusiasm and atheism. Second, in order to defend his metaphysical dualism, he had to respond to traditional accounts of the imagination as a mediating faculty between body and soul.
    [Show full text]